Decentering the Brain: Embodied Cognition and the Critique of Neurocentrism and Narrow-Minded Philosophy of Mind

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Decentering the Brain: Embodied Cognition and the Critique of Neurocentrism and Narrow-Minded Philosophy of Mind University of Wollongong Research Online Faculty of Law, Humanities and the Arts - Papers Faculty of Arts, Social Sciences & Humanities 1-1-2018 Decentering the brain: Embodied cognition and the critique of neurocentrism and narrow-minded philosophy of mind Shaun Gallagher University of Wollongong, University of Memphis, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://ro.uow.edu.au/lhapapers Part of the Arts and Humanities Commons, and the Law Commons Recommended Citation Gallagher, Shaun, "Decentering the brain: Embodied cognition and the critique of neurocentrism and narrow-minded philosophy of mind" (2018). Faculty of Law, Humanities and the Arts - Papers. 3784. https://ro.uow.edu.au/lhapapers/3784 Research Online is the open access institutional repository for the University of Wollongong. For further information contact the UOW Library: [email protected] Decentering the brain: Embodied cognition and the critique of neurocentrism and narrow-minded philosophy of mind Abstract Context: Challenges by embodied, enactive, extended and ecological approaches to cognition have provided good reasons to shift away from neurocentric theories. Problem: Classic cognitivist accounts tend towards internalism, representationalism and methodological individualism. Such accounts not only picture the brain as the central and almost exclusive mechanism of cognition, they also conceive of brain function in terms that ignore the dynamical relations among brain, body and environment. Method: I review four areas of research (perception, action/ agency, self, social cognition) where enactivist accounts have shown alternative ways of thinking about the brain. Results: Taken together, such analyses form a comprehensive alternative to the classic conceptions of cognitivist, computational neuroscience. Implications: Such considerations motivate the need to re-think our understanding of how the brain itself works. They suggest that the best explanation of brain function may be found in the mixed vocabularies of embodied and situated cognition, developmental psychology, ecological psychology, dynamic systems theory, applied linguistics, the theory of affordances and material engagement, rather than the narrow vocabulary of computational neuroscience. Constructivist content: This account is consistent with an enactivist-constructivist approach to cognition. Disciplines Arts and Humanities | Law Publication Details Gallagher, S. (2018). Decentering the brain: Embodied cognition and the critique of neurocentrism and narrow-minded philosophy of mind. Constructivist Foundations, 14 (1), 8-21. This journal article is available at Research Online: https://ro.uow.edu.au/lhapapers/3784 4E Cognition Decentering the Brain Embodied Cognition and the Critique of Neurocentrism and Narrow-Minded Philosophy of Mind Shaun Gallagher University of Memphis, USA, and University of Wollongong, Australia • s.gallagher/at/memphis.edu > Context • Challenges by embodied, enactive, extended and ecological approaches to cognition have provided good reasons to shift away from neurocentric theories. > Problem • Classic cognitivist accounts tend towards internalism, representationalism and methodological individualism. Such accounts not only picture the brain as the central and almost exclusive mechanism of cognition, they also conceive of brain function in terms that ignore the dynami- cal relations among brain, body and environment. > Method • I review four areas of research (perception, action/ agency, self, social cognition) where enactivist accounts have shown alternative ways of thinking about the brain. > Results • Taken together, such analyses form a comprehensive alternative to the classic conceptions of cognitivist, computational neuroscience. > Implications • Such considerations motivate the need to re-think our understanding of how the brain itself works. They suggest that the best explanation of brain function may be found in the mixed vo- OGNITION C cabularies of embodied and situated cognition, developmental psychology, ecological psychology, dynamic systems E theory, applied linguistics, the theory of affordances and material engagement, rather than the narrow vocabulary of computational neuroscience. > Constructivist content • This account is consistent with an