“Equal Right to the Poor” Richard M

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

“Equal Right to the Poor” Richard M “Equal Right to the Poor” Richard M. Re† By law, federal judges must swear or affirm that they will “do equal right to the poor and to the rich.” This frequently overlooked oath, which I call the “equal right principle,” has historical roots dating back to the Bible and entered US law in a statute passed by the First Congress. Today, the equal right principle is often understood to require only that judges faithfully apply other laws. But that reading, like the idea that the rich and poor are equally barred from sleeping under bridges, is questionable in light of the equal right principle’s text, context, and history. This Article argues that the equal right principle supplies at least a plausible basis for federal judges to consider substantive economic equality when implement- ing underdetermined sources of law. There are many implications. For example, the equal right principle suggests that federal courts may legitimately limit the poor’s disadvantages in the adjudicative and legislative processes by expanding counsel rights and interpreting statutes with an eye toward economically vulnera- ble groups. The equal right principle should also inform what qualifies as a com- pelling or legitimate governmental interest within campaign finance jurispru- dence, as well as whether to implement “underenforced” equal protection principles. More broadly, the equal right principle should play a more central role in constitutional culture. The United States is unusual in that its fundamental law is relatively silent on issues of economic equality. The equal right principle can fill that void by providing a platform for legal and public deliberation over issues of wealth inequality. Through judicial confirmation hearings and other forms of public contestation, the equal right principle can help to specify federal judges’ legal and moral commitments toward the poor. † Assistant Professor of Law, UCLA School of Law. Many thanks to Michelle Wilde Anderson, Will Baude, Josh Blackman, Sam Bray, Grace Bridwell, Craig Chosiad, Ryan Doerfler, Laura Donohue, Elliot Dorff, Greg Dubinsky, Kristen Eichensehr, Jonah Gelbach, Robert Goldstein, Mark Greenberg, Tara Leigh Grove, John McGinnis, Aaron Nielson, Jide Nzelibe, Jim Pfander, Alex Potapov, Sabeel Rahman, Larry Sager, Seana Shiffrin, Ganesh Sitaraman, Mila Sohoni, Sabine Tsuruda, Mark Tushnet, Margo Uhrman, David Waddilove, Eugene Volokh, Adam Winkler, Rebecca Zietlow, The University of Chicago Law Review, and participants in the Northwestern Constitutional Law Colloquium, the University of Pennsylvania Legislation Workshop, the Junior Scholars Federal Courts Workshop, and the UCLA School of Law Faculty Colloquium. 1149 1150 The University of Chicago Law Review [84:1149 INTRODUCTION .................................................................................................. 1150 I. HISTORICIZING EQUAL RIGHT ..................................................................... 1157 A. The Bible ........................................................................................... 1157 B. British Practice ................................................................................. 1160 C. American Law ................................................................................... 1163 II. UNDERSTANDING EQUAL RIGHT ................................................................. 1167 A. Statutory Interpretation ................................................................... 1167 B. Promissory Constitutionalism .......................................................... 1177 III. IMPLEMENTING EQUAL RIGHT .................................................................... 1189 A. Adjudicative Equality ....................................................................... 1189 B. Canon of Interpretation .................................................................... 1197 C. Governmental Interests .................................................................... 1203 D. Protected “Class” ............................................................................... 1209 CONCLUSION ..................................................................................................... 