Philosophy News 6.Pdf

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Philosophy News 6.Pdf View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Apollo Philosophy at Cambridge Newsletter of the Faculty of Philosophy Issue 6 May 2009 From the Chairman D.H. Mellor Tim Crane When I came up to Clare, there were 70 applicants to read Philosophy. 34 were accepted. That was 1985. job at ICI to work on his PhD on This year 308 applied, but just 56 probability with Mary Hesse in HPS, were successful. This is not a blip. most of his work (and certainly his Since 2002 Philosophy’s application/ best work) has been in metaphysics. acceptance ratio has been way above When I wrote something for the overall University average, and the excellent Festschrift edited by higher still than the average in the Arts. Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra and Why is Philosophy so popular? One Hallvard Lillehammer in 2003 (Real explanation is that the subject is now Metaphysics), I commented that a firmly on the map in schools, as dominant theme of Hugh’s work is a GCSE and A-level option, often as what I called his ‘objectivism’ about a substantial element in the teaching metaphysics. This is his view that the of Religious Studies. Over 23,000 subject-matter of metaphysics is the UK students took Religious Studies or way it is regardless of what anyone Philosophy A-level last year, more than thinks about it. In the philosophy of French and German combined. This is probability, Hugh defended single-case objective chances or propensities; in reflected in the changing intellectual D.H. Mellor formation of our undergraduates: 2/3 the philosophy of time he defended of our current freshers have studied Emeritus Professor D.H. (Hugh) the reality of the temporal series Philosophy in some form at A-level. Mellor, who in 2008 celebrated his ordered in terms of earlier and later, But why Philosophy at Cambridge? 70th birthday, originally studied and argued that the ‘now’ is a kind It doesn’t take much investigation to chemical engineering at Pembroke of illusion. In the philosophy of discover that we offer a Rolls-Royce College. Although he had developed mind, Hugh argued against those education. Nowhere in the world can an interest in philosophy at school in like Thomas Nagel who think that the match it. And it will be even stronger Manchester, Hugh did not formally self is something outside the objective this coming year when Tim Crane study the subject until he visited the order of the world. Our metaphysics and Fraser MacBride join the Faculty. University of Minnesota as a Harkness should not mix facts about the way I know first-hand that they are Fellow. There he took a course on the we represent the phenomena with inspirational teachers. philosophy of science taught by the the phenomena themselves. Mastering facts and figures is one great Vienna Circle empiricist Herbert This is perhaps more of a of the first chores for an incoming Feigl. Feigl began his course by ‘philosophy of philosophy’ than you Chairman, but the principal pleasure announcing that there are three kinds would get from Hugh himself. Hugh is sustaining and developing our of philosophy: ‘the philosophy of tended to be impatient with people dynamic community. The Faculty nothing but’ (needless reductionism), who speculated about the essence of simply couldn’t operate without the ‘the philosophy of something more’ philosophy, thinking this a question goodwill and superb work of its (mysticism and spirituality) and Feigl’s of as little interest as the question extended network of philosophers – own preferred middle way, ‘the of the essence of science. “I’m not Junior and Senior Research Fellows, philosophy of what’s what’. interested in philosophy” he would College Teaching Officers, Affiliated ‘The philosophy of what’s what’ sometimes say “I’m interested in Lecturers, Directors of Studies, not might make a good subtitle for Hugh’s time, causation, probability, the to mention our army of top graduate collected papers. It nicely captures mind …”. Philosophy is its own students. I’ll end this note with a both his unpretentious, down-to-earth thing: there is truth and falsehood in tribute to all of them. attitude towards the subject, and his philosophy; the truth can be attained; respect for the facts revealed to us and our philosophical questions are, Alex Oliver by common sense and by science. on the whole, about exactly what they Chairman, Philosophy Faculty Board Although Hugh started off as a seem to be about: time, causation, philosopher of science, leaving his probability, the mind and so on. Philosophy at Cambridge page 1 May 2009 When I was a research student epistemology, which is not an area the enormous amount he has also in the 1980s, Hugh was one of the of philosophy in which he had much done