A History of the Concept of God

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

A History of the Concept of God A HISTORY OF THE CONCEPT OF GOD A HISTORY OF THE CONCEPT OF GOD A PROCESS APPROACH DANIEL A. DOMBROWSKI Published by State University of New York Press, Albany © 2016 State University of New York All rights reserved Printed in the United States of America No part of this book may be used or reproduced in any manner whatsoever without written permission. No part of this book may be stored in a retrieval system or transmitted in any form or by any means including electronic, electrostatic, magnetic tape, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise without the prior permission in writing of the publisher. For information, contact State University of New York Press, Albany, NY www.sunypress.edu Production, Ryan Morris Marketing, Anne M. Valentine Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Dombrowski, Daniel A. A history of the concept of God : a process approach / Daniel A. Dombrowski. pages cm Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 978-1-4384-5937-0 (hardcover : alk. paper) ISBN 978-1-4384-5938-7 (e-book) 1. God—History of doctrines. I. Title. BT98.D566 2016 211.09—dc23 2015008207 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 Contents Introduction 1 Part 1. Classical Theism 9 1. Philo (30 bce–50 ce) 11 2. St. Augustine (354–430) 21 3. St. Anselm (1033–1109) 25 4. Al Ghazzali (1058–1111) 35 5. Maimonides (1135–1204) 39 6. St. Thomas Aquinas (1225–1274) 43 7. Rene Descartes (1596–1650) 61 8. Gottfried Leibniz (1646–1716) 65 9. Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) 75 Part 2. Ancient Greek Theism 85 10. Plato (427–347 bce): Omnipresence 87 11. Plato (427–347 bce): Against Omnipotence 101 12. Aristotle (384–322 bce) 109 13. Plotinus (205–270 ce) 121 v vi Contents Part 3. Neoclassical or Process Theism 129 14. Faustus Socinus (1539–1604) 133 15. Friedrich von Schelling (1775–1854) 137 16. Gustav Fechner (1801–1887) 141 17. Charles Sanders Peirce(1839–1914) 149 18. Otto Pfleiderer (1839–1908) 157 19. Nicholas Berdyaev (1874–1948) 161 20. Mohammed Iqbal (1877–1938) 173 21. Martin Buber (1878–1965) 177 22. Pierre Teilhard de Chardin (1881–1955) 181 Part 4. Henri Bergson and 191 Alfred North Whitehead 23. Henri Bergson (1859–1941) 193 24. Alfred North Whitehead (1861–1947): 213 Up to Process and Reality 25. Alfred North Whitehead: 235 Appraisal and Works after Process and Reality Bibliography 259 Index 271 Introduction Literary critics are much more likely than philosophers, theologians, or religious studies scholars to talk about “genre” or a particular type of writing that admits of many different instances. No one objects when a new novel is written or when a new murder mystery appears. A rich genre has appeared relatively recently in philosophy of religion, system- atic theology, or religious studies that is worthy of note and that admits of several additional instantiations: the history of God. At least three works illustrate the type of writing I have in mind. First is the New York Times bestseller by Karen Armstrong, A History of God: The 4,000 Year Quest of Judaism, Christianity, and Islam (1993). This book was followed by the richly illustrated and sprawling work by John Bowker, God: A Brief History (2002), and the concise work by Paul Capetz also titled God: A Brief History (2003), where the subtitle makes much more sense. I love all three works, but for quite different reasons, as I will show. Much more needs to be said in this genre however. Some books appear to be in this genre, but are not. One book, The Evolution of God, appears to be in it, but it deals only tangentially with the his- tory of the concept of God and is more concerned with the evolution of religious belief and the question of why people have believed in God at all (see Wright 2009). The present work makes a scholarly contribution in this genre from the perspective of neoclassical or process theism. Although the authors of the above works mention process thinkers such as Alfred North Whitehead, Charles Hartshorne, Pierre Teilhard de Chardin, Daniel Day Williams, and John Cobb, there is no explicit treatment of the history of the concept of God as interpreted by process thinkers. In 1 2 A HISTORY OF THE CONCEPT OF GOD fact, although all three authors tantalize the reader by implying some sort of admiration for neoclassical or process theism, they nonetheless interpret the history of the concept of God in ways that are very much at odds with neoclassical or process theism. That is, despite the consid- erable strengths of these three books, they are all overly influenced by the tradition of classical theism. This book is an attempt to supplement the works of Armstrong, Bowker, and Capetz from a neoclassical or process point of view. The book deals