enactivist-constructivist approach to cognition. > Key words • Internalism, perception, agency, autonomy, self, social cognition, predictive TS IN 4 P processing, enactivism. ONCE C HICAL P Introduction: Internalism that are built into our brains at the factory. These health states: “The brain is like a central and methodological devices do crucial things for us, from managing computer that controls all bodily functions individualism in cognitive our walking and breathing to helping us with syl- […]” Likewise, according to many research- PHILOSO logisms.” (Gazzaniga 1998: xiii) ers, improving education involves learning science how the brain learns, since that is where 8 « 2 » The related claim by Alvin Gold- learning happens (e.g., Blakemore & Frith « 1 » According to classic cognitivist, man and Frederique de Vignemont (2009: 2005; Jones 2009). i.e., computationalist/internalist theories, 154) that the “central system of the mind [… « 3 » In thinking about cognition, self, the brain is the most central part of the i.e., ] the brain is the seat of most, if not all, agency, free will, autonomy, social cognition, central nervous system, where everything mental events” represents a similar view. Ac- and other aspects of mind – and in think- of importance concerning cognition, ac- cording to this classic orthodoxy, the brain ing about when things go wrong in these tion, self-awareness and our relations with is where emotions happen; it is where inten- domains (as in psychopathology) – neuro- others happens. Michael Gazzaniga (1998), tions are formed, and actions are prepared; centrism (or neuroessentialism) is standard. in his prediction that psychology will be a it is where our understanding of others takes Indeed, recently developed neuro-based dis- thing of the past, to be replaced by neurosci- shape. If there is a self it is in the brain (e.g., ciplines – neurophilosophy, neurotheology, ence, provides a nice example of an idea that Northoff et al. 2006), or as Francis Crick neuroeconomics, neuro-marketing, neuro- operates in numerous theories of cognition, once put it: “You’re nothing but a pack of aesthetics, neuropolitics, neurolaw, neuroed- namely that psychological processes are re- neurons” (Crick 1994: 1). This neurocentric ucation, and so on – purportedly help us to ducible to neurological processes: view has become so pervasive it is taught to explain any topic. Across a number of fields, parents who want to understand their chil- neurocentrism has strong advocates who de- “ My view of how the brain works is rooted in an dren. Thus, a website1 devoted to children’s fend it as the only or best way to think about evolutionary perspective that moves from the fact such things (e.g., Huber & Kutschenko 2009; that our mental life reflects the actions of many, 1 | http://kidshealth.org/en/parents/brain- Titley, Brunel & Hansel 2017; Shelley 2013; perhaps dozens to thousands, of neural devices nervous-system.html accessed 17 May 2018. Lee, VanderPloeg & Strifler 2016). CONSTRUCTIVIST FOUNDATIONs vol. 14, N°1 4E Cognition TOC Shaun Gallagher « 4 » In philosophy, neurocentrism here.2 My intent is to paint a large picture long known and well established (Broca as a form of internalism is represented by and to suggest that, taken together, such 1861). The presence of mirror neurons in the well-known brain-in-the-vat thought analyses form a comprehensive alternative this area links it to action recognition (Riz- experiment, which, beyond its use as a to the classic conceptions of cognitivist, zolatti et al. 1996). Mirror neurons are an- thought experiment, is sometimes pro- computational neuroscience. If one thinks other example of reuse: originally motor posed as a model for our best understand- of these different areas of research as four neurons involved in motor control, they are ing of how things work. distinct topics, then one might also think exapted in the course of evolution to serve that these apparently dissociated investiga- social cognition. “ Some form of internalism must be right be- tions actually converge on some basic as- « 9 » This idea of reuse has been ap- cause there isn’t anything else to do the job. The sumptions about how to best make sense propriated by a narrow, internalist “weak” brain is all we have for the purpose of represent- of cognitive phenomena. I will try to show, conception of embodied cognition (EC). ing the world to ourselves and everything we can as we go along, however, that the conver- According to weak EC, neither the physical use must be inside the brain. Each