An Analysis and Assessment

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

An Analysis and Assessment THE UNIVERSITY OF OKLAHOMA GRADUATE COLLEGE CHARLES HARTSHORNE'S GLOBAL ARGUMENT FOR GOD'S EXISTENCE: AN ANALYSIS AND ASSESSMENT A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE GRADUATE FACULTY in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY BY DONALD WAYNE VINEY Norman, Oklahoma 1982 CHARLES HARTSHORNE'S GLOBAL ARGUMENT FOR GOD'S EXISTENCE: AN ANALYSIS AND ASSESSMENT APPROVED BY M A jP^À: DISSERTATION COMMITTEE For Jenny ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I owe so much to so many. Professor Hartshorne has my undying gratitude for having agreed to be a member of ray committee. It is a rare privilege to be able to write on a philosopher of Hartshorne's stature. Rarer still is for that person to read and correct one's work. My debt to Dr. Robert Shahan is probably beyond r e ­ payment. By inviting Dr. Hartshorne to serve on ray commit­ tee, he is directly responsible for offering me the oppor­ tunity of a life-time. My mother and father, Wayne and Noni Viney, also had their part in the making of this work. My father invited me to accompany him on an expense free trip to Harvard Univer­ sity in January 1982. There, 1 was able to read Hartshorne's dissertation. Without this opportunity the present work would have remained incomplete. The other members of my committee are also to be thanked. The bulk of this dissertation was written in the span of two months. Drs. Tom Boyd, Francis Kovach, Kenneth Merrill, and Stewart Umphrey are to be commended for staying IV abreast of this deluge of material. Special thanks are in order for Drs. Boyd and Kovach whose comments, more than once, saved me from ambiguity of statement or, in some cases, outright error. I will always be grateful to Drs. Gary Nowlin and Peter Hutcheson. Through long hours of conversation and lengthy correspondence with these friends, many of my ideas took shape. Finally there is my wife, Chris, whose constant faith in my potential was no small factor in the attainment of the goals I sought. KEY TO HARTSHORNE REFERENCES References to Hartshorne's books occur in brackets throughout the text. The source is cited by an abbrevia­ tion of the book title followed by the page number. OP An Outline and Defense of the Argument for the Unity ÔT Being in the Absolute or Divine Good, unpublished doctoral dissertation. Harvard 1923 BH Beyond Humanism: Essays in the Philosophy of Nature. Gloucester, Mass.: Peter Smith, 1975, originally published 1937 M\'~ G Man ' s Vision of God and the Logic of Theism. Chicago: Willett, Clark § Co., 1941 DR The Divine Relativity : A Social Conception of God. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1948 RSP Reality as Social Process : Studies in Metaphysics and Religion. Boston: The Beacon Press, 1953 PSG Philosophers Speak of God. With William L. Reese. Chicago : University of Chicago, 1953 LP The Logic of Perfection and Other Essays in Neoclas- sical Metaphysics. La Salle, II.: Open Court, 1962 AD Anselm's Discovery. La Salle, 11.: Open Court, 1965 NT A Natural Theology for Our Time. La Salle, II. : Open Court, 1967 CS Creative Synthesis and Philosophic Method. La Salle, II.: Open Court, 1970 WP Whitehead's Philosophy: Selected Essays, 1955-197 0. Lincoln : University of Nebraska Press, 1972 VI AW Aquinas to Whitehead : Seven Centuries of Metaphysics of Religion. Milwaukee: Marquette University Pub., 1976 WV Whitehead's View of Reality. With Creighton Peden. New York: Pilgrim Press, 1981 There have been arguments to prove or disprove a purely ab­ solute being; and others which, if they proved anything, could only establish the existence or nonexistence of a purely relative and contingent God; but what is hard to find (until Schelling or later impossible) is an argument expli­ citly and clearly bearing on the question whether there is a God both absolute or necessary and (in another aspect) rela­ tive or contingent, that is, reflexively transcendenr. Such arguments are possible, and only when philosophers have con­ sidered them with something of the care they have bestowed upon arguments dealing with a less intelligible conception will it be time to say that the arguments for God's existence have been either validated or invalidated. The question we need to investigate concerns the existence of a being whose nature conforms to the formal structure of the idea: "sur­ passing self and all others." Charles Hartshorne (RSP, 124-125) TABLE OF CONTENTS Page ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS............................................. iv KEY TO HARTSHORNE REFERENCES................................vi INTRODUCTION................................................... 1 Chapter I. THE IDEA OF A CUMULATIVE CASE.......................... 5 II. THE GLOBAL ARGUMENT: PRELIMINARY CONSIDERATIONS.......................................26 III. NEOCLASSICAL THEISM................................... 38 IV. THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT............................ 66 V. THE COSMOLOGICAL ARGUMENT............................ 