1216 Each justice or judge of the United States shall take the following oath or affirmation before performing the duties of his office: “I, ______, do solemnly swear (or affirm) that I will administer justice without respect to persons, and do equal right to the poor and to the rich, and that I will faithfully and impartially discharge and perform all the duties incumbent upon me as ___ under the Constitution and laws of the United States. So help me God.” 1 INTRODUCTION During the confirmation hearings for then-Judge John Roberts, Senator Richard Durbin asked about economic equality. “Would you at least concede,” Durbin asked, “that you would take into consideration that in our system of justice the race goes to the swift, and the swift are those with the resources, the money, the lawyers, the power in the system?”2 “Absolutely,” Roberts replied. After all, “the judicial oath talks about doing justice without regard to persons, to rich and to poor.”3 So it’s “critically important,” Roberts continued, “to appreciate that there are going to be interests who, for one reason or another, don’t have the same resources as people on the other side.”4 1 28 USC § 453. 2 See Nomination of John G. Roberts Jr to Be Chief Justice of the United States, Hearing before the Senate Committee on the Judiciary, 109th Cong, 1st Sess 448 (2005) (“Roberts Hearings”). Roberts also referred to the phrase “Equal Justice Under Law.” See notes 233–34 and accompanying text. 3 Roberts Hearings, 109th Cong, 1st Sess at 448–49 (cited in note 2). 4 Id at 449. 2017] “Equal Right to the Poor” 1151 Roberts was referring to the statutory oath of office taken by every federal judge.5 In the Judiciary Act of 1789,6 the First Congress required that all federal judges “solemnly swear or af- firm” that they would, among other things, “do equal right to the poor and to the rich.”7 That statutory oath requirement, which I call “the equal right principle,” remains in place today.8 Remarkably, the language in question long predates the United States. For centuries, British judges were instructed to “do equal right to the Poor, and to the Rich.”9 And similar injunctions ap- pear among the ancient judicial duties set out in the biblical texts of Exodus, Leviticus, and Deuteronomy.10 What does this evocative oath mean? On its face, the com- mand to “do equal right to the poor and to the rich” has several components. Its reference to “equal right” connotes some form of impartial justice, or fair treatment with respect to legal decision- making.11 And in applying not only “to the poor” but also “to the rich,” the oath conveys that even vast disparities in wealth must be met with “equal” provision of “right.”12 In short, the equal right principle obligates federal judges to honor an unspecified form of economic equality. That basic idea can be fleshed out via either of two broad approaches.13 The first broad approach emphasizes formal equality. A weak version of formal equality would assert a straightforward directive: federal judges must apply other laws without regard to disparities in wealth. In other words, federal judges should 5 See id at 448–49. 6 1 Stat 73. 7 Judiciary Act of 1789 § 8, 1 Stat at 76, 28 USC § 453. 8 Federal judges also take the general federal oath to “support and defend the Constitution.” 5 USC § 3331. 9 The Book of Oaths and the Several Forms Thereof, Both Ancient and Modern 176 (1689). See also Part I.B. 10 See Part I.A. See also Alvin K. Hellerstein, The Influence of a Jewish Education and Jewish Values on a Jewish Judge, 29 Touro L Rev 517, 525 (2013) (noting that the federal judicial oath “resonates Biblically”). 11 See notes 91–92 and accompanying text. 12 To the extent that the equal right principle requires a working definition of “the poor” and “the rich,” other sources of federal law supply useful benchmarks. See, for ex- ample, San Antonio Independent School District v Rodriguez, 411 US 1, 19–20 (1973) (identifying the poor as those who “because of their impecunity [ ] were completely unable to pay for some desired benefit, and as a consequence, they sustained an absolute depri- vation of a meaningful opportunity to enjoy that benefit”); US Department of Health and Human Services, U.S. Federal Poverty Guidelines Used to Determine Financial Eligibil- ity for Certain Federal Programs (Jan 26, 2017), archived at http://perma.cc/LR6J-YL46. 13 See Aviam Soifer, Law and the Company We Keep 134, 167 (Harvard 1995). 1152 The University of Chicago Law Review [84:1149 simply follow separate sources of law, wherever they lead.14 Fed- eral judicial duty would thus be unchanged if Congress had omitted any mention of “the poor” and “the rich” and had instead demanded, for example, equal right “to the short and to the tall.” In fact, this reading would cast the equal right principle as a merely rhetorical flourish, because the federal judicial oath in- cludes separate commitments to impartiality and lawfulness.15 A stronger version of formal equality is also possible, as the equal right principle could be read as a statutory ban on considering wealth disparities or accommodating poverty. These arguments are not merely hypothetical. Courts, legislators, and scholars have enlisted formal equality readings to oppose judicial “empathy” for the poor.16 And those readings could call into question such entrenched accommodations
