Philosophy at Cambridge Newsletter of the Faculty of Philosophy Issue 14 May 2017

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Philosophy at Cambridge Newsletter of the Faculty of Philosophy Issue 14 May 2017 Philosophy at Cambridge Newsletter of the Faculty of Philosophy Issue 14 May 2017 ISSN 2046-9632 From the Chair Tim Crane Many readers will know that the British Government’s periodic assessment of research quality in universities now involves an assessment of the ‘impact’ of this research on the world. In the 2014 exercise, demonstrations of impact were supposed to trace a causal chain from the original research to some effect in the ‘outside world’. It’s hard to know how the ‘impact’ approach would have handled with the achievements of Bernard Williams, one of the Cambridge philosophers we have celebrated this year – in his case with a conference in the Autumn of 2016 on Williams and the Ancients at Newnham College, organised by Nakul Krishna and Sophia Connell (pp. 2 & 3). In numerous ways, Williams had an impact in the public sphere, and his work has profound Onora O’Neill has been named the winner of the 2017 Holberg Prize. Photo: Martin Dijkstra implications for our understanding of politics. But it’s hard to see how one could this way is Casimir Lewy, whose life and Central European University in August. trace any of these effects back through work we celebrated at a delightful event at It’s been an exciting period in the Faculty, a simple chain to one or two ideas. Trinity College in February (p. 6). The list of with many new appointments and Another example of a Cambridge philosophers Lewy taught in his 30 years in unprecedented success in acquiring philosopher who is still a leading public Cambridge contains some of the leading research grants. It has been an honour figure is Onora O’Neill, who has made philosophers of the last 50 years; and it is to work in this great university, with its significant contributions in public life, as clear that they owed a vast amount to him. rich tradition in philosophy, stimulating well as developing a distinctive version Surely every philosopher wants their colleagues and wonderful and talented of Kantian moral philosophy. How exactly work to have impact of some kind – the students. The Faculty is very fortunate we should trace the exact connections only question is what this means. The truth to have Rae Langton as my successor between her work in ethics and her work of the matter seems to be that it is hard to as Knightbridge Professor and Chair of on, say, the Leveson Inquiry, is a difficult predict or control which ideas have which the Faculty from 2017. As readers of task, and not obviously the best way specific effects, both inside and outside this newsletter will know, Rae came to to think about her achievements. the academic context. By all accounts, the Cambridge in 2013 after teaching at MIT, Fortunately, this did not bother the forthcoming assessment exercise (in 2021) Edinburgh, Sheffield and Monash. She committee in Norway who awarded her is likely to take a more nuanced approach works on ethics, feminism, Kant, philosophy the prestigious Holberg Prize earlier this to impact. of language, metaphysics and many year. We congratulate Onora on this Speaking personally, I do not expect to other things too. Appointing Rae to the wonderful achievement. be around in Cambridge in 2021, though. Knightbridge Chair – the first woman to One way in which a philosopher can Not only is this my last newsletter as Faculty be appointed to this ancient professorship clearly and indisputably have impact, Chair (a position I have occupied for five – also gives us the opportunity, we hope, though, is through their students. Someone years and a bit), it is also my last term at to expand and enrich the Faculty by making whose lasting legacy can be measured in Cambridge – I move to take up a job at the more junior appointments. Watch this space. Philosophy at Cambridge page 1 May 2017 Togas and Olives Nakul Krishna “The legacy of Greece to Western philosophy is Western philosophy.” The audacious first line – of Bernard Williams’ essay, ‘The Legacy of Greek Philosophy’, strikes a characteristic note: considered, unapologetic, magisterial. And yet, as the reader discovers a few sentences in, the aphoristic punchiness is not achieved through exaggeration. Williams goes on to describe, in an account succinct but rich in telling detail, the relation between Greek and later Western philosophy so that his metaphor of a legacy proves to have a precision that A.N. Whitehead’s better- known remark about Western philosophy as “a series of footnotes to Plato” lacks. Legacies can be squandered, but they can also be improved upon, and Williams – a modern philosopher through and through – never looked to the Greeks as sages. Educated at Oxford in the late 1940s in what he once described as “the Detail from The Remorse of Orestes by William-Adolphe Bouguereau. Photo: Wikimedia Commons heyday of analytic confidence”, Williams absorbed an approach to the study of modern world was lamentably Socratic be a different and more sophisticated thing, Greek philosophical texts informed by in its “heightened reflectiveness, self- and it will represent an achievement.” ‘triumphant anachronism’. The view that consciousness, and inwardness”, and A philosopher writing in the late 20th “we should approach the works of Plato these things, Nietzsche had thought, century, Williams assured his Berkeley as though they had appeared in last “it was ... one of the charms, and indeed the audiences that he did not wish to ally month’s issue of Mind” was, of course, power, of the Greeks to have done without.” himself “with those who suspect that the theoretically indefensible. Indeed it was When Williams was invited in the early closing scenes of the Eumenides already barely intelligible; for one thing, the works 1990s to deliver the prestigious Sather