87 VI. THE DESIGN ARGUMENT.................................. 119 VII. THE EPISTEMIC ARGUMENT............................. 147 VIII. THE MORAL ARGUMENT..................................167 IX. THE AESTHETIC ARGUMENT............................. 187 X. AN ASSESSMENT OF THE GLOBALAR G U M E N T .............2 04 HISTORICAL N O T E ............................................ 236 BIBLIOGRAPHY................................................. 239 CHARLES HARTSHORNE'S GLOBAL ARGUMENT FOR GOD'S EXISTENCE: AN ANALYSIS AND ASSESSMENT INTRODUCTION Charles Hartshorne has long been known for his lively defense of the ontological argument. What few realize, how­ ever, is that the ontological argument is not the only rea­ son, or even the most important reason, that Hartshorne is a theist. Hartshorne says. If 1 were asked, "Why do you believe in God?," 1 would not reply, "Because of the ontological argument." Rath­ er, 1 would say that it is because of a group of argu­ ments that mutually support one another so that their combined strength is not, as Kant would have it, like that of a chain which is as weak as its weakest link, but like that of a cable whose strength sums the strength of its several fibers.^ The nexus of arguments to which Hartshorne refers is called the global argument. Surprisingly, even some careful stu­ dents of Hartshorne's thought are ignorant of the important role the global argument plays in Hartshorne's theism. David Charles Hartshorne, Forward to The Ontological Argument of Charles Hartshorne by George L. Goodwin (Mis- soula, Montana: Scholar's Press, 1978), p. xi. Pailin, for example, criticizes Hartshorne's ontological argument on the grounds that it does not prove that the con­ cept of God is coherently conceivable.” This is a criticism Hartshorne, time and again, has acknowledged.^ Hartshorne never took the ontological argument to be a complete proof of theism. In the twelve years since Hartshorne first expli­ citly formalized the global argument, not one article, book, or dissertation has dealt with the argument in more than a cursory fashion.^ Hartshorne admits that he may be partially responsible for the neglect of his argument. The 1970 pre­ sentation of the global argument is sketchy and brief.^ Nevertheless, the present work (see especially Chapter II) proves that the global argument has been part of Hartshorne's philosophy ever since his days at Harvard in the 1920s. The misunderstanding of Hartshorne's position and the relative neglect of the global argument provide the raison d 'etre of this work. It is also my purpose to high- 2 David A. Pailin, "Some Comments on Hartshorne's Presentation of the Ontological Argument," Religious Studies, 4, 1 (1968), p. 114. ^Charles Hartshorne, "What the Ontological Proof Does Not Do," Review of Metaphysics, 17, 4 (June 1964), pp. 608- 609. ^The global argument was published in The Monist, 54, 2 (April 1970), pp. 159-180 and as Chapter XIV of CS. ^In a letter dated February 2, 1981 Hartshorne writes, "The account of the arguments in Creative Synth. [sic] is very brief and, I now think, is one reason it has had so little attention." light the fact that the global argument is a cumulative case. The case for God's existence is built on a series of interrelated arguments which support each other at their weakest points. Too many philosophers of religion labor u n ­ der the assumption that theism stands or falls with the suc­ cess or failure of a single argument. The global argument is a much needed remedy for this prevalent misconception. Chapter I discusses the concept of a cumulative case and answers the few objections that have been raised against such an enterprise. Chapter II deals with the history and form of Hartshorne's cumulative case. Chapter III familiar­ izes the reader with Hartshorne's concept of God. Chapters IV through IX take up the elements of the global argument on an individual basis. Thus, there are discussions of the ontological argument, the design argument, the moral argu­ ment and so on. Chapter X attempts to show the interrela­ tions among the elements of the global argument and offers some critical observations of Hartshorne's position. According to Hartshorne, an entire metaphysical sys­ tem can be spun from a sufficiently clarified concept of God CCS 39). The global argument, therefore, could be under­ stood as a restatement of some of the major themes of Hartshorne's metaphysics. Understanding this, I often became dizzy contemplating the complexity of the task before me. To keep the work to a manageable length it was often neces­ sary to discuss problems with less thoroughness than they deserve. Nevertheless, it is hoped that this overview of the global argument can serve as a basis for a better under­ standing of Hartshorne's thought and as an impetus for fu­ ture dialogue. CHAPTER I THE IDEA OF A CUMULATIVE CASE Rational support for theism has traditionally taken the form of offering one or more of the standard proofs of God's existence. The proofs are usually presented as if each one must bear the full weight of the theistic conclu­ sion, much as the center post of a tent must support the entire weight of the canvass.
