Philosophy, Linguistic Analysis, and Linguistics

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Philosophy, Linguistic Analysis, and Linguistics KAREL MOM (Amsterdam) Philosophy, linguistic analysis, and linguistics I Introduction In his essay about Chomsky’s generative grammar Flach assesses the philo- sophically relevant doctrines of Chomsky’s linguistic theory. Generally, Flach considers those doctrines as philosophically relevant that are amena- ble or at least directly connective to a philosophic discipline. 1 On the basis of his assessment, Flach declares the development of this theory a second linguistic turn in philosophy (LT2), stretching from the late 1950s through the 1960s. 2 This verdict Chomsky owes to his discussion of the reciprocal epistemological relation between linguistics and philosophy. 3 Flach observes that LT1, in its varieties of ideal language philosophy (ILP), ordinary language philosophy (OLP) and the ontologic-hermeneutical doctrine of communication has scarcely produced an account of the prob- lem of language, i.e. of the structure of language along with its systematic classification. 4 By contrast, LT2, with the generative grammar as its main as- set, reveals this problemtheoretical deficit of LT1 in its quest for a philoso- phical theory of language which could serve as the philosophical foundation 1 Flach, W. 1974: Die generative linguistische Theorie und die Prinzipienlehre des Denkens . In: Simon, J. (ed.), Aspekte und Probleme der Sprachphilosophie. Freiburg, 69-110, 92. Flach considers publications of Chomsky’s from Chomsky, N. 1957: Syntactic Structures . The Hague , up till 1970 (Ibid., 78 fn. 21.) For a recent development of Chomsky’s theory see below. 2 Die generative … , 73. 3 Ibid., 24 fn. 12. Notice that Flach uses the word ‘Wechselbeziehung’, which cap- tures, though not states explicitly, the asymmetry of this relation, linguistics being principiated by the principles that epistemology purports to establish. 4 Ibid., 70f., Bergmann, G. 1964: Logic and reality . Madison. Bergmann does not dis- tinguish Flach’s third variety, which, incidentally, equally is met with Flach’s criticism, specifically for its abstract-theoretically oriented neotranscendentalism ( Die generative …, 99 fn. 44.). For a similar scepticism as regards the transcendental po- tential of linguistic pragmatism see, Aschenberg, R. 1982, Sprachanalyse und Transzen- dentalphilosophie , Stuttgart, 1982, 29. 244 Karel Mom for linguistics. 5 However, for all its merits, Chomsky’s theory, in particular its mentalistic conception of linguistic competence, is vulnerable to Flach’s criticism. 6 In this paper I will argue that Flach’s observations show some interesting parallels with Strawson’s position concerning LT1,2. This might seem sur- prising, given the apparent incommensurability of the approaches of both philosophers as is suggested by the differences in the vocabularies they em- ploy, despite their obvious Kantianism. However, if Flach mentions Straw- son, next to Quine 7, as an example of methodological criticism of generative linguistics Strawson’s substantive philosophical position with respect to it is equally noteworthy. 8 For it is here that interesting parallels come to the fore. After this introductory section this paper is organised as follows. In sec- tion II I will give an account of the relation between linguistics and philosophy as Flach sees it, albeit imperfectly, exemplified in Chomsky’s lin- guistic theory. This account links up with Flach’s model of the historicity [Geschichtlichkeit] of philosophy and the problematicity [Problemcharakter] of its topic [Gegenstand]. 9 In section III I will trace the historical antece- dents of LT1,2, viewed from a perpective of the philosophy of linguistic sciences and confront the model, outlined in section II, with this perspec- tive. Section IV proposes a comparative analysis of Strawson’s position concerning linguistic analysis as advocated in LT1,2 with reference to Flach’s exposition of the concept of linguistic competence. In a concluding section I will state some generalisations derived form the comparative analy- sis ( section V ). 5 Die generative , 72f. 6 Ibid., 102. 7 Quine signals e.g. an equivocity in Chomsky’s interpretation of ‘rule of grammar’, having the connotations both of guiding and of fitting linguistic behaviour, the for- mer as a matter of cause and effect, the latter as a matter of true description. (see Quine, W. V. 1970: Methodological Reflections on Current Linguistic Theory . Synthese, 21, 386–98, 386. It is questionable whether Chomsky’s notion of grammar as an in- ternalised system of rules (cf. Die generative … , 83) eludes Quine’s dichotomy. 8 Die generative ... 92 fn. 38. 9 Flach, W. 1963: Die Geschichtlichkeit der Philosophie und der Problemcharakter des phi- losophischen Gegenstandes . Kant-Studien 54, 17–28. Philosophy, linguistic analysis, and linguistics 245 II Linguistics and philosophy At the outset of his essay Flach states, referring to Plato and Aristotle, that the theme of language always also has been considered a philosophical theme. 10 The mere reference to Plato and Aristotle, though, underdeter- mines the way in which Flach conceives the epistemological relation bet- ween language and philosophy, let alone how this relation is exemplified in the connection of Chomsky’s linguistic theory with the philosophical doc- trine of the principles of thought. 11 The expression 'always also' [immer auch] in the abovecited statement implies nonetheless a distributive divison of language as a theme between philosophy and linguistics. This division implies a distinction between philosophical doctrine and linguistic theory, each with its own, to use Katz’s phrase, proto-theory of language. 