primarily with the concept of God and not neces- sarily with the existence of God. When I do discuss the existence of God, it is to illuminate some aspect of the concept of God. The hope is that the subject matter of the book will be of interest to those who are curious about this concept, whether they be theist, agnostic, or atheist. A sense of urgency lies behind this book. As I see things, philosoph- ical theism is at a crisis stage wherein two competing forces are at work: continued defenses of classical or traditional theism (described in detail in part 1) that are, on my interpretation, doomed to failure, on the one hand, and equally unpersuasive defenses of religious skepticism, whether atheistic or agnostic, on the other. Neoclassical or process theists try to drive a wedge between these two forces and are thereby likely to receive ire from both sides. Classical theists tend to be intel- lectual conservatives who are distrustful of any neoclassical or process innovation in the concept of God and religious skeptics tend to view neoclassical or process theism as a warmed over leftover from a bygone era. Although it will sound hyperbolic to religious skeptics to put the issue in the following manner, I think that Hartshorne does not in the least exaggerate when he claims that: “The theistic question . is not one more question, even the most important one. It is, on the fun- damental level, and when all its implications are taken into account, the sole question” (Hartshorne 1962, 131). Or again, “philosophy’s most important function . is to clarify the religious question” (Hartshorne 1965, 24). In due course I will try to deliver on these promissory notes. This book resists both of the types of opposition mentioned and indicates the historical roots of the contemporary impasse. To put my thesis succinctly, if philosophical theism is to have a viable future (which is by no means guaranteed given the popularity of both the old and the new atheisms), it must retrace its steps in the past to see where it went wrong. If this judgment also seems hyperbolic, it is nonetheless Introduction 3 important to note that Whitehead shared it decades ago, and he is reported to have said that the classical concept of God that has histor- ically supported Christianity (as well as Judaism and Islam) is “one of the great disasters of the human race” (Whitehead 2001, 171). One could have legitimately expected so much more from it. To cite just one preliminary example, if God is truly omnipotent, as classical theists in the Abrahamic religions (Judaism, Christianity, Islam) attest, then there is no avoiding the conclusion that a mother who gives birth to an infant with an intensely painful deformity can be told (or, more accurately, should be told) that such a tragedy is either sent by, or at least permitted by, God. We can do better, I think. Indeed, we have to do better if philosophical theism is to flourish in that thinking people increasingly notice that the emperor of classical theism has no clothes. The history offered herein is obviously not intended to be compre- hensive so as to cover everything that has been said about the concept of God. Like Armstrong, Bowker, and Capetz, I offer a selective history, but my principles of selection differ from theirs. The major tension in the book involves the similarities and differences between classical theism and neoclassical or process theism. These three authors tend to assume that the legacy of the ancient Greeks for philosophical theism is the idea that, because God is (by definition) perfect, God could not change because to change would indicate a need to transition out of a less than perfect condition. Granted, this caricature of the influence of Greek philosophy on philosophical theism captures part of the story that I will tell, but this story is much more complex than has been told to date. Whitehead is famous for his quip that “the safest general characterization of the European philosophical tradition is that it consists of a series of foot- notes to Plato” (Whitehead [1929] 1978, 39). In no area is this claim more accurate than in the concept of God. A key part of this book is Plato’s role in inadvertently influencing both classical theism and its neoclas- sical or process alternative in all three Abrahamic religions; hence the present history of the concept of God is broadly ecumenical. Part 1, “Classical Theism,” details exactly what I mean by “classical theism” as it developed chronologically in nine philosophers in various periods in the histories of the Abrahamic religions. Part 2, “Ancient Greek Philosophy,” retraces the first part so as to examine three ancient Greek philosophers, Plato, Aristotle, and Plotinus, to show the historical 4 A HISTORY OF THE CONCEPT OF GOD origins of both the insights and the mistakes of classical theists.