for the Faculty and the dominant figures in the Cambridge interest. The inaugural is a fine piece, University. He was the prime mover scene. Tireless, tough and energetic but his greatest achievements have in the ambitious redesign of the Raised as a graduate supervisor, he also gave been in metaphysics: in particular in Faculty Building, and he also served as inspiring undergraduate lectures and the philosophy of time (Real Time Pro-Vice Chancellor, managing to do he was a formidable opponent at the was published in 1980, and the heavily at least three times as many things in Moral Sciences Club. Many visiting revised version Real Time II in 1998) a day than most academics. Since he speakers came away from meetings and in causation, where his dense retired, Hugh has taken a well-earned with their papers in severe need of and condensed book The Facts of break from all this kind of thing reconstruction (I know that mine Causation (1995) argued for some (though not from philosophy, publishing did). We coined the Philosophers’ very radical doctrines, for example his philosophical introduction to Lexicon-style definition: hughmellorate the view that causation is not a probability a few years ago) and has (verb, transitive) = to show a visiting relation. These works surely belong been spending more and more time speaker that their paper is completely among the best works of metaphysics on his other great passion, the theatre. worthless. But Hugh did not do this of the late twentieth century. To his students, Hugh is a model to score points; he wanted to get to Hugh’s work in metaphysics fits of how to take philosophy seriously the heart of the matter, without any squarely into a Cambridge tradition without being solemn about it; waffle and without affectation. which is hard to define but easy how to have high standards in the Some found Hugh just too dogmatic to recognise – a tradition which in subject without being crippled by in those days, and even those who the 20th century included Bertrand the enormity of the problems or didn’t would sometimes poke fun at Russell, F.P. Ramsey, C.D. Broad and the weight of the tradition; how to him affectionately. I remember Jeremy R.B. Braithwaite. Hugh has always take account of the known facts Butterfield in a lecture describing a view said how much he owed to Ramsey, without slavish devotion to science; about time as what Hugh believes, and but he also owed a lot to Ramsey’s and how the first and guiding aim of adding: “He won’t tell you he believes friend Braithwaite, who would also philosophers should be to aim to say it. He’ll tell you it’s true. That’s his way become a friend of Hugh’s. He also what is true, without fuss and without of saying he believes it”. And a friend claims as his other influences Hans obscurity. The philosophy of what’s summed up Hugh’s inaugural lecture, Reichenbach, and the Australian what, in other words. The Warrant of Induction in two metaphysics of J.J.C. Smart, D.M. sentences: “How do we know the future Armstrong, Frank Jackson and Tim Crane (PhD 1989), Professor will be like the past? Because it will!”. David Lewis. of Philosophy, UCL. He joins the It was odd, in a way, that Hugh Hugh’s substantial achievements in Faculty as Knightbridge Professor should give his inaugural lecture on philosophy should not over-shadow in September 2009 Philosophy at Cambridge page 2 May 2009 An Oxford Lad at Cambridge Sidney A. Josephs I came up to Trinity in 1957, on a accommodate the expected larger I drove down from London early on Cambridge Bursary for Adult students, than usual audience. Saturday mornings, and spent the day to read Moral Sciences (Neither moral My third year was a shambles. in supervisions with my students, before nor scientific!). I was 24 years old and Lacking a classical background I driving back to my pad in the then had been working on the production had to take the History of Modern poorest part of Chelsea (aptly named line in one of the Oxford car factories. Philosophy option for Part II, which, ‘The World’s End’!). I’m sure that such a I had become interested in philosophy with the exception of David Hume, situation would not be tolerated today! at the age of 16, when I started seeking held little interest for me. This lack For more than ten years after I left logical arguments to support my of interest and motivation, allied to Cambridge, in addition to my full-time empirical atheism. a delightful, but time-consuming and job in publishing, I taught evening I was fortunate, from 1954–56, to emotionally demanding love affair with classes in philosophy for the Extra- attend, in Oxford, a Workers’ Education an undergraduate from Newnham Mural Boards of Cambridge, London Association evening class in philosophy (no, reader, I did not marry her), and, subsequently, Oxford Universities.