12 This distinction can be projected on the model Flach construes to describe the topic-systematic connections between the conception of phi- losophy, of its history [Geschichte] and the theory [Historie] about this history. According to Flach, whereas philosophy shares with science that it generates knowledge from principles of (the things in) the world, it differs from science in that it is moreover knowledge of the principles of thought themselves and their principiating function. Consequently, the topic of phi- losophy is knowledge in the entire scope of its structural particularity [Bestimmtheit]. From this it follows that philosophy, as the steady and uni- versal reflection on available knowledge is sceptical towards science as well as itself and its history. Therefore, answers to questions about the constitu- tion of knowledge always have a provisional character and the topic of philosophy is intrinsically problematic. Accordingly, for philosophy, the ref- lection on its own history, i.e. Historie as mentioned above, is the explication of the development of self-consciousness of philosophy itself. The historical course of philosophy, therefore, is a steady interplay between systematicity 10 Die generative ..., 69. 11 I render Flach’s ‘Denken’ here as ‘thought’. Notice that Dummett, in his under- standing of the object of philosophy declares that “the goal of philosophy is the structure of thought [...] that the study of thought is to be sharply distinguished from the study of the psychological process of thinking ; and [...] that the only proper me- thod of analysing thought consists in the analysis of language [...]” (Dummett, M.A.E. 1978: Can analytical philosophy be systematic and ought it to be? in id. Truth and other Enigmas, London, 437–458, 458 (orig. emph.) 12 Katz, J.J. 1990. The Metaphysics of Meaning , Cambridge (Mass.), passim. 246 Karel Mom and the explication of this self-consciousness, in short, between system- thinking [Systemdenken] and problem-thinking [Problemdenken]. This in- terplay consists in the continuous systematization of philosophical know- ledge in the totality of its insights, i.e. the necessary and encompassing implications of all factive and possible philosophical problems generated by the universal principle of reflection. 13 These insights are, of course, also operative in Flach’s essay, provided that it has an exclusive systematic approach. 14 Here Flach’s focus is on the classification of Chomsky’s justification of his linguistic theory within the overall problematic of the justification of knowledge. 15 Flach’s discussion of the exemplification of the epistemological relation between linguistics and philosophy seizes upon Chomsky’s conception of a grammar of a language. Being the linguistic objectivation [Objektion] of that language, i.e. its object- disclosing determination, Chomsky conceives grammar as a theory about the formation of the expressions of that language, i.e. of its structure, from the aspect of observation (through the aspect of description) to the aspect of explanation. As such, Flach considers the generative linguistic theory, which claims the adequacy of the grammar it establishes on the aspects of observation, description and explanation of linguistic facts 16 as a threefold justification of its linguistic objectivation. As such, it is a philosophical theory of language [Sprachtheorie] because its language-theoretical question involves a preliminary theory that warrants the coherent, i.e. scientific, es- tablishment of the linguistic facts. 17 For Flach, the philosophical relevance of this theory is unquestionable when it is taken into account that philoso- phy is itself a doctrine of justification of knowledge. 18 III Linguistics, a perspective from the philosophy of linguistic sciences Now from this model to the historical antecedents of LT1,2. In his account of the history of the analysis of natural language,
Recommended publications
  • The Empirical Base of Linguistics: Grammaticality Judgments and Linguistic Methodology
    UCLA UCLA Previously Published Works Title The empirical base of linguistics: Grammaticality judgments and linguistic methodology Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/05b2s4wg ISBN 978-3946234043 Author Schütze, Carson T Publication Date 2016-02-01 DOI 10.17169/langsci.b89.101 Data Availability The data associated with this publication are managed by: Language Science Press, Berlin Peer reviewed eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California The empirical base of linguistics Grammaticality judgments and linguistic methodology Carson T. Schütze language Classics in Linguistics 2 science press Classics in Linguistics Chief Editors: Martin Haspelmath, Stefan Müller In this series: 1. Lehmann, Christian. Thoughts on grammaticalization 2. Schütze, Carson T. The empirical base of linguistics: Grammaticality judgments and linguistic methodology 3. Bickerton, Derek. Roots of language ISSN: 2366-374X The empirical base of linguistics Grammaticality judgments and linguistic methodology Carson T. Schütze language science press Carson T. Schütze. 2019. The empirical base of linguistics: Grammaticality judgments and linguistic methodology (Classics in Linguistics 2). Berlin: Language Science Press. This title can be downloaded at: http://langsci-press.org/catalog/book/89 © 2019, Carson T. Schütze Published under the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 Licence (CC BY 4.0): http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ ISBN: 978-3-946234-02-9 (Digital) 978-3-946234-03-6 (Hardcover) 978-3-946234-04-3 (Softcover) 978-1-523743-32-2