Recommended publications
  • An Examination of Charles Hartshorne's Concept of God
    THE DIVINE BECOMING: AN EXAMINATION OF CHARLES HARTSHORNE'S CONCEPT OF GOD By TERRY RICHARD HALL ~ Bachelor of Arts Oklahoma State University Stillwater, Oklahoma 1971 Submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate College of the Oklahoma State University in partial fulfillment of the requirem~nts for the Degree of MASTER OF ARTS July, 1975 \he~~_s l ~15 1-111'fcl verf· ;;L STATE UNl'.'ERSITY Liaf<ARY OCT 23 1975 THE DIVINE BECOMING: AN EXAMINATION OF CHARLES HARTSHORNE'S CONCEPT OF GOD Thesis Approved: Dean of the Gl'a!uate C9llege 923517 ii ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I wish to acknowledge my debt to t~e members of the Philosophy Department· at Oklahoma. State University. They have helped immeasurably in.my sometimes faltering efforts to achieve intellectual maturity. I, would like to espe­ cially mention Dr. Walter Scott, my thesis adviser, and Dr. Edward La~ry, who first.acquainted me with the thought of Charles Hartshorne. They have been a constant source of aid and encouragement in my· attempts to think through the topics covered in this thesis; without, their guidance and advice this-thesis could not, have been written. In addi­ tton, grateful appreciation is·· extended to Professor Charles. Hartshorne; with whom I was privileged to discuss some of these ideas during his visit to the Oklahoma State Univer­ sity campus in the spring of.1975. I am also grateful for the patien'l; assistance of my Wife, Valerie. It·is a singular good fortune.when one's wife is also a philosopher, and many of the.ideas treated herein became clearer as a result of her perceptive com­ ments.
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae
    Curriculum Vitae Name: Daniel A. Dombrowski Birthdate: August 8, l953 Citizenship: USA Address: Philosophy Department; Seattle University; Seattle, WA 98122 Phone: 206-296-5465 E-mail: <[email protected]> Education: University of Maine, B.A., l974 Saint Louis University, Ph.D., l978 Books: l. Plato's Philosophy of History (Washington, DC: University Press of America, l98l), 217 pp. 2. The Philosophy of Vegetarianism (Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, l984), 188 pp. Also Vegetarianism: The Philosophy Behind the Ethical Diet (London: Thorsons, l985), 188 pp. Forward by Peter Singer. 3. Thoreau the Platonist (Frankfurt: Verlag Peter Lang, l986), 219 pp. 4. Hartshorne and the Metaphysics of Animal Rights (Albany: State University of New York Press, l988), 159 pp. 5. Christian Pacifism (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1991), 181 pp. 6. St. John of the Cross: An Appreciation (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1992), 219 pp. 7. Analytic Theism, Hartshorne, and the Concept of God (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1996), 247 pp. 8. Babies and Beasts: The Argument from Marginal Cases (Champaign: University of Illinois Press, 1997), 221 pp. 9. Kazantzakis and God (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1997), 193 pp. 10. A Brief, Liberal, Catholic Defense of Abortion, with Robert Deltete (Champaign: University of Illinois Press, 2000), 158 pp. Also Una Difesa Cattolica Dell’Aborto. Tr. Susi Ferrarello (Rome: Aracne, 2013), 157 pp. 1 11. Not Even a Sparrow Falls: The Philosophy of Stephen R. L. Clark (East Lansing: Michigan State University Press, 2000), 366 pp. 12. Rawls and Religion: The Case for Political Liberalism (Albany: State University of New York Press, 2001), 192 pp.