Recommended publications
  • Is Plantinga's Argument for God Incompatible with Human Free Will?
    123 IS PLANTINGA'S ARGUMENT FOR GOD INCOMPATIBLE WITH HUMAN FREE WILL? MARINA GARNER1 Abstract / Resumo es Morriston has written a few articles claiming the incompatibility of Alvin WPlantinga’s Modal Ontological Argument and the Free Will Argument against the problem of evil. According to him, the Modal Ontological Argument defends an essentially good and free God in opposition to the Free Will Argument, which defends that the best kind of freedom is the significant freedom (SF), justifying God creating us with such freedom. In this paper, we attempt to summarize the arguments and Morriston’s position. In conclusion, we will see that there are reasons to agree with both of Plantinga’s arguments without falling in to a contradiction. Key words: Alvin Plantinga; Modal ontological argument; Free will argument; Wes Morriston. es Morriston escreveu alguns artigos afirmando a incompatibilidade do WArgumento Ontológico Modal de Alvin Plantinga e o Argumento do Livre Arbítrio contra o problema do mal. De acordo com ele, o Argumento Ontológico Modal defende um Deus essencialmente bom e livre em oposição ao Argumento do Livre Arbítrio, que defende que o melhor tipo de liberdade é a liberdade significativa, justificando a pessoa de Deus ao nos criar com tal liberdade. Nesse trabalho tentaremos resumir os argumentos e a posição de Morriston. Concluindo, veremos que há razões para concordar com ambos os argumentos de Plantinga sem entrar em contradição. Palavras-chaves: Alvin Plantinga; Argumento ontológico modal; Argumento do livre- arbítrio; Wes Morrison. In the realm of Christian apologetics and the doctrine of God, all arguments would ideally be in perfect accord.
    [Show full text]
  • An Examination of Charles Hartshorne's Concept of God
    THE DIVINE BECOMING: AN EXAMINATION OF CHARLES HARTSHORNE'S CONCEPT OF GOD By TERRY RICHARD HALL ~ Bachelor of Arts Oklahoma State University Stillwater, Oklahoma 1971 Submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate College of the Oklahoma State University in partial fulfillment of the requirem~nts for the Degree of MASTER OF ARTS July, 1975 \he~~_s l ~15 1-111'fcl verf· ;;L STATE UNl'.'ERSITY Liaf<ARY OCT 23 1975 THE DIVINE BECOMING: AN EXAMINATION OF CHARLES HARTSHORNE'S CONCEPT OF GOD Thesis Approved: Dean of the Gl'a!uate C9llege 923517 ii ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I wish to acknowledge my debt to t~e members of the Philosophy Department· at Oklahoma. State University. They have helped immeasurably in.my sometimes faltering efforts to achieve intellectual maturity. I, would like to espe­ cially mention Dr. Walter Scott, my thesis adviser, and Dr. Edward La~ry, who first.acquainted me with the thought of Charles Hartshorne. They have been a constant source of aid and encouragement in my· attempts to think through the topics covered in this thesis; without, their guidance and advice this-thesis could not, have been written. In addi­ tton, grateful appreciation is·· extended to Professor Charles. Hartshorne; with whom I was privileged to discuss some of these ideas during his visit to the Oklahoma State Univer­ sity campus in the spring of.1975. I am also grateful for the patien'l; assistance of my Wife, Valerie. It·is a singular good fortune.when one's wife is also a philosopher, and many of the.ideas treated herein became clearer as a result of her perceptive com­ ments.