    [Show full text]
  • Linguistic Competence
    University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Transactions of the Nebraska Academy of Sciences and Affiliated Societies Nebraska Academy of Sciences 1983 Linguistic Competence John Tienson University of Nebraska-Lincoln Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/tnas Part of the Life Sciences Commons Tienson, John, "Linguistic Competence" (1983). Transactions of the Nebraska Academy of Sciences and Affiliated Societies. 259. https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/tnas/259 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Nebraska Academy of Sciences at DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. It has been accepted for inclusion in Transactions of the Nebraska Academy of Sciences and Affiliated Societiesy b an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. 1983. Transactions of the Nebraska Academy of Sciences, XI:99-104. LINGUISTIC COMPETENCE John Tienson Department of Philosophy University of Nebraska-Lincoln Lincoln, Nebraska 68588-0321 The notion of linguistic competence as a cognitive system that essential to the notion. This will make clear that Chomsky produces knowledge not antecedently present in the mind of the sub­ should not have said that a theory of competence is an ideali­ ject, e.g., knowledge of grammatical relations in response to certain zation, and that there is no reason to say that a speaker knows stimuli is an important contribution to philosophical understanding of linguistics, and of cognitive psychology in general. This notion has not the rules of the grammar. been as well received as it should have been, in part because of certain false things that have been said about it.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Irrelevance of Transformational Grammar to Second Language Pedagogy
    ON THE IRRELEVANCE OF TRANSFORMATIONAL GRAMMAR TO SECOND LANGUAGE PEDAGOGY John T. Lamendella The University of Michigan Many scholars view transformational grammar as an attempt to represent the structure of linguistic knowledge in the mind and seek to apply transformational descriptions of languages to the de- velopment of second language teaching materials. It will be claimed in this paper that it is a mistake to look to transformational gram- mar or any other theory of linguistic description to provide the theoretical basis for either second language pedagogy or a theory of language acquisition. One may well wish to describe the ab- stract or logical structure of a language by constructing a trans- formational grammar which generates the set of sentences identi- fied with that language. However, this attempt should not be con- fused with an attempt to understand the cognitive structures and processes involved in knowing or using a language. It is a cogni- tive theory of language within the field of psycholinguistics rather than a theory of linguistic description which should underlie lan- guage teaching materials. A great deal of effort has been expended in the attempt to demonstrate the potential contributions of the field of descriptive linguistics to the teaching of second languages and, since the theory of transformational grammar has become the dominant theory in the field of linguistics, it is not surprising that applied linguists have sought to apply transformational grammar to gain new in- sights into the teaching of second languages. It will be claimed in this paper that it is a mistake to look to transformational grammar or any other theory of linguistic description to provide the theoretical basis for either second language pedagogy or a theory of language acquisition.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Linguistics
    Philosophy of Linguistics Brian Rabern Philosophy DSB 4.04c 0131 651 5178 [email protected] Geoff Pullum Linguistics DSB 2.23 0131 650 3603 [email protected] Meetings The class meetings are from 11:00 to 13:00 each Wednesday from 19th September to 28th November in Old Library 2.19, Geography building, Old Infirmary complex (weeks 1–3 and 6–11) and in 01M.469 Teaching Room 12 (Doorway 3), Medical School building. Class meetings are mandatory. Readings Required reading is to be done before the class meets; background reading to be studied as time and specific interests permit. Assessment (i) short paper (1000-1500 words) to be turned in by 5 p.m. on Monday 15th October (topics will be provided); (ii) final essay examination with choice of questions from the whole of the course. Week 1 (19th September; Old Library 2.19): Introduction What linguistics is. Linguistics as a special science. Syntax and semantics as conceived in logic. Charles Morris’s trichotomy of syntax, semantics, and pragmatics. Philosophy of science applied to linguistics. Required reading • Hunter, Geoffrey (1971) Metalogic: An Introduction to the Metatheory of Standard First Order Logic (Berkeley: University of California Press), pp. 4–13. Background reading • Stainton, Robert (2014) ‘Philosophy of linguistics’, Oxford Handbooks Online. Online at https://works.bepress.com/robertstainton/126/ Week 2 (26th September; Old Library 2.19): Language and languages The metaphysics of linguistics. The vexed question of whether language should be regarded as psychological, social, or purely abstract. The descriptive linguistics of the American structuralists and the mentalist/cognitive backlash; ‘God’s truth’ (realism) vs.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 7 Linguistics As a Science of Structure Ryan M