of our beliefs gence of principles reflects deeper connec- body itself (its anatomy, activity, postural must be possible for a being who is a brain in a tions among these areas. Before turning to body-schematic processes) nor the environ- vat because each of us is precisely a brain in a vat; these topics, I will discuss the idea that we ment is an important contributory to cog- the vat is a skull and the ‘messages’ coming in are need to re-think our understanding of how nition. Rather, what is important for weak coming in by way of impacts on the nervous sys- the brain itself works, specifically from the EC are B(ody)-formatted representations tem.” (Searle 1983: 230) perspective of
Recommended publications
  • Minding the Body Interacting Socially Through Embodied Action
    Linköping Studies in Science and Technology Dissertation No. 1112 Minding the Body Interacting socially through embodied action by Jessica Lindblom Department of Computer and Information Science Linköpings universitet SE-581 83 Linköping, Sweden Linköping 2007 © Jessica Lindblom 2007 Cover designed by Christine Olsson ISBN 978-91-85831-48-7 ISSN 0345-7524 Printed by UniTryck, Linköping 2007 Abstract This dissertation clarifies the role and relevance of the body in social interaction and cognition from an embodied cognitive science perspective. Theories of embodied cognition have during the past two decades offered a radical shift in explanations of the human mind, from traditional computationalism which considers cognition in terms of internal symbolic representations and computational processes, to emphasizing the way cognition is shaped by the body and its sensorimotor interaction with the surrounding social and material world. This thesis develops a framework for the embodied nature of social interaction and cognition, which is based on an interdisciplinary approach that ranges historically in time and across different disciplines. It includes work in cognitive science, artificial intelligence, phenomenology, ethology, developmental psychology, neuroscience, social psychology, linguistics, communication, and gesture studies. The theoretical framework presents a thorough and integrated understanding that supports and explains the embodied nature of social interaction and cognition. It is argued that embodiment is the part and parcel of social interaction and cognition in the most general and specific ways, in which dynamically embodied actions themselves have meaning and agency. The framework is illustrated by empirical work that provides some detailed observational fieldwork on embodied actions captured in three different episodes of spontaneous social interaction in situ.
    [Show full text]
  • The Narrative Sense of Others
    University of Wollongong Research Online Faculty of Law, Humanities and the Arts - Papers Faculty of Arts, Social Sciences & Humanities 1-1-2017 The narrative sense of others Shaun Gallagher University of Memphis, University of Wollongong, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://ro.uow.edu.au/lhapapers Part of the Arts and Humanities Commons, and the Law Commons Recommended Citation Gallagher, Shaun, "The narrative sense of others" (2017). Faculty of Law, Humanities and the Arts - Papers. 3301. https://ro.uow.edu.au/lhapapers/3301 Research Online is the open access institutional repository for the University of Wollongong. For further information contact the UOW Library: [email protected] The narrative sense of others Abstract Comment on Duranti, Alessandro. 2015. The anthropology of intentions: Language in a world of others. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Disciplines Arts and Humanities | Law Publication Details Gallagher, S. (2017). The narrative sense of others. HAU: Journal of Ethnographic Theory, 7 (2), 467-473. This journal article is available at Research Online: https://ro.uow.edu.au/lhapapers/3301 2017 | Hau: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 7 (2): 467–473 BOOK SYMPOSIUM The narrative sense of others Shaun Gallagher, University of Memphis Comment on Duranti, Alessandro. 2015. The anthropology of intentions: Language in a world of others. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Philosophers often point to the role of narrative in supporting judgments of agency and evaluative judgments of responsibility in cases of individual action and inten- tion formation. Very few of them, however, suggest that narrative can play a simi- lar role in collaborative decision-making and joint or collective action (Gallagher and Tollefsen 2017).