Recommended publications
  • Philosophy at Cambridge Newsletter of the Faculty of Philosophy Issue 14 May 2017
    Philosophy at Cambridge Newsletter of the Faculty of Philosophy Issue 14 May 2017 ISSN 2046-9632 From the Chair Tim Crane Many readers will know that the British Government’s periodic assessment of research quality in universities now involves an assessment of the ‘impact’ of this research on the world. In the 2014 exercise, demonstrations of impact were supposed to trace a causal chain from the original research to some effect in the ‘outside world’. It’s hard to know how the ‘impact’ approach would have handled with the achievements of Bernard Williams, one of the Cambridge philosophers we have celebrated this year – in his case with a conference in the Autumn of 2016 on Williams and the Ancients at Newnham College, organised by Nakul Krishna and Sophia Connell (pp. 2 & 3). In numerous ways, Williams had an impact in the public sphere, and his work has profound Onora O’Neill has been named the winner of the 2017 Holberg Prize. Photo: Martin Dijkstra implications for our understanding of politics. But it’s hard to see how one could this way is Casimir Lewy, whose life and Central European University in August. trace any of these effects back through work we celebrated at a delightful event at It’s been an exciting period in the Faculty, a simple chain to one or two ideas. Trinity College in February (p. 6). The list of with many new appointments and Another example of a Cambridge philosophers Lewy taught in his 30 years in unprecedented success in acquiring philosopher who is still a leading public Cambridge contains some of the leading research grants.
    [Show full text]
  • Hacking, Ian (1936-)
    Hacking, Ian (1936-) Reijula, Samuli samuli.reijula@helsinki.fi Theoretical Philosophy / TINT University of Helsinki, Finland Author manuscript version, 26 February 2021 final encyclopedia entry published in Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy∗ Article Summary Ian Hacking (born in 1936, Vancouver, British Columbia) is most well-known for his work in the philosophy of the natural and social sciences, but his contributions to philosophy are broad, spanning many areas and traditions. In his detailed case studies of the development of probabilistic and statistical reasoning, Hacking pioneered the naturalistic approach in the philosophy of science. Hacking’s research on social constructionism, transient mental illnesses and the looping effect of the human kinds make use of historical materials to shed light on how developments in the social, medical, and behavioral sciences have shaped our contemporary conceptions of identity and agency. Hacking’s other contributions to philosophy include his work on the philosophy of mathematics (Hacking 2014), philosophy of statistics, philosophy of logic, inductive logic (Hacking 1965; 1979; 2001) and natural kinds (Hacking 1991, 2007a). ∗https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/biographical/hacking-ian-1936/v-1 1 Hacking, Ian (1936-) 1 Naturalism in the philosophy of science Ian Hacking completed his first degree, a BA in mathematics and physics, at the University of British Columbia in 1956. He earned his PhD from Cambridge, where he studied under the direction of Casimir Lewy, a former student of Ludwig Wittgenstein (De Sousa 1992; Vagelli 2014). After holding various positions both in the US and in Europe, in 1982 he was granted a professorship at the University of Toronto.
    [Show full text]
  • WHAT MATHEMATICS HAS DONE to SOME and ONLY SOME PHILOSOPHERS Ian Hacking
    Hacking page 1 WHAT MATHEMATICS HAS DONE TO SOME AND ONLY SOME PHILOSOPHERS Ian Hacking 1 HOW IS PURE MATHEMATICS POSSIBLE? 2 JOHN STUART MILL 3 PLATO 4 LEIBNIZ 5 THE TERMS OF ART 6 DESCARTES 7 LAKATOS 8 WITTGENSTEIN 1 HOW IS PURE MATHEMATICS POSSIBLE? According to Bertrand Russell, ‘the question which Kant put at the beginning of his philosophy, namely “How is pure mathematics possible?” is an interesting and difficult one, to which every philosophy which is not purely sceptical must find an answer’.1 Russell exaggerated. Many philosophies that are not purely sceptical have had no interest in Kant’s question. It never even occurred to them, much less struck them as important. I shall not be invidious, but we quickly think of canonical Western philosophers of all periods who have not troubled themselves with mathematics at all. Hence the ‘some and only some’ of my title. But the spirit of Russell’s remark is right. A great many of the philosophers whom we still read have been deeply impressed by mathematics, and have gone so far as to tailor much of their philosophy to their vision of mathematical knowledge, mathematical reality, or, what I think is crucial, mathematical proof. Why do so many philosophies try to answer Kant’s question? And, incidentally, why do a great many not address it? We need not distinguish between Russell’s talk of philosophies and individual philosophers, so long as we examine only a few famous philosophers each of whom has defined a philosophy. I shall employ the very opposite of Myles Burnyeats’ skillful scholarship, for I am less concerned with philosophical texts or doctrines than with the broader question, of why a philosopher should have become obsessed by mathematics as a source of philosophical inspiration.