    [Show full text]
  • Aquinas to Whitehead: Seven Centuries of Metaphysics of Religion
    125 SELECTED BIBLIOGRAPHY A complete list of Charles Hartshorne's writings, arranged chronologically, was compiled and published by his wife, Dorothy. The bibliography of his writings until 1976 appeared in Process Studies, VI, 1 (Spring, 1976), pp. 73 - 93. The up-dated list, which includes his writings up to 1980, was published in Process Studies, XI, 2 (Summer, 1981), pp. 108 -112. Biblio­ graphies of secondary sources, also compiled by Mrs. Hartshorne, will be found in Process Studies, III, 3 (Fall, 1973), pp. 179-227 and Process Studies, XI, 2 (Spring, 1981), pp. 112 - 120. A list of dissertations and theses on Charles Hartshorne was prepared by Dean R. Fowler and published in Process Studies, III, 4 (Winter, 1973), pp. 304-307. Addenda to that list, compiled by Philip Ricards, appeared in Process Studies XI, 2 (Summer, 1981), pp. 151-152. PRIMARY SOURCES Books Anselm's Discovery. La Salle: Open Court, 1967. Aquinas to Whitehead: Seven Centuries of Metaphysics of Religion. The Aquinas Lecture, 1976. Milwaukee: Marquette University Publications, 1976. Beyond Humanism: Essays in the New Philosophy of Nature. Chicago: Willett, Clark & Co., 1937. Bison Book Edition, with new Preface. Lincoln: The University of Nebraska Press, 1968. Creative Synthesis and Philosophic Method. London: SCM Press, Ltd., 1970. La Salle: Open Court, 1970. Creativity in American Philosophy. State University of New York Press, 1984. The Divine Relativity: A Social Conception of God. The Terry Lectures, 1947. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1948. Insights and Oversights of Great Thinkers: an Evaluation of Western Philos­ ophy. State University of New York Press, 1983.
    [Show full text]
  • Panentheism and Panexperientialism for Open and Relational Theology
    Panentheism and Panexperientialism for Open and Relational Theology Thomas Jay Oord and Wm. Andrew Schwartz Open and relational theologies have a particular affinity for panentheism and panexperientialism (panpsychism). These theologies come in various forms, however. And scholars propose various forms of panentheism and panexperi- entialism. Diversity reigns. We begin this essay by describing open and relational theology. We also describe panentheism and panexperientialism, broadly understood. We note reasons why open and relational theists would be attracted to each. And we argue that panentheism and panexperientialism complement one another, al- though a person could be attracted only to one. Much of the essay argues for one form of open and relational theology we think makes the best sense overall. This form includes belief in a personal/ relational God, makes distinctions between God and creatures, affirms God ev- erlastingly creates (thereby denying creatio ex nihilo), and offers a solution to the theoretical aspect of the problem of evil. Adopting panexperientialism and panentheism offers ways to overcome theoretical problems in contemporary thought, while arguably motivating adherents of the view to love (promote overall well-being). 1. Open and Relational Theology The label »open and relational theology« serves as an umbrella designation for a family of theologies.1 This family shares at least two core convictions. The »open« aspect refers to the idea that both creatures and God experience the ongoingness of time. Consequently, both God and creatures face an open, yet to be determined future. Because the future is not actual, it is inherently 1 These include theologies using labels such as open theism, process theism, various relational theologies, some Wesleyan theologies, some feminist theologies, some ecological theologies, some Arminian theologies, some postcolonial theologies, and more.
    [Show full text]
  • Openness and Inerrancy: Can They Be Compatible?