    Chapter 7 Linguistics as a science of structure Ryan M. Nefdt University of the Western Cape Generative linguistics has rapidly changed during the course of a relatively short period. This has caused many to question its scientific status as a realist scientific theory (Stokhof & van Lambalgen 2011; Lappin et al. 2000). In this chapter, I argue against this conclusion. Specifically, I claim that the mathematical foundations of the science present a different story below the surface. I agree with critics that due to the major shifts in theory over the past 80 years, linguistics is indeed opened up to the problem of pessimistic meta-induction or radical theory change. However, I further argue that a structural realist approach (Ladyman 1998; French 2006) can save the field from this problem and at the same time capture its structural nature. I discuss particular historical instances of theory change in generative grammar as evidence for this interpretation and finally attempt to extend it beyond the gener- ative tradition to encompass previous frameworks in linguistics. 1 Introduction The generativist revolution in linguistics started in the mid-1950s, inspired in large part by insights from mathematical logic and in particular proof theory. Since then, generative linguistics has become a dominant paradigm, with many connections to both the formal and natural sciences. At the centre of the newly established discipline was the syntactic or formal engine, the structures of which were revealed through modelling grammatical form. The generativist paradigm in linguistics initially relied heavily upon the proof-theoretic techniques intro- duced by Emil Post and other formal logicians to model the form language takes (Tomalin 2006; Pullum 2011; 2013).1 Yet despite these aforementioned formal be- ginnings, the generative theory of linguistics has changed its commitments quite 1Here my focus will largely be on the formal history of generative syntax but I will make some comments on other aspects of linguistics along the way.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle on Verbal Communication: the First Chapters of De Interpretatione
    EJPC 7 (2) pp. 239–253 Intellect Limited 2016 Empedocles: European Journal for the Philosophy of Communication Volume 7 Number 2 © 2016 Intellect Ltd Critical Review. English language. doi: 10.1386/ejpc.7.2.239_3 CRITICAL REVIEW ANITA KASABOVA Sofia University VLADIMIR MARINOV New Bulgarian University Aristotle on verbal communication: The first chapters of De Interpretatione ABSTRACT KEYWORDS This article deals with the communicational aspects of Aristotle’s theory of significa- Aristotle tion as laid out in the initial chapters of the De Interpretatione (Int.).1 We begin De Interpretatione by outlining the reception and main interpretations of the chapters under discussion, verbal communication rather siding with the linguistic strand. We then argue that the first four chap- signification ters present an account of verbal communication, in which words signify things via linguistic expressions thoughts. We show how Aristotle determines voice as a conventional and hence acci- convention dental medium of signification: words as ‘spoken sounds’ are tokens of thoughts, language use which in turn are signs or natural likenesses of things. We argue that, in this way, 1. We follow the standard linguistic expressions may both signify thoughts and refer to things. This double edition of the Greek account of signification also explains the variety of ontological, logical and psycho- text of Int. by Minio- logical interpretations of the initial chapters of Int. Paluello (1949: 47–72), unless otherwise stated. All references to Aristotle’s works 239 11_EJPC 7.2_Critical review article_239-253.indd 239 11/22/16 1:55 PM Anita Kasabova and Vladimir Marinov follow the citation 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Paul Rastall, a Linguistic Philosophy of Language, Lewiston, Queenston
    Linguistica ONLINE. Published: July 10, 2009 http://www.phil.muni.cz/linguistica/art/mulder/mul-001.pdf ISSN 1801-5336 PAUL RASTALL: A LINGUISTIC PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE, LAMPETER – LEWISTON, 2000[*] review article by Jan W. F. Mulder (University of St. Andrews, UK) Introductory note by Aleš Bičan In 2006 I happened to have a short e-mail conversation with Jan Mulder. I asked him for off-prints of his articles, as some of them were rather hard to find. He was so generous to send me, by regular post, a huge packet of them. It took me some time to realize that some of the included writings had never been published. One of them was a manuscript (type- script) of a discussion of a book by Paul Rastall, a former student of his, which was pub- lished in 2000 by The Edwin Press. I naturally contacted Paul Rastall and asked him about the article. He was not aware of it but supported my idea of having it published in Linguis- tica ONLINE. He consequently spoke to Mulder who welcomed the idea and granted the permission. The article below is thus published for the first time. It should be noted, how- ever, that Jan Mulder has not seen its final form. The text is reproduced here as it appears in the manuscript. I have only corrected a few typographical errors here and there. The only significant change is the inclusion of a list of references. Mulder refers to a number of works, but bibliographical information is not pro- vided. I have tried to list all that are mentioned in the article.