    [Show full text]
  • The Common Sense Philosophy of G. E. Moore
    Loyola University Chicago Loyola eCommons Master's Theses Theses and Dissertations 1970 The Common Sense Philosophy of G. E. Moore Mark A. Phillips Loyola University Chicago Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Phillips, Mark A., "The Common Sense Philosophy of G. E. Moore" (1970). Master's Theses. 2480. https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses/2480 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Master's Theses by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Copyright © Mark A. Phillips THE COMMON SENSE PHII1080J?Iff OF G. E. MOORE by Mark A. J?hillips A Thesis Submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate School of Loyola University in Partial Fulfillmem:1-'0f· the Requirements for the Degree'' of. ' Master of Philosophy · · . ·" .(., r· \,! June 1970 PREJAOE The primary purpose of this thesis is to clarify the notion ot common sense in the philosophy of G. E. Moore. As such, it will serve as no more than a propaedeutic tor evaluating whether a common sense philosophy is viable. The scope of dis­ cussion is admittedly JD.70pic: there is no presentation of earlier common sense philosophies, nor criticisms of such philosophies. ~e only excuse tor this omission is that it is impossible thor­ ~ughly to discuss even the twentieth-century material in a short work.
    [Show full text]
  • The Wittgenstein Lectures-2019 Update Cambria
    Updated version: September 2019 James C. Klagge Public and Private Occasions [[p. 331]] Chapter 3: The Wittgenstein Lectures Just as we have a catalogue of Wittgenstein’s papers, it would be useful to have a guide to Wittgenstein’s lectures. It would be useful to know when he gave lectures, where and to whom, and on what topics, and more specifically what he said. Since his lectures, unlike his papers, have no enduring existence, they are harder to study. Nevertheless, we have evidence about his lectures—comments he made in letters, notes he made in preparation, recollections and notes from his listeners and friends, official records and minutes, diary entries, and so forth. Though Wittgenstein nearly always lectured extemporaneously, the lectures were preceded by enormous preparation, and Wittgenstein took them very seriously. As Norman Malcolm has reported (1984, p. 48), Wittgenstein “said that he had always regarded his lectures as a form of publication.” And Casimir Lewy recalled: “Wittgenstein once said to me that ‘to publish’ means ‘to make public’, and that therefore lecturing is a form of publication” (1976, p. xi). Yorick Smythies, who probably attended more of Wittgenstein’s lectures than any other student, wrote the following in a draft of an introduction to a planned publication of Wittgenstein’s lectures (Smythies 2017, xi): Re-reading [these notes], now, after thirty years, I find them more natural, fluent, simple, continuous, expressive, than the remarks contained in Wittgenstein’s so-far published writings. While he was lecturing, he was not able to delete what had been said, or to give to trains of thought more tightness than they were showing themselves to have.
    [Show full text]
  • Almagest Undergraduate Journal for History and Philosophy of Science Copyright C 2019 Almagest Undergraduate Journal for History and Philoso- Phy of Science
    Almagest Issue 5, 2019 Almagest Undergraduate Journal for History and Philosophy of Science Copyright c 2019 Almagest Undergraduate Journal for History and Philoso- phy of Science Published by Almagest www.almagestjournal.com Cover photo taken from the U.S. National Archives, item identifier 22122886. Citation: Department of Energy. Lawrence Berkeley National Laboratory. Public Affairs Department. Strategic Resources Office. Photography Services. 2012. LATEXtemplate created by Slava Lyubchich and Shashi Kumar https://www.overleaf.com/latex/templates/krantz-book-template/ vfrsjggghjcd and licensed under the Creative Commons CC BY 4.0. See the License for the specific language governing permissions and lim- itations under the License. You may obtain a copy of the License at https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/. The rights to each ar- ticle remain with the respective author. First printing, November 2019 We are indebted to our sponsors, without whom this publication would not be possible. The creation of this issue was supported by the History and Philos- ophy of Science Undergraduate Society, The Institute for History and Philos- ophy of Science and Technology, Victoria College, St. Michael's College, and the Arts and Science Student Union. If you are interested in supporting future issues of Almagest, please contact us at [email protected]. Foreword Founded in 2014, the Almagest Undergraduate Journal for History and Phi- losophy of Science is a student-run, peer-reviewed academic journal which features high-quality original research from students. Created in close connec- tion with the University of Toronto's HPS Undergraduate Society (HPSUS), and based at the Institute for History and Philosophy of Science and Tech- nology (IHPST), Almagest is proud to have been able to present students in Toronto with a platform to refine and publish their own creative work.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy at Cambridge Newsletter of the Faculty of Philosophy