Recommended publications
  • Reckless Caution: the Perils of Judicial Minimalism
    RECKLESS CAUTION: THE PERILS OF JUDICIAL MINIMALISM Tara Smith* ABSTRACT Judicial Minimalism is the increasingly popular view that judges decide cases properly to the extent that they minimize their own imprint on the law by meticulously assessing “one case at a time,” ruling on narrow and shallow grounds, eschewing broader theories, and altering entrenched legal practices only incremen- tally. Minimalism’s ascendancy across the political spectrum, be- ing embraced by advocates of both right-wing and left-wing ide- ologies, is touted as a sign of its appropriate value-neutrality. This paper argues that such sought-after neutrality is, in fact, untenable. While others have objected to some of Minimalism’s specific tenets, critics have missed its more fundamental failing: it is an incoherent concept. On analysis, Minimalism’s several planks and rationales prove mutually contradictory and, corre- spondingly, offer conflicting guidance to judges. Thus the reason that Minimalism can appeal to people of such disparate substan- tive views is that in practice, it is merely a placeholder invoked to * Many people have offered helpful discussion of the ideas developed in this paper or feedback on earlier drafts. I am grateful to audiences at Oxford’s Uehiro Center and the University of Virginia, and in particular to Tom Bowden, Onkar Ghate, Wesley Hottot, Loren Lomasky, Al Martinich, Matt Miller, Adam Mossoff, Matt O’Brien, Greg Salmieri, Julian Savulescu, John Simmons, and Kevin Stuart. 347 348 New York University Journal of Law & Liberty [Vol. 5:347 sanction a grab-bag of desiderata rather than a distinctive method of decision-making that offers genuine guidance.
    [Show full text]
  • Rethinking Judicial Minimalism: Abortion Politics, Party Polarization, and the Consequences of Returning the Constitution to Elected Government Neal Devins
    Vanderbilt Law Review Volume 69 | Issue 4 Article 3 5-2016 Rethinking Judicial Minimalism: Abortion Politics, Party Polarization, and the Consequences of Returning the Constitution to Elected Government Neal Devins Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.vanderbilt.edu/vlr Part of the Supreme Court of the United States Commons Recommended Citation Neal Devins, Rethinking Judicial Minimalism: Abortion Politics, Party Polarization, and the Consequences of Returning the Constitution to Elected Government, 69 Vanderbilt Law Review 935 (2019) Available at: https://scholarship.law.vanderbilt.edu/vlr/vol69/iss4/3 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Scholarship@Vanderbilt Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in Vanderbilt Law Review by an authorized editor of Scholarship@Vanderbilt Law. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Rethinking Judicial Minimalism: Abortion Politics, Party Polarization, and the Consequences of Returning the Constitution to Elected Government Neal Devins* IN TROD U CTION ............................................................................... 935 I. MINIMALISM THEORY AND ABORTION ................................. 939 II. WHAT ABORTION POLITICS TELLS US ABOUT JUDICIAL M INIMALISM ........................................................ 946 A . R oe v. W ade ............................................................. 947 B . From Roe to Casey ................................................... 953 C. Casey and Beyond ..................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Maximinimalism