    [Show full text]
  • The Routledge Handbook of Embodied Cognition
    THE ROUTLEDGE HANDBOOK OF EMBODIED COGNITION Embodied cognition is one of the foremost areas of study and research in philosophy of mind, philosophy of psychology and cognitive science. The Routledge Handbook of Embodied Cognition is an outstanding guide and reference source to the key philosophers, topics and debates in this exciting subject and essential reading for any student and scholar of philosophy of mind and cognitive science. Comprising over thirty chapters by a team of international contributors, the Handbook is divided into six parts: Historical underpinnings Perspectives on embodied cognition Applied embodied cognition: perception, language, and reasoning Applied embodied cognition: social and moral cognition and emotion Applied embodied cognition: memory, attention, and group cognition Meta-topics. The early chapters of the Handbook cover empirical and philosophical foundations of embodied cognition, focusing on Gibsonian and phenomenological approaches. Subsequent chapters cover additional, important themes common to work in embodied cognition, including embedded, extended and enactive cognition as well as chapters on embodied cognition and empirical research in perception, language, reasoning, social and moral cognition, emotion, consciousness, memory, and learning and development. Lawrence Shapiro is a professor in the Department of Philosophy, University of Wisconsin – Madison, USA. He has authored many articles spanning the range of philosophy of psychology. His most recent book, Embodied Cognition (Routledge, 2011), won the American Philosophical Association’s Joseph B. Gittler award in 2013. Routledge Handbooks in Philosophy Routledge Handbooks in Philosophy are state-of-the-art surveys of emerging, newly refreshed, and important fields in philosophy, providing accessible yet thorough assessments of key problems, themes, thinkers, and recent developments in research.
    [Show full text]
  • Wittgenstein and Embodied Cognition: a Critique of the Language of Thought Amber Sheldon University of San Diego, [email protected]
    University of San Diego Digital USD Keck Undergraduate Humanities Research Fellows Humanities Center Spring 2019 Wittgenstein and Embodied Cognition: A Critique of the Language of Thought Amber Sheldon University of San Diego, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digital.sandiego.edu/hc-keck Part of the Other Philosophy Commons, Philosophy of Language Commons, and the Philosophy of Mind Commons Digital USD Citation Sheldon, Amber, "Wittgenstein and Embodied Cognition: A Critique of the Language of Thought" (2019). Keck Undergraduate Humanities Research Fellows. 2. https://digital.sandiego.edu/hc-keck/2 This Working Paper is brought to you for free and open access by the Humanities Center at Digital USD. It has been accepted for inclusion in Keck Undergraduate Humanities Research Fellows by an authorized administrator of Digital USD. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Sheldon Fall 2018 Wittgenstein and Embodied Cognition: A Critique of the Language of Thought Amber Sheldon University of San Diego, 2018 1 Sheldon Fall 2018 Wittgenstein and Embodied Cognition: A Critique of the Language of Thought Amber Sheldon University of San Diego, 2018 Introduction The “computer metaphor” views the content of the mind as being akin to software. Our brains are coded using abstract symbols to represent concepts and semantic rules.1 Such models for understanding the relation between mind and body have been popular among cognitive scientists and philosophers.2 Computational Functionalism views the mind/brain like a computer that works according to a system of symbolic inputs and corresponding outputs. The framework of these computational mental representations is the “language of thought.”3 This symbolic mental language is often analogized with the symbolic “language” of a computer.