    Philosophy at Cambridge Newsletter of the Faculty of Philosophy Issue 4 May 2007 The Human Touch From the Chair Michael Frayn A few facts to welcome you to Most of the books I’ve written have book takes its rise from what the fourth issue of the Faculty’s been fiction. The Human Touch, I first learned and discussed there, Newsletter. though, is something else. It’s an and I remain immensely indebted In 1953 there were 13 candidates exploration of what seems to me to to the people who taught me for Part II of the Moral Sciences be the central oddity of the universe (especially to Jonathan Bennett, my Tripos (among them Pat Crossman, we live in, and of our relations with supervisor in my last year). Some as she tells us on p.6). In 1957 there it. The oddity is an obvious one — slight acquaintance with the subject, were 19 (among them Michael Frayn, so obvious that you might go though, makes me wary of claiming who writes opposite about how the through a whole lifetime without to be practising it (particularly in a subject gripped him). By 1968 (when even registering it, just as you might publication issued by my old Faculty the present author sat Part II) there without ever consciously taking in itself). I know enough to understand were 24, and in 2006 the number was the staggering complexity of what that professional philosophy these 56. And in the 1950s the Faculty had you see when you look at the back days is a very specialised and often a mere handful of graduate students.
    [Show full text]
  • From the Archives
    Nordic Wittgenstein Review 2 (2013) FROM THE ARCHIVES David Stern, Gabriel Citron and Brian Rogers Moore’s Notes on Wittgenstein’s Lectures, Cambridge 1930-1933: Text, Context, and Content 1. Context: The middle Wittgenstein The co-authors of this paper are currently editing G. E. Moore’s notes of Wittgenstein’s Cambridge lectures, 1930-1933, for a book to be published by Cambridge University Press. In this paper we examine the importance of Wittgenstein’s 1930-33 lectures in the context of the development of his philosophy more generally, and in the context of contemporary scholarly debates about how best to understand Wittgenstein’s later thought; we describe the text of Moore’s notes, explaining their unique value as records of Wittgenstein’s 1930-33 lectures; we briefly review the varied and wide-ranging content of the lectures; we discuss Moore’s role in the lectures themselves and in responding to their content; and finally, we outline the principal editorial challenges that these materials present, and provide a brief outline of our editorial project. In 1929, Wittgenstein returned to Cambridge and philosophical writing, criticising his own earlier work and turning his focus to how language is used in ordinary life. These years were a time of transition between his early and his later work, and are of great 161 Stern & Citron & Rogers BY-NC-SA interest for anyone who wants to understand the development of his thought. Wittgenstein’s writings and lectures during the first half of the 1930s play a crucial role in any interpretation of the relationship between the Tractatus and the Philosophical Investigations.
    [Show full text]
  • Casimir Lewy: Themes & Work
    Casimir Lewy: Themes & Work Simon Blackburn I WISH to make some remarks on Mr. A. E. Duncan-Jones's paper called " Does Philosophy analyse Common Sense ? " which was read before the Joint Session of the Aristotelian Society and the Mind Association at Bristol, 1937, and published in the I6th Supplementary Volume of the Aristotelian Society. I. Mr. Duncan-Jones starts with the remark (which seems to me to be of some importance) that " all philosophical analyses and all accounts of the process of analysing, have a certain general pattern in common " (p. 140). All analyses attempt " either to reduce the number of objects in the world or the number of words in our vocabulary ”. I am not at all clear as to what is meant by this. I am not at all clear how a philosopher can by his philosophical activities " reduce the number of objects in the world ". Whatever does this mean? Wisdom says (op. cit. p. 463) that " statements about pro- positions and characteristics such as ' He asserted the proposition that Africa is hot ', ' She is chic ', can be turned into statements about words ' He uttered the sentence. " Africa is hot " ', ' She is what the French call " chic " ', if, and only if the verbal statements are so used that we say that a man understands them only if he understands not merely the expression ' the sentence " Africa is hot "' but also understands that sentence and similarly understands the word ' chic’ Some notes on assertion (Analysis 1939) I take Mr. Russell's argument to be an instance of a certain kind of" senseless lament."' The genus to which Mr.