    [Show full text]
  • Structural Reflection and the Ultimate L As the True, Noumenal Universe Of
    Scuola Normale Superiore di Pisa CLASSE DI LETTERE Corso di Perfezionamento in Filosofia PHD degree in Philosophy Structural Reflection and the Ultimate L as the true, noumenal universe of mathematics Candidato: Relatore: Emanuele Gambetta Prof.- Massimo Mugnai anno accademico 2015-2016 Structural Reflection and the Ultimate L as the true noumenal universe of mathematics Emanuele Gambetta Contents 1. Introduction 7 Chapter 1. The Dream of Completeness 19 0.1. Preliminaries to this chapter 19 1. G¨odel'stheorems 20 1.1. Prerequisites to this section 20 1.2. Preliminaries to this section 21 1.3. Brief introduction to unprovable truths that are mathematically interesting 22 1.4. Unprovable mathematical statements that are mathematically interesting 27 1.5. Notions of computability, Turing's universe and Intuitionism 32 1.6. G¨odel'ssentences undecidable within PA 45 2. Transfinite Progressions 54 2.1. Preliminaries to this section 54 2.2. Gottlob Frege's definite descriptions and completeness 55 2.3. Transfinite progressions 59 3. Set theory 65 3.1. Preliminaries to this section 65 3.2. Prerequisites: ZFC axioms, ordinal and cardinal numbers 67 3.3. Reduction of all systems of numbers to the notion of set 71 3.4. The first large cardinal numbers and the Constructible universe L 76 3.5. Descriptive set theory, the axioms of determinacy and Luzin's problem formulated in second-order arithmetic 84 3 4 CONTENTS 3.6. The method of forcing and Paul Cohen's independence proof 95 3.7. Forcing Axioms, BPFA assumed as a phenomenal solution to the continuum hypothesis and a Kantian metaphysical distinction 103 3.8.
    [Show full text]
  • A Cardinal Sin: the Infinite in Spinoza's Philosophy
    Macalester College DigitalCommons@Macalester College Philosophy Honors Projects Philosophy Department Spring 2014 A Cardinal Sin: The nfinitI e in Spinoza's Philosophy Samuel H. Eklund Macalester College, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.macalester.edu/phil_honors Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Eklund, Samuel H., "A Cardinal Sin: The nfinitI e in Spinoza's Philosophy" (2014). Philosophy Honors Projects. Paper 7. http://digitalcommons.macalester.edu/phil_honors/7 This Honors Project is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy Department at DigitalCommons@Macalester College. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Honors Projects by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@Macalester College. For more information, please contact [email protected]. A Cardinal Sin: The Infinite in Spinoza’s Philosophy By: Samuel Eklund Macalester College Philosophy Department Honors Advisor: Geoffrey Gorham Acknowledgements This thesis would not have been possible without my advisor, Professor Geoffrey Gorham. Through a collaborative summer research grant, I was able to work with him in improving a vague idea about writing on Spinoza’s views on existence and time into a concrete analysis of Spinoza and infinity. Without his help during the summer and feedback during the past academic year, my views on Spinoza wouldn’t have been as developed as they currently are. Additionally, I would like to acknowledge the hard work done by the other two members of my honors committee: Professor Janet Folina and Professor Andrew Beveridge. Their questions during the oral defense and written feedback were incredibly helpful in producing the final draft of this project.
    [Show full text]
  • An Anselmian Approach to Divine Simplicity
    Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers Volume 37 Issue 3 Article 3 7-1-2020 An Anselmian Approach to Divine Simplicity Katherin A. Rogers Follow this and additional works at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy Recommended Citation Rogers, Katherin A. (2020) "An Anselmian Approach to Divine Simplicity," Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers: Vol. 37 : Iss. 3 , Article 3. DOI: 10.37977/faithphil.2020.37.3.3 Available at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy/vol37/iss3/3 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers by an authorized editor of ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. applyparastyle "fig//caption/p[1]" parastyle "FigCapt" applyparastyle "fig" parastyle "Figure" AQ1–AQ5 AN ANSELMIAN APPROACH TO DIVINE SIMPLICITY Katherin A. Rogers The doctrine of divine simplicity (DDS) is an important aspect of the clas- sical theism of philosophers like Augustine, Anselm, and Thomas Aquinas. Recently the doctrine has been defended in a Thomist mode using the intrin- sic/extrinsic distinction. I argue that this approach entails problems which can be avoided by taking Anselm’s more Neoplatonic line. This does involve AQ6 accepting some controversial claims: for example, that time is isotemporal and that God inevitably does the best. The most difficult problem involves trying to reconcile created libertarian free will with the Anselmian DDS. But for those attracted to DDS the Anselmian approach is worth considering.