    JETS 45/4 (December 2002) 629–49 OPENNESS AND INERRANCY: CAN THEY BE COMPATIBLE? jason a. nicholls* i. introduction To some observers, the resolution concerning divine foreknowledge passed at the 2001 ETS Annual Meeting in Colorado Springs might seem rather harmless. “We believe the Bible clearly teaches that God has com- plete, accurate, and infallible knowledge of all events past, present, and future, including all future decisions and actions of free moral agents.”1 It undoubtedly reflects the society’s majority viewpoint. Yet this vote comes on the heels of several years of discussion and debate, albeit rather limited until recently, on the question of whether the position known as the open- ness of God is compatible with evangelical theology.2 In fact, some are in- terpreting the results of this vote as the first step down the road toward outright dismissing advocates of the open view from the ETS. Scholars such as Wayne Grudem have admitted as much by characterizing the vote as a “gentle nudge” for open theists to exit the society.3 But exactly why would critics of the openness view want to see this theological position expelled from the society, and why have its proponents come under such intense fire? * Jason A. Nicholls is lecturer in theology at Marquette University, P.O. Box 1881, Milwaukee, WI 53201. 1 See David Neff’s editorial, “Scholars Vote: God Knows Future,” Christianity Today 46/1 (Jan- uary 7, 2002) 21. As Neff reports, this resolution was passed at the 2001 Annual Meeting in Col- orado Springs by a vote of 253 to 66, with 41 members abstaining.
    [Show full text]
  • Charles Hartshorne's Letters to a Young Philosopher: 1979-1995
    Pittsburg State University Pittsburg State University Digital Commons Faculty Submissions Philosophy Fall 2001 Charles Hartshorne's Letters to a Young Philosopher: 1979-1995 Donald W. Viney Pittsburg State University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.pittstate.edu/phil_faculty Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Viney, Donald W., "Charles Hartshorne's Letters to a Young Philosopher: 1979-1995" (2001). Faculty Submissions. 40. https://digitalcommons.pittstate.edu/phil_faculty/40 This Book is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy at Pittsburg State University Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Submissions by an authorized administrator of Pittsburg State University Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. What follows is the contents of Logos-Sophia, volume 11 (Fall 2001), which contains the manuscript of Charles Hartshorne’s Letters to a Young Philosopher: 1979-1995, edited by Donald Wayne Viney. The pagination of the original journal issue is indicated in square brackets. The photo of Hartshorne on the cover of the journal was taken by Don Viney on March 23, 1985 in St. Louis, Missouri. The color photos reproduced here on pages 59 and 60 were originally printed in black and white. The original journal issue included an index, but since this is an electronic document, it can easily be searched so there was no need to include the index in this version. Donald Wayne Viney September 19, 2016 Pittsburg State University 2 Contents Page Introduction 3 [1] Charles Hartshorne’s Letters to a Young Philosopher: 1979-1995 Edited by Donald Wayne Viney 4 [2] Appendix I: The Table of Sixteen Options and Neoclassical Theism 53 [55] Appendix II: Sample Letter from Hartshorne 57 [60] Appendix III: Hartshorne Memorial Statement 58 [61] Index 3 [1] Introduction The Pittsburg State University Philosophical Society is pleased to present the eleventh volume of its journal, Logos-Sophia.
    [Show full text]
  • Theism, the Postmodernist Burial of Metaphysics, and Indian Mind-Body Dualism
    Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers Volume 26 Issue 5 Article 5 12-1-2009 Theism, The Postmodernist Burial of Metaphysics, and Indian Mind-Body Dualism Vladimir K. Shokhin Follow this and additional works at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy Recommended Citation Shokhin, Vladimir K. (2009) "Theism, The Postmodernist Burial of Metaphysics, and Indian Mind-Body Dualism," Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers: Vol. 26 : Iss. 5 , Article 5. DOI: 10.5840/faithphil200926553 Available at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy/vol26/iss5/5 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers by an authorized editor of ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. THEISM, THE POSTMODERNIST BURIAL OF METAPHYSICS, AND INDIAN MIND-BODY DUALISM Vladimir K. Shokhin There is a post-modernist myth that metaphysics has always been an exclu- sively Western heritage. This article refutes such a view by reviewing the many centuries of debate between Indian mind-body dualists and champions of reductionist physicalism. It also suggests the relevance of the Indian dual- istic arguments for contemporary discussions of the mind-body issue. I Mind-body dualism has long been integral, not only to the philosophy of mind, but also to the philosophical foundations of theism. Indeed, the direct opposition between dualism and two rival ontologies of mind is of very old age. One of these rivals is physicalism, or naturalistic reduc- tionism, or the identity theory of mind, all of which allow the status of substance only to the body with its functions.