    [Show full text]
  • Linguistics As a Resouvce in Language Planning. 16P
    DOCUMENT RESUME ED 095 698 FL 005 720 AUTHOR Garvin, Paul L. TITLE' Linguistics as a Resouvce in Language Planning. PUB DATE Jun 73 NOTE 16p.; PaFPr presented at the Symposium on Sociolinguistics and Language Planning (Mexico City, Mexico, June-July, 1973) EPRS PPICE MF-$0.75 HC-$1.50 PLUS POSTAGE DESCRIPTORS *Applied Linguistics; Language Development; *Language Planning; Language Role; Language Standardization; Linguistics; Linguistic Theory; Official Languages; Social Planning; *Sociolinguistics ABSTPACT Language planning involves decisions of two basic types: those pertaining to language choice and those pertaining to language development. linguistic theory is needed to evaluate the structural suitability of candidate languages, since both official and national languages mast have a high level of standardizaticn as a cultural necessity. On the other hand, only a braodly conceived and functionally oriented linguistics can serve as a basis for choosiag one language rather than another. The role of linguistics in the area of language development differs somewhat depending on whether development is geared in a technological and scientific or a literary, artistic direction. In the first case, emphasis is on the development of terminologies, and in the second case, on that of grammatical devices and styles. Linguistics can provide realistic and practical arguments in favor of language development, and a detailed, technical understanding of such development, as well as methodological skills. Linguists can and must function as consultants to those who actually make decisions about language planning. For too long linguists have pursued only those aims generated within their own field. They must now broaden their scope to achieve the kind of understanding of language that is necessary for a productive approach to concrete language problems.
    [Show full text]
  • What Is Linguistics?
    What is Linguistics? Matilde Marcolli MAT1509HS: Mathematical and Computational Linguistics University of Toronto, Winter 2019, T 4-6 and W 4, BA6180 MAT1509HS Win2019: Linguistics Linguistics • Linguistics is the scientific study of language - What is Language? (langage, lenguaje, ...) - What is a Language? (lange, lengua,...) Similar to `What is Life?' or `What is an organism?' in biology • natural language as opposed to artificial (formal, programming, ...) languages • The point of view we will focus on: Language is a kind of Structure - It can be approached mathematically and computationally, like many other kinds of structures - The main purpose of mathematics is the understanding of structures MAT1509HS Win2019: Linguistics Linguistics Language Families - Niger-Congo (1,532) - Austronesian (1,257) - Trans New Guinea (477) - Sino-Tibetan (449) - Indo-European (439) - Afro-Asiatic (374) - Nilo-Saharian (205) - Oto-Manguean (177) - Austro-Asiatic (169) - Tai-Kadai (92) - Dravidian (85) - Creole (82) - Tupian (76) - Mayan (69) - Altaic (66) - Uto-Aztecan (61) MAT1509HS Win2019: Linguistics Linguistics - Arawakan (59) - Torricelli (56) - Sepik (55) - Quechuan (46) - Na-Dene (46) - Algic (44) - Hmong-Mien (38) - Uralic (37) - North Caucasian (34) - Penutian (33) - Macro-Ge (32) - Ramu-Lower Sepik (32) - Carib (31) - Panoan (28) - Khoisan (27) - Salishan (26) - Tucanoan (25) - Isolated Languages (75) MAT1509HS Win2019: Linguistics Linguistics MAT1509HS Win2019: Linguistics Linguistics The Indo-European Language Family: Phylogenetic Tree
    [Show full text]
  • Why Major in Linguistics (And What Does a Linguist Do)? by Monica Macaulay and Kristen Syrett
    1 Why Major in Linguistics (and what does a linguist do)? by Monica Macaulay and Kristen Syrett What is linguistics? Speakers of all languages know a lot about their languages, usually without knowing that they know If you are considering becoming a linguistics it. For example, as a speaker of English, you major, you probably know something about the possess knowledge about English word order. field of linguistics already. However, you may find Perhaps without even knowing it, you understand it hard to answer people who ask you, "What that Sarah admires the teacher is grammatical, exactly is linguistics, and what does a linguist do?" while Admires Sarah teacher the is not, and also They might assume that it means you speak a lot of that The teacher admires Sarah means something languages. And they may be right: you may, in entirely different. You know that when you ask a fact, be a polyglot! But while many linguists do yes-no question, you may reverse the order of speak multiple languages—or at least know a fair words at the