    [Show full text]
  • From Embodied Cognition to Free Will
    Introduction Agency: From Embodied Cognition to Free Will Duccio Manetti* [email protected] Silvano Zipoli Caiani** [email protected] Traditional theories about experience have always represented the subject as a passive recipient of sensory stimuli, which get processed through successive layers of the brain cortex and culminate in a phenomenal experience, omitting any mention of the role of the personal sense of agency. According to this formulation, experience emerges as a combination of biological and phenomenological descriptions, linking mechanical processes to subjective qualitative reports. Conceptual frameworks provided by neuroscience and phenomenological analysis are alternative descriptive systems originally conceived for alternative explanatory purposes. Here is the origin of many of the theoretical tensions in cognitive science. Today, after years in which dualism and reductionism have been the only games in town, the idea of an embodied dynamicism is emerging in the field of cognitive science with support from substantial empirical evidence. As perceptual experience is shaped by action execution, it seems necessary to assume a theoretical framework within which the interconnection between the perceiving subject’s conscious states, his body and the environment is adequately emphasized. For the phenomenological debate, the notion of embodiment coincides with the rebuttal of what is usually considered the Cartesian dualism, that is, the segregation of any bodily influence from the subjective experiential domain.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Science of Embodied Cognition in the 2010S
    This article was downloaded by: [University of California, San Diego] On: 17 October 2011, At: 10:02 Publisher: Routledge Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer House, 37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK Journal of the Learning Sciences Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information: http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/hlns20 On the Science of Embodied Cognition in the 2010s: Research Questions, Appropriate Reductionism, and Testable Explanations Rafael Núñez a a Department of Cognitive Science, University of California–San Diego Available online: 02 Sep 2011 To cite this article: Rafael Núñez (2011): On the Science of Embodied Cognition in the 2010s: Research Questions, Appropriate Reductionism, and Testable Explanations, Journal of the Learning Sciences, DOI:10.1080/10508406.2011.614325 To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/10508406.2011.614325 PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE Full terms and conditions of use: http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms- and-conditions This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematic reproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan, sub-licensing, systematic supply, or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden. The publisher does not give any warranty express or implied or make any representation that the contents will be complete or accurate or up to date. The accuracy of any instructions, formulae, and drug doses should be independently verified with primary sources. The publisher shall not be liable for any loss, actions, claims, proceedings, demand, or costs or damages whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with or arising out of the use of this material.
    [Show full text]
  • From the Chair Welcome New Faculty
    Sophia Department of Philosophy From the Chair Issue 3 / Spring 2013 Dear Friends of the University of Memphis Philosophy Department, There have been many exciting new developments in the Philosophy department since our last newsletter. To name just a few: We have made four new faculty hires over the past two years! Despite the economic downturn, our administration has supported our efforts to build our program. They know a good investment when they see it. Dr. Somogy Varga and Dr. Luvell Anderson have joined us as Assistant Professors in the fall of 2012. Dr. Melissa Ebbers joined us as a full-time instructor and coordinator of our online BA program in the fall as well. We have also very recently recruited Dr. Verena Erlenbusch as an assistant professor, and she will join us in the fall of 2013. These hires have allowed us to reinforce our strengths in social and political philosophy. Dr. Varga’s research in critical theory, Dr. Anderson’s research on racial slurs, and Dr. Erlenbusch’s research on terrorism and sovereignty will provide our students with cutting edge work in social and political philosophy. Please be sure to read about them in our new faculty spotlight. In addition to faculty recruitment, our graduate and undergraduate programs continue to flourish. With over 75 majors and an active philosophy club, our undergrads are taking the campus by storm. Their undergraduate conference received over 50 submissions this year and was a huge success. Our graduate students are giving talks at national and international conferences and remain competitive despite a difficult job market.