    [Show full text]
  • Talks and Meetings with Charles Hartshorne
    Pittsburg State University Pittsburg State University Digital Commons Faculty Submissions Philosophy 9-2016 Talks and Meetings with Charles Hartshorne Donald W. Viney Pittsburg State University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.pittstate.edu/phil_faculty Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Viney, Donald W., "Talks and Meetings with Charles Hartshorne" (2016). Faculty Submissions. 41. https://digitalcommons.pittstate.edu/phil_faculty/41 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy at Pittsburg State University Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Submissions by an authorized administrator of Pittsburg State University Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Talks and Meetings with Charles Hartshorne Donald Wayne Viney Charles Hartshorne by Michelle Bakay I knew Charles Hartshorne (June 5, 1897 – October 9, 2000) for the last two decades of his life. One does not easily forget a meeting with him: the smiling eyes behind wire-rimmed glasses; the disheveled eyebrows; the beak-like nose; the voice, pitched high with age, cracking with excitement at some philosophical insight; the slightly disconcerting sense of self- importance tempered by humility before the genius of Plato, Peirce, or Whitehead; the witty anecdotes; the fondness for birds; the blink and nod that bade a charming farewell. His small frame and mail-order clothes only served to bring into relief that one was conversing with a surviving member of the pantheon of twentieth century philosophers, many of whom he knew. 2 Hartshorne’s reputation for entertaining conversation was well-deserved. All who knew the man have their favorite “Hartshorne stories” and I am no exception.
    [Show full text]
  • Systematic Theology
    Systematic Theology Joseph M. Holden All rights reserved 2007 1 Table of Contents Prolegomena ........................................................................................ 4 Bibliology .......................................................................................... 16 Theology Proper ................................................................................. 68 Christology ........................................................................................ 97 Pneumatology .................................................................................. 126 Angelology ....................................................................................... 139 Anthropology and Hamartology .......................................................... 145 Soteriology ...................................................................................... 154 Ecclesiology ..................................................................................... 169 Eschatology ..................................................................................... 180 All rights reserved 2007 Joseph M. Holden 2 “And this is eternal life, that they may know You, the only true God, and Jesus Christ whom You have sent” ~ John 17:3 3 Prolegomena Prolegomena (lit. before I speak ) is the first topic in systematic theology to be studied since it lays the preparatory foundation for theological study by addressing introductory matters such as definitions, methodology, and justifying the possibility of conducting theological research.
    [Show full text]
  • “Hartshorne, Plato, and the Concept of God” by Daniel A
    “Hartshorne, Plato, and the Concept of God” By Daniel A. Dombrowski (Seattle University) [email protected] 1. Introduction. Both religious believers and religious skeptics alike tend to assume that they understand the concept of God quite well. They may disagree regarding the existence of God, but they generally have the same concept in mind. God, it is alleged, is an omnipotent, omniscient (even with respect to future contingencies), and omnibenevolent being who is eternal (in the sense of existing outside of time and history), and who, as a consequence, is strictly immutable. It is to Charles Hartshorne’s credit that he realizes that this concept of God is sedimented in the sense that it is the result of decisions made long ago. These were literal de- cisions that involved the cutting off of some possibilities so that others remained unscathed. Even after the reasons for these decisions were long forgotten, the conceptual sediment remained. The purpose of the present article is to both desedimentize the concept of God and to briefly indicate the superiority of a process or neoclassical concept of God to the classical theistic concept mentioned above. More particularly, my thesis is that a Hartshornian perspective on a Platonic view of God has been largely neglected and that this neglect impoverishes both our view of Plato and more importantly our view of what could profitably be said in contemporary philosophy of religion about the concept of God from a process or neoclassical point of view. At the outset I would like to address the concern that some readers will no doubt have that we are not likely to 1 get very far with a process theism that appeals to Plato in that he was a staunch opponent to the world of becoming.