    GREENE.38.2.8 (Do Not Delete) 12/14/2016 12:55 PM MAXIMINIMALISM Jamal Greene† TABLE OF CONTENTS INTRODUCTION .................................................................................................................623 I. ONE CONCEPTION OF MINIMALISM.........................................................................626 II. CHIEF JUSTICE ROBERTS’S MAXIMINIMALISM .........................................................629 A. What Chief Justice Roberts Has Preached ..................................................629 B. What Chief Justice Roberts Has Practiced .................................................631 1. Citizens United v. FEC ......................................................................632 2. Shelby County v. Holder ...................................................................635 3. NFIB v. Sebelius .................................................................................638 C. Other Examples .............................................................................................644 III. ASSESSMENT ...............................................................................................................646 CONCLUSION......................................................................................................................649 INTRODUCTION When John Roberts became Chief Justice of the United States more than a decade ago, commenters frequently described him as a minimalist.1 Although Chief Justice Roberts himself resisted this label,2 he fairly inspired it by advocating
    [Show full text]
  • The Philosophy and Jurisprudence of Chief Justice Roberts
    Utah Law Review Volume 2014 | Number 1 Article 4 2014 The hiP losophy and Jurisprudence of Chief Justice Roberts Kiel Brennan-Marquez Follow this and additional works at: http://dc.law.utah.edu/ulr Part of the Judges Commons, Jurisprudence Commons, and the Supreme Court of the United States Commons Recommended Citation Brennan-Marquez, Kiel (2014) "The hiP losophy and Jurisprudence of Chief Justice Roberts," Utah Law Review: Vol. 2014 : No. 1 , Article 4. Available at: http://dc.law.utah.edu/ulr/vol2014/iss1/4 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Utah Law Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Utah Law Review by an authorized editor of Utah Law Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE PHILOSOPHY AND JURISPRUDENCE OF CHIEF JUSTICE ROBERTS Kiel Brennan-Marquez* Abstract A thicket of commentary has blossomed around the figure of Chief Justice Roberts. The bulk of it, however, has either focused exclusively on his role in the 2011 term or has lumped him in uncritically with the Court’s conservative wing. In response, this Article takes a wider view of his tenure, arguing that Chief Justice Roberts is best understood as an idealist, a true believer in the rule of law, with a special sensitivity toward issues of constitutional structure. In the first Part of the Article, I explore Chief Justice Roberts’s penchant for infusing his opinions with “teaching moments”—a tendency certainly on display in National Federation of Independent Business v. Sebelius1 (NFIB), but discernable in many other opinions as well.
    [Show full text]
  • The Administrative State's Passive Virtues
    University of Colorado Law School Colorado Law Scholarly Commons Articles Colorado Law Faculty Scholarship 2014 The Administrative State's Passive Virtues Sharon B. Jacobs University of Colorado Law School Follow this and additional works at: https://scholar.law.colorado.edu/articles Part of the Administrative Law Commons, and the Courts Commons Citation Information Sharon B. Jacobs, The Administrative State's Passive Virtues, 66 ADMIN. L. REV. 565 (2014), available at https://scholar.law.colorado.edu/articles/431. Copyright Statement Copyright protected. Use of materials from this collection beyond the exceptions provided for in the Fair Use and Educational Use clauses of the U.S. Copyright Law may violate federal law. Permission to publish or reproduce is required. This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Colorado Law Faculty Scholarship at Colorado Law Scholarly Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Articles by an authorized administrator of Colorado Law Scholarly Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. +(,121/,1( Citation: 66 Admin. L. Rev. 565 2014 Provided by: William A. Wise Law Library Content downloaded/printed from HeinOnline Tue May 2 11:38:55 2017 -- Your use of this HeinOnline PDF indicates your acceptance of HeinOnline's Terms and Conditions of the license agreement available at http://heinonline.org/HOL/License -- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text. -- To obtain permission to use this article beyond the scope of your HeinOnline license, please use: Copyright Information THE ADMINISTRATIVE STATE'S PASSIVE VIRTUES SHARON B.JACOBS* Fift years ago, Alexander Bickelfamousy suggested that courts use tools like standing, ripeness, and the political question doctrine to avoid reaching the merits of difficult cases.