    [Show full text]
  • William James As American Plato? Scott Sinclair
    WILLIAM JAMES AS AMERICAN PLATO? ______________________________________________________________________________ SCOTT SINCLAIR ABSTRACT Alfred North Whitehead wrote a letter to Charles Hartshorne in 1936 in which he referred to William James as the American Plato. Especially given Whitehead’s admiration of Plato, this was a high compliment to James. What was the basis for this compliment and analogy? In responding to that question beyond the partial and scattered references provided by Whitehead, this article briefly explores the following aspects of the thought of James in relation to Whitehead: the one and the many, the denial of Cartesian dualism, James’s background in physiology, refutation of Zeno’s paradoxes, religious experience, and other kinships. In the end, the author agrees with Robert Neville that James had seminal ideas which could correctly result in a complimentary analogy with Plato. Therefore, a greater focus on the important thought of James is a needed challenge in contemporary philosophy. Michel Weber provided a very helpful article in two parts entitled, “Whitehead’s Reading of James and Its Context,” in the spring 2002 and fall 2003 editions of Streams of William James. Weber began his article with a reference to Bertrand Russell: “When Bertrand Russell (1872-1970) visited Harvard in 1936, ‘there were two heroes in his lectures – Plato and James.’”1 Although he goes on to affirm that Whitehead could have said the same, Weber either overlooks the fact, or is not aware, that Whitehead actually did compare James to Plato in his January 2, 1936 hand-written letter to Charles Hartshorne, as printed by Whitehead’s biographer, Victor Lowe: European philosophy has gone dry, and cannot make any worthwhile use of the results of nineteenth century scholarship.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Infinite in Leibniz's Philosophy
    On the Infinite in Leibniz's Philosophy Elad Lison Interdisciplinary Studies Unit Science, Technology and Society Ph.D. Thesis Submitted to the Senate of Bar-Ilan University Ramat-Gan, Israel August 2010 This work was carried out under the supervision of Dr. Ohad Nachtomy (Department of Philosophy), Bar-Ilan University. Contents א.……………………………….…………………………………………Hebrew Abstract Prologue…………………………………………………………...………………………1 Part A: Historic Survey Methodological Introduction…………………………………………………………..15 1. Aristotle: Potential Infinite………………………………………………………….16 2. Thomas Aquinas: God and the Infinite………………………………………..…….27 3. William of Ockham: Syncategorematic and Actual Infinite……………………..….32 4. Rabbi Abraham Cohen Herrera: Between Absolute Unity and Unbounded Multitude………………………………………………………………………..….42 5. Galileo Galilei: Continuum Constructed from Infinite Zero's………………………49 6. René Descartes: Infinite as Indefinite…………………………………………….…58 7. Pierre Gassendi: Rejection of the Infinite…………………………………………...69 8. Baruch Spinoza: Infinite Unity…………………………………………………...…73 9. General Background: Leibniz and the History of the Infinite……………………....81 Summary…………………………………………………………………………….…94 Part B: Mathematics Introduction…………………………………………………………………………….99 1. 'De Arte Combinatoria' as a Formal Basis for Thought: Retrospective on Leibniz's 1666 Dissertation………………………………………………………………....102 2. Leibniz and the Infinitesimal Calculus……………………………………….……111 2.1. Mathematical Background: Mathematical Works in 16th-17th Centuries…..111 2.2. Leibniz's Mathematical Development…………………………………….…127
    [Show full text]
  • Cantor on Infinity in Nature, Number, and the Divine Mind
    Cantor on Infinity in Nature, Number, and the Divine Mind Anne Newstead Abstract. The mathematician Georg Cantor strongly believed in the existence of actually infinite numbers and sets. Cantor’s “actualism” went against the Aristote- lian tradition in metaphysics and mathematics. Under the pressures to defend his theory, his metaphysics changed from Spinozistic monism to Leibnizian volunta- rist dualism. The factor motivating this change was two-fold: the desire to avoid antinomies associated with the notion of a universal collection and the desire to avoid the heresy of necessitarian pantheism. We document the changes in Can- tor’s thought with reference to his main philosophical-mathematical treatise, the Grundlagen (1883) as well as with reference to his article, “Über die verschiedenen Standpunkte in bezug auf