display a dangerous weakening toward of Plato could not have made it past the Lectures at the University of California, liberalism.” (This is the scene where the referees. But oddly enough, as Williams Berkeley – later published as Shame and frenzied Furies, figures of vengeance, was the first to admit, the method worked, Necessity (1993) – he had a good deal to are transformed into guardians of justice, producing a generation of philologically say about the Greek philosopher. But his with courts and procedures to go with and philosophically acute scholars real interest was in overturning, with every their new role.) The point wasn’t to do who refused to patronise the texts and argumentative and rhetorical resource away with the achievements of the took them seriously as articulating available to him, a certain ‘Whiggish’ modern world in thought and politics arguments that we might accept or interpretation of history. This interpretation in exchange for some slave-owning, reject on their merits. saw the modern world and its philosophy toga-wearing, olive-eating and largely In the 1970s, Williams’ thinking about as equipped with a set of notions – invented vision of a classical past. The the Greeks underwent a deep shift, in part morality, responsibility and ‘the will’ among point was to give us and our institutions the consequence of his own, increasingly others – that the Greeks had lacked and a more truthful self-understanding, and pessimistic, ideas about what philosophy been the worse off for lacking. learning to see the Greeks aright might could do, in part the consequence of his Williams denied this: the Greeks had all be one way to do that. growing fascination with Nietzsche. The the notions they, or we, needed. A simpler In his writings in the 1990s, Williams Greeks, Nietzsche had more than once philosophy of action, using only the terms came to articulate with a startling remarked, “were superficial – out of available to Homer, could make all the directness the pessimistic reflections profundity”. Nietzsche was not talking necessary distinctions without muddying towards which he had been reaching in of the respectable philosophical Greeks the waters with concerns derived from all his previous work: “human beings are to who took their cue from Socrates and that unfortunate institution, morality some degree a mess”. Given our history took virtue and wisdom as the way to (or, as Williams preferred to say, ‘the – our natural, evolutionary, history as well happiness. The Greeks he most respected morality system’). But one couldn’t as that of the last two or three thousand were the characters and creators of tragedy, regain the pre-Socratic Greeks’ profound years of civilization – “no form of life is history and rhetoric, even the teachers of superficiality just by trying. “That is not likely to prove entirely satisfactory, either rhetoric Socrates maligned as ‘sophists’. possible for us,” wrote Williams, “after so individually or socially”. We will always want For Nietzsche, as Williams put it, the much history: any such attitude for us will more things than we can have, and this is Philosophy at Cambridge page 2 May 2017 not just a contingent – if unfortunate – how far the existence of a worthwhile life truth about the world, but a necessary for some people involves the imposition truth about beings like us, cursed with of suffering on others.” desires and aspirations that cannot by The ‘we’ is deliberately provocative. It is their nature be jointly satisfied. And to clear enough what the right-on thing to say the extent that we might simplify our is, but to what extent are those convictions desires so that they can be satisfied, our reflected in the lives and lifestyles of those new existence may not be one we can of us living, and sometimes flourishing, recognise as an improvement. under capitalism? What would it be like Life, in other words, will always be a for us to try to live in ways that imposed disappointment to us.
Recommended publications
  • Holberg Prize Reception Speech Bruno Latour, Sciences Po, Paris Speech Given for the Reception of the Holberg Prize, 5Th of June 2013, Bergen, Norway
    Holberg Prize reception speech Bruno Latour, Sciences Po, Paris Speech given for the reception of the Holberg Prize, 5th of June 2013, Bergen, Norway. Minister, Excellency, Officers of the Ludwig Holberg Memorial Fund, Ladies and gentlemen, colleagues, friends and family. There is something slightly reassuring in having people like me receiving an award such as the one you have decided to bestow on my work tonight. Through sheer labour, ordinary people may achieve something that no one could have predicted from the way their mind works or from their personality. Having worried all my life about the fact that a white provincial male of bourgeois extraction and of limited intellectual skills could not possibly be the real target of the thoughts that had traversed his desk since he was sixteen, I am now totally reassured: everyone is able to tackle problems of vastly disproportionate size and even have the good fortune, if not to solve them, at least to give them a more reasonable shape. Reassured that it is not me but those slightly reshaped problems that are rewarded tonight, it is to them that I may now safely turn. The first problem is that of the exact nature of the intellectual practices themselves. To think productively is often to make positive use of one’s own limitation. Sometimes, ignorance is bliss. There is no doubt that, had I had a 129-Holberg reception speech 2 stronger power of abstraction or even the love for mathematics of Ian Hacking, my colleague and predecessor at this very lectern, I would never have been so totally obsessed by the difficulties of thinking, of gathering any piece of data, of convincing anyone of the smallest part of a proof; thus, I would never have put so much stress on the materiality of writing and visualizing.