    [Show full text]
  • Justice Samuel A. Alito's Lonely War Against Abhorrent, Low-Value Clay Calvert
    Hofstra Law Review Volume 40 Article 11 Issue 1 FORTIETH ANNIVERSARY VOLUME 2011 Justice Samuel A. Alito's Lonely War Against Abhorrent, Low-Value Clay Calvert Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarlycommons.law.hofstra.edu/hlr Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Calvert, Clay (2011) "Justice Samuel A. Alito's Lonely War Against Abhorrent, Low-Value," Hofstra Law Review: Vol. 40: Iss. 1, Article 11. Available at: http://scholarlycommons.law.hofstra.edu/hlr/vol40/iss1/11 This document is brought to you for free and open access by Scholarly Commons at Hofstra Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in Hofstra Law Review by an authorized administrator of Scholarly Commons at Hofstra Law. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Calvert: Justice Samuel A. Alito's Lonely War Against Abhorrent, Low-Value JUSTICE SAMUEL A. ALITO'S LONELY WAR AGAINST ABHORRENT, LOW-VALUE EXPRESSION: A MALLEABLE FIRST AMENDMENT PHILOSOPHY PRIVILEGING SUBJECTIVE NOTIONS OF MORALITY AND MERIT Clay Calvert* I. INTRODUCTION A trio of U.S. Supreme Court rulings during its most recent two terms demonstrates that Justice Samuel Anthony Alito, Jr. is no friend to expression that offends his personal sense of both morality and substantive merit. In fact, he might be the justice most prone to censor offensive speech on today's High Court. In April 2010, the Supreme Court in United States v. Stevens' struck down on First Amendment2 overbreadth 3 grounds a federal statute4 targeting crush videos.5 Although the content of such videos is * Professor & Brechner Eminent Scholar in Mass Communication and Director of the Marion B.
    [Show full text]
  • The Scope of Precedent
    Michigan Law Review Volume 113 Issue 2 2014 The Scope of Precedent Randy J. Kozel Notre Dame Law School Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.law.umich.edu/mlr Part of the Constitutional Law Commons, Courts Commons, Jurisprudence Commons, Law and Philosophy Commons, and the Supreme Court of the United States Commons Recommended Citation Randy J. Kozel, The Scope of Precedent, 113 MICH. L. REV. 179 (2014). Available at: https://repository.law.umich.edu/mlr/vol113/iss2/1 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Michigan Law Review at University of Michigan Law School Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Michigan Law Review by an authorized editor of University of Michigan Law School Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE SCOPE OF PRECEDENT Randy J. Kozel* The scope of Supreme Court precedent is capacious. Justices of the Court com- monly defer to sweeping rationales and elaborate doctrinal frameworks articu- lated by their predecessors. This practice infuses judicial precedent with the prescriptive power of enacted constitutional and statutory text. The lower fed- eral courts follow suit, regularly abiding by the Supreme Court’s broad pro- nouncements. These phenomena cannot be explained by—and, indeed, oftentimes subvert—the classic distinction between binding holdings and dis- pensable dicta. This Article connects the scope of precedent with recurring and foundational debates about the proper ends of judicial interpretation. A precedent’s for- ward-looking effect should not depend on the superficial categories of holding and dictum. Instead, it should reflect deeper normative commitments that de- fine the nature of adjudication within American legal culture.