das aktuelle Unendliche” (“Concerning Various Perspec- tives on the Actual Infinite”) (1885). I. he Philosophical Reception of Cantor’s Ideas. Georg Cantor’s dis- covery of transfinite numbers was revolutionary. Bertrand Russell Tdescribed it thus: The mathematical theory of infinity may almost be said to begin with Cantor. The infinitesimal Calculus, though it cannot wholly dispense with infinity, has as few dealings with it as possible, and contrives to hide it away before facing the world Cantor has abandoned this cowardly policy, and has brought the skeleton out of its cupboard. He has been emboldened on this course by denying that it is a skeleton. Indeed, like many other skeletons, it was wholly dependent on its cupboard, and vanished in the light of day.1 1Bertrand Russell, The Principles of Mathematics (London: Routledge, 1992 [1903]), 304.
    [Show full text]
  • Statement of the Problem 1
    Liberty Baptist Theological Seminary THE INCOMPATIBILITY OF OPEN THEISM WITH THE DOCTRINE OF INERRANCY A Report Presented in Partial Fulfillment Of the Requirements for the Degree of Master of Theology by Stuart M. Mattfield 29 December 2014 Copyright © 2015 by Stuart M. Mattfield All Rights Reserved ii ACKNOWLEDGMENTS As with all things, the first-fruits of my praise goes to God: Father, Son and Spirit. I pray this work brings Him glory and honor. To my love and wife, Heidi Ann: You have been my calm, my sanity, my helpful critic, and my biggest support. Thank you and I love you. To my kids: Madison, Samantha, and Nick: Thank you for your patience, your humor, and your love. Thank you to Dr. Kevin King and Dr. Dan Mitchell. I greatly appreciate your mentorship and patience through this process. iii ABSTRACT The primary purpose of this thesis is to show that the doctrine of open theism denies the doctrine of inerrancy. Specifically open theism falsely interprets Scriptural references to God’s Divine omniscience and sovereignty, and conversely ignores the weighty Scriptural references to those two attributes which attribute perfection and completeness in a manner which open theism explicitly denies. While the doctrine of inerrancy has been hotly debated since the Enlightenment, and mostly so through the modern and postmodern eras, it may be argued that there has been a traditional understanding of the Bible’s inerrancy that is drawn from Scripture, and has been held since the early church fathers up to today’s conservative theologians. This view was codified in October, 1978 in the form of the Chicago Statement of Biblical Inerrancy.
    [Show full text]
  • A Contextual Examination of Three Historical Stages of Atheism and the Legality of an American Freedom from Religion
    ABSTRACT Rejecting the Definitive: A Contextual Examination of Three Historical Stages of Atheism and the Legality of an American Freedom from Religion Ethan Gjerset Quillen, B.A., M.A., M.A. Mentor: T. Michael Parrish, Ph.D. The trouble with “definitions” is they leave no room for evolution. When a word is concretely defined, it is done so in a particular time and place. Contextual interpretations permit a better understanding of certain heavy words; Atheism as a prime example. In the post-modern world Atheism has become more accepted and popular, especially as a reaction to global terrorism. However, the current definition of Atheism is terribly inaccurate. It cannot be stated properly that pagan Atheism is the same as New Atheism. By interpreting the Atheisms from four stages in the term‟s history a clearer picture of its meaning will come out, hopefully alleviating the stereotypical biases weighed upon it. In the interpretation of the Atheisms from Pagan Antiquity, the Enlightenment, the New Atheist Movement, and the American Judicial and Civil Religious system, a defense of the theory of elastic contextual interpretations, rather than concrete definitions, shall be made. Rejecting the Definitive: A Contextual Examination of Three Historical Stages of Atheism and the Legality of an American Freedom from Religion by Ethan Gjerset Quillen, B.A., M.A. A Thesis Approved by the J.M. Dawson Institute of Church-State Studies ___________________________________ Robyn L. Driskell, Ph.D., Interim Chairperson Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of Baylor University in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Master of Arts Approved by the Thesis Committee ___________________________________ T.