    [Show full text]
  • The Embodied Self, the Pattern Theory of Self, and the Predictive Mind
    fpsyg-09-02270 November 21, 2018 Time: 19:51 # 1 ORIGINAL RESEARCH published: 23 November 2018 doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2018.02270 The Embodied Self, the Pattern Theory of Self, and the Predictive Mind Albert Newen* Institut für Philosophie II, Ruhr-Universität Bochum, Bochum, Germany Do we have to presuppose a self to account for human self-consciousness? If so, how should we characterize the self? These questions are discussed in the context of two alternatives, i.e., the no-self position held by Metzinger(2003, 2009) and the claim that the only self we have to presuppose is a narrative self (Dennett, 1992; Schechtman, 2007; Hardcastle, 2008) which is primarily an abstract entity. In contrast to these theories, I argue that we have to presuppose an embodied self, although this is not a metaphysical substance, nor an entity for which stable necessary and jointly sufficient conditions can be given. Self-consciousness results from an integration of an embodied, basic affective flow with an intentional object (the self as agent or as center of imagination or thought), where this integration remains anchored in an embodied self. This embodied self is a flexible and variable entity, which we can account for only Edited by: with a pattern theory of the self (in line with Gallagher, 2013). Furthermore, I outline Wanja Wiese, how this pattern theory of the self fits into the predictive coding framework, which also Johannes Gutenberg University Mainz, Germany answers the open question whether self-representation is prior to world-representation Reviewed by: or the other way around. The principal organization of a mechanism of building up a self- Philipp Rau, model is such that both types of representations are always activated and developed University of Sheffield, United Kingdom in parallel.
    [Show full text]
  • The Strength of Weak Embodiment International Journal of Psychological Research, Vol
    International Journal of Psychological Research ISSN: 2011-2084 ISSN: 2011-7922 Facultad de Psicología. Universidad de San Buenaventura, Medellín Tirado, Carlos; Khatin-Zadeh, Omid; Gastelum, Melina; Leigh-Jones, Nathan; Marmolejo-Ramos, Fernando The strength of weak embodiment International Journal of Psychological Research, vol. 11, no. 2, 2018, July-December, pp. 77-85 Facultad de Psicología. Universidad de San Buenaventura, Medellín DOI: https://doi.org/10.21500/20112084.3420 Available in: https://www.redalyc.org/articulo.oa?id=299058815009 How to cite Complete issue Scientific Information System Redalyc More information about this article Network of Scientific Journals from Latin America and the Caribbean, Spain and Journal's webpage in redalyc.org Portugal Project academic non-profit, developed under the open access initiative Int. j. psychol. res, Vol. 11 (2) 77-85, 2018 DOI 10.21500/20112084.3420 The strength of weak embodiment Carlos Tirado1*, Omid Khatin-Zadeh2, Melina Gastelum3, Nathan Leigh Jones4, Fernando Marmolejo-Ramos4 Abstract While popular within some cognitive science approaches, the embodiment approach has still found resistance, particularly in light of evidence arguing against strong forms of embodiment. Among other things, the embodiment approach breaks away from the Cartesian ontology of the modulatory system. We claim that the advantages of the embodiment approach are: a) it grounds cognition into modal experience, b) it is harmonious with a materialist philosophy of mind (emergent materialism), and c) it is supported by experimental research in various fields. However, embodiment must still address abstractions, theoretical misunderstandings (representations vs non-representations) and neuroscientific findings that challenge the extension and relevance of sensorimotor properties into cognitive processes.
    [Show full text]
  • Robots As Powerful Allies for the Study of Embodied Cognition from the Bottom Up, in A
    Author version of: Hoffmann, M. & Pfeifer, R. (2018), Robots as powerful allies for the study of embodied cognition from the bottom up, in A. Newen, L. de Bruin; & S. Gallagher, ed., 'The Oxford Handbook 4e Cognition', Oxford University Press, pp. 841-862. DOI - Link to OUP website: https://doi.org/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780198735410.013.45. (version with final formatting can be requested from matej.hoffmann [guess what] fel.cvut.cz) Robots as powerful allies for the study of embodied cognition from the bottom up Matej Hoffmann1,2 & Rolf Pfeifer3 1 - Department of Cybernetics, Faculty of Electrical Engineering, Czech Technical University in Prague, Karlovo Namesti 13, 121 35 Prague 2, Prague, Czech Republic, e-mail: [email protected] 2 - iCub Facility, Istituto Italiano di Tecnologia, Via Morego 30, 16163 Genoa, Italy 3 – Living with robots, [email protected] Abstract A large body of compelling evidence has been accumulated demonstrating that embodiment – the agent’s physical setup, including its shape, materials, sensors and actuators – is constitutive for any form of cognition and as a consequence, models of cognition need to be embodied. In contrast to methods from empirical sciences to study cognition, robots can be freely manipulated and virtually all key variables of their embodiment and control programs can be systematically varied. As such, they provide an extremely powerful tool of investigation. We present a robotic bottom-up or developmental approach, focusing on three stages: (a) low-level behaviors like walking and reflexes, (b) learning regularities in sensorimotor spaces, and (c) human-like cognition. We also show that robotic based research is not only a productive path to deepening our understanding of cognition, but that robots can strongly benefit from human-like cognition in order to become more autonomous, robust, resilient, and safe.