    [Show full text]
  • Spiritual Warfare” in the Anglican Charismatic Renewal
    The Church Militant: A Study of “Spiritual Warfare” in the Anglican Charismatic Renewal by GRAHAM RUSSELL SMITH A thesis submitted to the University of Birmingham for the degree of DOCTOR of PHILOSOPHY School of Philosophy, Theology and Religion College of Arts and Law University of Birmingham July 2011 University of Birmingham Research Archive e-theses repository This unpublished thesis/dissertation is copyright of the author and/or third parties. The intellectual property rights of the author or third parties in respect of this work are as defined by The Copyright Designs and Patents Act 1988 or as modified by any successor legislation. Any use made of information contained in this thesis/dissertation must be in accordance with that legislation and must be properly acknowledged. Further distribution or reproduction in any format is prohibited without the permission of the copyright holder. ABSTRACT This thesis uses a practical-theological methodology to explore the theology and spirituality of „spiritual warfare‟ that developed in the charismatic renewal from the 1960s. Beginning with a study of twelve charismatic Anglican pioneers, a detailed case study then explores spiritual warfare praxis in a charismatic Anglican congregation. The ensuing theological reflection focuses on the ontology of evil, through dialogue with Nigel Wright, Amos Yong, and Gregory Boyd, as well as Karl Barth and Walter Wink. The thesis argues for a positive ontology for evil powers, based on a charismatic hermeneutic of biblical texts; on the grounds that Jesus treated Satan and demons as real spiritual entities, the Pauline epistles refer to real evil spiritual powers in the heavenly realms, and charismatic experience supports this ontology.
    [Show full text]
  • INTRODUCTION 1. 'Five Stages of Greek Religion' (Watts, 1943) P
    Notes INTRODUCTION 1. 'Five Stages of Greek Religion' (Watts, 1943) p. 12. CHAPTER 1 1. Diaspora means 'dispersion' and refers to Jews living outside Palestine. 2. A group of Christian theologians who wrote c. 120-220. 3. The (first) Council of Nicaea was in 325. 4. I shall quote both from the new Blackfriars edition (which I shall use unless I indicate otherwise) and from the two anthologies entitled 'Philosophical Texts' and 'Theo­ logical Texts', ed. T. Gilby (Oxford University Press, 1951 and 1955). 5. The name given to the author of Isaiah 40-55. 6. 1 Cor. 8:5-6. 7. 'ST' Ia 11, 3. 8. For such a discussion, see the volume in this series on 'Arguments for the Existence of God'. 9. The Christian Trinity and the Plotinian Triad also differ in their structure. The members of the former are, but the members of the latter are not, coequal. I shall discuss Plotinus later. 10. 'God and Philosophy' (Hutchinson, 1966) p. 47. 11. 'ST' la 7, 1. 12. 'New Essays in Philosophical Theology', ed. A. Flew and A. Macintyre (S.C.M. Press, 1963) p. 68. Hick has shown that the failure to distinguish between ontological and logical necessity vitiates Malcolm's reformulation of the ontological argument ('The Many-Faced Argument' Macmillan, 1968 pp. 341-56). 152 13. In his 'De Consolatione', 5. 14. 'ST' la 10, 1. 15. 'Timaeus', 37 D. 16. Mal. 3:6 (quoted by Aquinas in 'ST' la 9, 1). 17. So far as revelation is concerned, we have a symbol of this divine transfiguration in the manner in which the Johannine Christ (as the incarnate Word) associates 'glory' with his Passion.
    [Show full text]