    [Show full text]
  • The Doctrine of Constitutional Avoidance: a Legal Overview
    The Doctrine of Constitutional Avoidance: A Legal Overview Andrew Nolan Legislative Attorney September 2, 2014 Congressional Research Service 7-5700 www.crs.gov R43706 The Doctrine of Constitutional Avoidance: A Legal Overview Summary Article III of the Constitution established the judicial branch of the United States, staffing the branch with life-tenured and salary-protected judges. Amongst the powers of the federal judiciary is the power of “judicial review”—that is, the power to invalidate the acts of other branches of government and the states that contravene the Constitution. The Framers of the Constitution established this “countermajoritarian” role for the judiciary to help protect the written Constitution and its principles against incursions from the political branches. The power of judicial review is both a potent and controversial power, as American history has been replete with examples of outcry at when unelected federal judges invalidate the acts of a democratically elected branch of government. The potential for backlash to judicial review by the political branches has resulted in what late Professor Alexander Bickel termed a “countermajoritarian difficulty,” as the judiciary is needed to protect the basic principles of the Constitution, but is also necessarily dependent on the political branches to enforce the judiciary’s mandates. In other words, judicial review, while necessary to protect the mandates of the Constitution, is inherently antidemocratic, risking an erosion of the judiciary’s role in the American constitutional form of government. The prominent solution to the potential perils of the countermajoritarian difficulty, as espoused by Professor Bickel, is that the judiciary—and in particular the High Court—should exercise the “passive virtues,” a set of tools, such as the justiciability doctrines, with which a court can return an unsettled and controversial constitutional problem to the political realm for resolution.
    [Show full text]
  • The Rise and Fall of Judicial Self-Restraint
    University of Chicago Law School Chicago Unbound Journal Articles Faculty Scholarship 2012 The Rise and Fall of Judicial Self-Restraint Richard A. Posner Follow this and additional works at: https://chicagounbound.uchicago.edu/journal_articles Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Richard A. Posner, "The Rise and Fall of Judicial Self-Restraint," 100 California Law Review 519 (2012). This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Scholarship at Chicago Unbound. It has been accepted for inclusion in Journal Articles by an authorized administrator of Chicago Unbound. For more information, please contact [email protected]. California Law Review VOL. 100 JUNE 2012 NO. 3 Copyright D 2012 by California Law Review, Inc., a California Nonprofit Corporation The Rise and Fall of Judicial Self-Restraint Richard A. Posner* Judicial self-restraint, once a rallying cry for judges and law professors, has fallen on evil days. It is rarely invoked or advocated. This Essay traces the rise and fall of its best-known variant- restraint in invalidating legislative action as unconstitutional-as advocated by the "School of Thayer, " consisting of James Bradley Thayer and the influentialjudges and law professors who claimed to be his followers. The Essay argues, among other things, that both the strength and the weakness of the School was an acknowledged absence of a theory of how to decide a constitutionalcase. The rise of constitutional theory created an unbearable tension between Thayer's claim that judges should uphold a statute unless its invalidity was clear beyond doubt (as it would very rarely be), and constitutional theories that claimed to dispel doubt and yield certifiably right answers in all cases.
    [Show full text]
  • Roe Rage: Democratic Constitutionalism and Backlash
    Roe Rage: Democratic Constitutionalism and Backlash Robert Post* Reva Siegel* Progressive confidence in constitutional adjudication peaked during the Warren Court and its immediate aftermath. Courts were celebrated as "fora of principle,"' privileged sites for the diffusion of human reason. But progressive attitudes toward constitutional adjudication have recently begun to splinter and diverge. 2 Some progressives, following the call of "popular constitutionalism," have argued that the Constitution should be taken away from courts and restored to the people.3 Others have empha- sized the urgent need for judicial caution and minimalism.4 One of the many reasons for this shift is that progressives have be- come fearful that an assertive judiciary can spark "a political and cultural backlash that may ... hurt, more than" help, progressive values.5 A gen- eration ago, progressives responded to violent backlash against Brown v. Board of Education6 by attempting to develop principles of constitutional * David Boies Professor of Law, Yale University. Nicholas deB. Katzenbach Professor of Law, Yale University. Many thanks to Bruce Ackerman, Jack Balkin, David Barron, Eric Citron, Bill Eskridge, Owen Fiss, Barry Friedman, Sarah Gordon, Mark Graber, Michael Graetz, David Hollinger, Dawn Johnsen, Amy Kapczyn- ski, Michael Klarman, Scott Lemieux, Sandy Levinson, Joanne Meyerowitz, Sasha Post, Judith Resnik, Neil Siegel, and Christine Stansell for comments on the manuscript. We had the pleasure of working with an extraordinary group of Harvard and Yale research assis- tants on this Essay, including Nick Barnaby, Robert Cacace, Kathryn Eidmann, Rebecca Engel, Sarah Hammond, Kara Loewentheil, Sandra Pullman, Sandeep Ramesh, Sandra Vasher, and Justin Weinstein-Tull. ' Ronald Dworkin, The Forum of Principle, 56 N.Y.U.