    [Show full text]
  • Return to an Old Refrain: What Proof Does to Concepts
    Return to an Old Refrain: What Proof Does to Concepts Ian Hacking, Toronto Many texts could illustrate my subject. Here is one, almost at random. It is the third and last paragraph in one of the numbered remarks in the Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics: One would like to say: the proof changes the grammar of our language, changes our concepts. It makes new connexions, and it creates the concept of these connexions. (It does not establish that they are there; they do not exist until it makes them.) (RFM III, §31.1) For a tiny bit of context, the previous remark, §30, ended by saying, ‘I want to say that the must corresponds to a track which I lay down in lan- guage.’ Why might one want to say these things? I shall suggest one possi- ble reason. I shall couch my answer in terms of what I have read in Witt- genstein, but I am not a scholar aiming at a correct interpretation of his texts. In addition, although this essay is about proof, I have made the tac- tical decision, on grounds of brevity, to pass by Wittgenstein’s remarks about perspicuous or surveyable proofs. They are of fundamental impor- tance to his philosophical thinking about mathematics. The omission here means most of what follows is in need of qualification in this respect. I also omit his important insistence on the motley of techniques of proof.2 (RFM III, § 46, 48.) 1 Throughout I shall use the translation and numbering of the third edition, Oxford: Blackwell, 1978.
    [Show full text]
  • 5 Ludwig Wittgenstein (1889–1951)
    5 Ludwig Wittgenstein (1889–1951) P. M. S. HACKER Background Ludwig Josef Johann Wittgenstein dominates the history of twentieth-century analytic philosophy somewhat as Picasso dominates the history of twentieth-century art. He did not so much create a “school,” but rather changed the philosophical landscape – not once, but twice. And his successors, within the broad stream of analytic philoso- phy, whether they followed the paths he pioneered or not, had to reorient themselves by reference to new landmarks consequent upon his work. He completed two diamet- rically opposed philosophical masterpieces, the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (1921) and the Philosophical Investigations (1953). Each gave rise to distinct phases in the history of the analytic movement. The Tractatus was a source of Cambridge analysis of the interwar years, and the main source of the logical positivism of the Vienna Circle. The Investigations was a primary inspiration for the form of analytic philosophy that flourished in the quarter of a century after the end of the Second World War, with its center at Oxford and its circumference everywhere in the English-speaking world and beyond. He taught at Cambridge from 1930 until his premature retirement in 1947. Many of his pupils became leading figures in the next generation of philosophers, trans- mitting his ideas to their students.1 Wittgenstein’s central preoccupations at the beginning of his philosophical career were with the nature of thought and linguistic representation, of logic and necessity, and of philosophy itself. These themes continue in his later philosophy, from 1929 onwards, although philosophy of mathematics occupied him intensively until 1944 and philosophy of psychology increasingly dominated his thought from the late 1930s until his death.
    [Show full text]
  • Download Download
    Nordic Wittgenstein Review 8 (1-2) 2019 | pp. 11-82 | DOI 10.15845/nwr.v8i0.3550 INVITED PAPER James C. Klagge [email protected] The Wittgenstein Lectures, Revisited Abstract This essay surveys what is known about Wittgenstein’s philosophical lectures, covering the Cambridge Moral Sciences Club, Cambridge University courses, and other lecture venues. Information provided includes titles, dates, locations, attendees and content, to the extent these are known. Sometimes content is simply referred to by citations of other publications. When it is relatively brief or difficult to access, content is occasionally provided directly. The original survey, published in 2003, is here updated, corrected and expanded. Preface In 2003 I published a survey of Wittgenstein’s lectures in Public and Private Occasions. Much has been learned about his lectures since then. This paper revisits the earlier survey and provides additional material and corrections, which amount to over 25%. In case it is useful, I have provided interlinear pagination from the original publication. If additional material or corrections come to light, I will update the paper as needed on my website: jamesklagge.net 11 James Klagge CC-BY THE LECTURES [[p. 331]] Just as we have a catalogue of Wittgenstein’s papers, it would be useful to have a guide to Wittgenstein’s lectures. It would be useful to know when he gave lectures, where and to whom, and on what topics, and more specifically what he said. Since his lectures, unlike his papers, have no enduring existence, they are harder to study. Nevertheless, we have evidence about his lectures—comments he made in letters, notes he made in preparation, recollections and notes from his listeners and friends, official records and minutes, diary entries, and so forth.
    [Show full text]