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae
    Curriculum Vitae Name: Daniel A. Dombrowski Birthdate: August 8, l953 Citizenship: USA Address: Philosophy Department; Seattle University; Seattle, WA 98122 Phone: 206-296-5465 E-mail: <[email protected]> Education: University of Maine, B.A., l974 Saint Louis University, Ph.D., l978 Books: l. Plato's Philosophy of History (Washington, DC: University Press of America, l98l), 217 pp. 2. The Philosophy of Vegetarianism (Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, l984), 188 pp. Also Vegetarianism: The Philosophy Behind the Ethical Diet (London: Thorsons, l985), 188 pp. Forward by Peter Singer. 3. Thoreau the Platonist (Frankfurt: Verlag Peter Lang, l986), 219 pp. 4. Hartshorne and the Metaphysics of Animal Rights (Albany: State University of New York Press, l988), 159 pp. 5. Christian Pacifism (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1991), 181 pp. 6. St. John of the Cross: An Appreciation (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1992), 219 pp. 7. Analytic Theism, Hartshorne, and the Concept of God (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1996), 247 pp. 8. Babies and Beasts: The Argument from Marginal Cases (Champaign: University of Illinois Press, 1997), 221 pp. 9. Kazantzakis and God (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1997), 193 pp. 10. A Brief, Liberal, Catholic Defense of Abortion, with Robert Deltete (Champaign: University of Illinois Press, 2000), 158 pp. Also Una Difesa Cattolica Dell’Aborto. Tr. Susi Ferrarello (Rome: Aracne, 2013), 157 pp. 1 11. Not Even a Sparrow Falls: The Philosophy of Stephen R. L. Clark (East Lansing: Michigan State University Press, 2000), 366 pp. 12. Rawls and Religion: The Case for Political Liberalism (Albany: State University of New York Press, 2001), 192 pp.
    [Show full text]
  • Aquinas to Whitehead: Seven Centuries of Metaphysics of Religion
    125 SELECTED BIBLIOGRAPHY A complete list of Charles Hartshorne's writings, arranged chronologically, was compiled and published by his wife, Dorothy. The bibliography of his writings until 1976 appeared in Process Studies, VI, 1 (Spring, 1976), pp. 73 - 93. The up-dated list, which includes his writings up to 1980, was published in Process Studies, XI, 2 (Summer, 1981), pp. 108 -112. Biblio­ graphies of secondary sources, also compiled by Mrs. Hartshorne, will be found in Process Studies, III, 3 (Fall, 1973), pp. 179-227 and Process Studies, XI, 2 (Spring, 1981), pp. 112 - 120. A list of dissertations and theses on Charles Hartshorne was prepared by Dean R. Fowler and published in Process Studies, III, 4 (Winter, 1973), pp. 304-307. Addenda to that list, compiled by Philip Ricards, appeared in Process Studies XI, 2 (Summer, 1981), pp. 151-152. PRIMARY SOURCES Books Anselm's Discovery. La Salle: Open Court, 1967. Aquinas to Whitehead: Seven Centuries of Metaphysics of Religion. The Aquinas Lecture, 1976. Milwaukee: Marquette University Publications, 1976. Beyond Humanism: Essays in the New Philosophy of Nature. Chicago: Willett, Clark & Co., 1937. Bison Book Edition, with new Preface. Lincoln: The University of Nebraska Press, 1968. Creative Synthesis and Philosophic Method. London: SCM Press, Ltd., 1970. La Salle: Open Court, 1970. Creativity in American Philosophy. State University of New York Press, 1984. The Divine Relativity: A Social Conception of God. The Terry Lectures, 1947. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1948. Insights and Oversights of Great Thinkers: an Evaluation of Western Philos­ ophy. State University of New York Press, 1983.
    [Show full text]