    [Show full text]
  • Judges' Varied Views on Textualism
    University of Colorado Law School Colorado Law Scholarly Commons Articles Colorado Law Faculty Scholarship 2017 Judges’ Varied Views on Textualism: The Roberts-Alito Schism and the Similar District Judge Divergence that Undercuts the Widely Assumed Textualism-Ideology Correlation Scott A. Moss University of Colorado Law School Follow this and additional works at: https://scholar.law.colorado.edu/articles Part of the Judges Commons, Jurisprudence Commons, Legislation Commons, and the Supreme Court of the United States Commons Citation Information Scott A. Moss, Judges’ Varied Views on Textualism: The Roberts-Alito Schism and the Similar District Judge Divergence that Undercuts the Widely Assumed Textualism-Ideology Correlation, 88 U. COLO. L. REV. 1 (2017), available at https://scholar.law.colorado.edu/articles/17. Copyright Statement Copyright protected. Use of materials from this collection beyond the exceptions provided for in the Fair Use and Educational Use clauses of the U.S. Copyright Law may violate federal law. Permission to publish or reproduce is required. This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Colorado Law Faculty Scholarship at Colorado Law Scholarly Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Articles by an authorized administrator of Colorado Law Scholarly Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. 8. 88.1 MOSS_FINAL (DO NOT DELETE) 11/16/2016 2:54 PM UNIVERSITY OF COLORADO LAW REVIEW Volume 88, Issue 1 2017 JUDGES’ VARIED VIEWS ON TEXTUALISM: THE ROBERTS-ALITO SCHISM AND THE SIMILAR DISTRICT JUDGE DIVERGENCE THAT UNDERCUTS THE WIDELY ASSUMED TEXTUALISM-IDEOLOGY CORRELATION SCOTT A. MOSS* INTRODUCTION .............................................................................2 I.
    [Show full text]
  • Grassroots Originalism: Rethinking the Politics of Judicial Philosophy
    Florida State University College of Law Scholarship Repository Scholarly Publications 2012 Grassroots Originalism: Rethinking the Politics of Judicial Philosophy Mary Ziegler Florida State University College of Law Follow this and additional works at: https://ir.law.fsu.edu/articles Part of the Law and Philosophy Commons, Law and Politics Commons, and the Legal History Commons Recommended Citation Mary Ziegler, Grassroots Originalism: Rethinking the Politics of Judicial Philosophy, 51 U. LOUISVILLE L. REV. 201 (2012), Available at: https://ir.law.fsu.edu/articles/331 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Scholarly Publications by an authorized administrator of Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. GRASSROOTS ORIGINALISM: JUDICIAL ACTIVISM ARGUMENTS, THE ABORTION DEBATE, AND THE POLITICS OF JUDICIAL PHILOSOPHY * Mary Ziegler I. INTRODUCTION How has originalism become so politically successful?1 In answering this question, leading scholarship has focused on the ways in which political leaders, judges, and lawyers have cultivated popular support for originalism. In one account, legal academics, politicians, and judges have explained the legal merits of originalism as a method of interpretation: its political neutrality and its democratic legitimacy.2 In a second version, political leaders—in particular, the Reagan Administration and the judges it nominated—made apparent that originalism would often produce outcomes that social conservatives found satisfactory.3 With some exceptions, leading studies primarily address the contributions made by elites to rhetoric about and justifications for originalism, including those rationales based on 4 judicial activism and judicial legitimacy.
    [Show full text]