beginning of the sentence and that the bit about multiple languages—the study of pitch of your voice goes up at the end of the linguistics means much more than this. sentence (for example, in Are you going?). Linguistics is the scientific study of language, and However, if you speak French, you might add est- many topics are studied under this umbrella. At the ce que at the beginning, and if you know American heart of linguistics is the search for the unconscious knowledge that humans have about language and how it is that children acquire it, an understanding of the structure of language in general and of particular languages, knowledge about how languages vary, and how language influences the way in which we interact with each other and think about the world.
    [Show full text]
  • Language and Psychology. New York: Wiley, 1970
    Some psychological aspects of linguistic data W. J. M. Levelt, Nijmegen In this article some aspects of the relation between linguistics and psychology are considered. It will be shown that some present day linguistic practices are dubious from the psychological point of view (section 4), whereas at the same time the psy­ chological relevance of linguistic theory is central to the transformationalists con­ ception of linguistics (section 2). But even if linguistics is given a more moderate place in the psychology of language (section 3), certain types of linguistic data, na­ mely different sorts of linguistic intuitions, deserve very careful attention in view of their psychological unreliability. Uncontrolable introspectionism should be avoi­ ded and some recommendations to this effect are made (section 5). It is especially stressed that the linguist should not rely on absolute judgment of grammaticality, but only on relative (rank order) judgments; that he should order his rules with respect to their grammatical importance; and that he should study intuitions which have a high degree of reliability, such as intuitions on cohesion. The paper is introduced by a short historical note (section 1), which out­ lines the main conceptions of the relation between psychology and linguistics during the past century and a half. 1. An historical note The views on the relations between psychology and linguistics are as diverse as-the opinions about the relation between human mind and human language. The nine­ teenth and twentieth century literature on this subject is so extensive, that any short review necessarily oversimplifies the intricate matters involved. This is especially true for the present introduction, which will confine itself to a summary indication of the three most outstanding conceptions that have been proposed during this period.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Language in the Twentieth Century Jason Stanley Rutgers University
    Philosophy of Language in the Twentieth Century Jason Stanley Rutgers University In the Twentieth Century, Logic and Philosophy of Language are two of the few areas of philosophy in which philosophers made indisputable progress. For example, even now many of the foremost living ethicists present their theories as somewhat more explicit versions of the ideas of Kant, Mill, or Aristotle. In contrast, it would be patently absurd for a contemporary philosopher of language or logician to think of herself as working in the shadow of any figure who died before the Twentieth Century began. Advances in these disciplines make even the most unaccomplished of its practitioners vastly more sophisticated than Kant. There were previous periods in which the problems of language and logic were studied extensively (e.g. the medieval period). But from the perspective of the progress made in the last 120 years, previous work is at most a source of interesting data or occasional insight. All systematic theorizing about content that meets contemporary standards of rigor has been done subsequently. The advances Philosophy of Language has made in the Twentieth Century are of course the result of the remarkable progress made in logic. Few other philosophical disciplines gained as much from the developments in logic as the Philosophy of Language. In the course of presenting the first formal system in the Begriffsscrift , Gottlob Frege developed a formal language. Subsequently, logicians provided rigorous semantics for formal languages, in order to define truth in a model, and thereby characterize logical consequence. Such rigor was required in order to enable logicians to carry out semantic proofs about formal systems in a formal system, thereby providing semantics with the same benefits as increased formalization had provided for other branches of mathematics.
    [Show full text]