    [Show full text]
  • Embodied Cognition As Grounding for Situatedness and Context in Mathematics Education
    RAFAEL E. NÚÑEZ, LAURIE D. EDWARDS and JOÃO FILIPE MATOS EMBODIED COGNITION AS GROUNDING FOR SITUATEDNESS AND CONTEXT IN MATHEMATICS EDUCATION ABSTRACT. In this paper we analyze, from the perspective of ‘Embodied Cognition’, why learning and cognition are situated and context-dependent. We argue that the nature of situated learning and cognition cannot be fully understood by focusing only on so- cial, cultural and contextual factors. These factors are themselves further situated and made comprehensible by the shared biology and fundamental bodily experiences of human beings. Thus cognition itself is embodied, and the bodily-grounded nature of cognition provides a foundation for social situatedness, entails a reconceptualization of cognition and mathematics itself, and has important consequences for mathematics education. After framing some theoretical notions of embodied cognition in the perspective of modern cognitive science, we analyze a case study – continuity of functions. We use conceptual metaphor theory to show how embodied cognition, while providing grounding for situ- atedness, also gives fruitful results in analyzing the cognitive difficulties underlying the understanding of continuity. 1. INTRODUCTION An important goal of mathematics education is to understand the think- ing involved in doing and learning mathematics. In recent years, it has become widely accepted that the learning and practice of mathematics are not purely intellectual activities, isolated from social, cultural, and contextual factors (Lave, 1988; Collins et al., 1989; Cobb, 1994; Confrey, 1995). Instead, it has been acknowledged that learning and teaching take place, and have always taken place, within embedding social contexts that do not just influence, but essentially determine the kinds of knowledge and practices that are constructed (Lave and Wenger, 1991; Rogoff, 1990; Walkerdine, 1982).
    [Show full text]
  • Comment on Gibbs' ``Social Nature of Embodied Cognition. a View From
    Comment on Gibbs’ “Social nature of Embodied Cognition. A View from the World of Metaphor”: Prerequisites for a Social and Cultural Approach to Cognition Caroline Cance To cite this version: Caroline Cance. Comment on Gibbs’ “Social nature of Embodied Cognition. A View from the World of Metaphor”: Prerequisites for a Social and Cultural Approach to Cognition. Intellectica - La revue de l’Association pour la Recherche sur les sciences de la Cognition (ARCo), Association pour la Recherche sur la Cognition, 2011, 56 (Linguistique cognitive : une exploration critique) (2), pp.321-327. 10.3406/intel.2011.1158. hal-02342950 HAL Id: hal-02342950 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-02342950 Submitted on 1 Nov 2019 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Intellectica. Revue de l'Association pour la Recherche Cognitive Comment on Gibbs’ «Social nature of Embodied Cognition. A View from the World of Metaphor»: Prerequisites for a Social and Cultural Approach to Cognition Caroline Cance Citer ce document / Cite this document : Cance Caroline. Comment on Gibbs’ «Social nature of Embodied Cognition. A View from the World of Metaphor»: Prerequisites for a Social and Cultural Approach to Cognition.
    [Show full text]