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae
    CURRICULUM VITAE Kwame Anthony Akroma-Ampim Kusi APPIAH Laurance S. Rockefeller University Professor of Philosophy and the University Center for Human Values University Center for Human Values Louis Marx Hall Princeton University Princeton, NJ 08544-1006 609-258-4289 Fax: 609-258-1502 Department of Philosophy 1879 Hall Princeton University Princeton, NJ 08544-1006 609-258-4798 Fax: 609-258-2729 WEBSITE: http://www.appiah.net E-MAIL: [email protected], [email protected] EFAX: 413-208-0985 LITERARY AGENT: Lynn Nesbit Janklow & Nesbit Associates 445 Park Ave New York, NY 10022 212-421-1700 Fax: 212-980-3671 http://www.janklowandnesbit.com/ LECTURE AGENT: David Lavin The Lavin Agency 222 Third Street, Ste. 1130 Cambridge, MA 02142 800-762-4234 Fax: 617-225-7875 http://www.thelavinagency.com/ CITIZENSHIP: United States DATE OF BIRTH: 8 May 1954 EDUCATION Clare College, Cambridge University, 1972-75 Exhibition, Medical Sciences 1972 First Class Honours (Part I b) 1974 Exhibition, Philosophy 1974 First Class Honours (Part II) 1975 BA (Honours), Philosophy 1975 MA 1980 1976-81 PhD, Philosophy 1982 (Thesis: Conditions for Conditionals) LANGUAGES: Asante-Twi, English, French, German, Latin Kwame Anthony Appiah CV 2 EMPLOYMENT Princeton Laurance S. Rockefeller University Professor of Philosophy and the University Center for Human Values July 2002- Associated Fields: African-American Studies (2002-), Comparative Literature (2005-), Politics (2006-), Program in Translation and Intercultural Communication (2007-) Bacon-Kilkenny Visiting Professor, Fordham University School of Law Fall 2008 Phi Beta Kappa-Romanell Professor, 2008-2009 Harvard Charles H. Carswell Professor of Afro-American Studies and of Philosophy July 1999-July 2002 Professor of Afro-American Studies and Philosophy July 1991-July 1999 Head Tutor, Afro-American Studies July 1991-July 2001 Acting Director of Graduate Studies, Philosophy Spring Semester 1991 Chair, Committee on African Studies 1995-2001 Associate Director, Black Fiction Project 1991-96 Member of the Board of the W.
    [Show full text]
  • Postmodernism and Classical Chinese Philosophy
    Cultural and Religious Studies, March 2016, Vol. 4, No. 3, 194-203 doi: 10.17265/2328-2177/2016.03.005 D DAVID PUBLISHING Postmodernism and Classical Chinese Philosophy Yong-Kang Wei University of Texas (RGV), Texas, USA While over two thousand years apart, Western postmodernism and ancient Chinese philosophy share some extraordinary similarities, especially epistemology wise. For example, they both recognize the role of language in constructing, and limiting, knowledge and reality. This is because thinkers of different cultures and geographical regions, and of different historical periods, can possibly come up with similar philosophical conclusions when addressing what is commonly known as the “human condition”. The paper will discuss, in general terms, some of the philosophical similarities between postmodernism and classical Chinese philosophy; it will also take a close look at three concepts in Chinese philosophy that register strong affinity with Western postmodernism: namely, change, dialectic, and relativism. Keywords: postmodernism, modernism, classical Chinese philosophy Introduction Postmodernism, as a philosophical concept, was first introduced in China by Fredric R. Jameson in 1985, when he was lecturing on “postmodernism” and “cultural theory” at Peking University (Wang, 2008). So readers may immediately sense a chronological incongruity between postmodernism and classical Chinese philosophy. However, it is quite possible, I would argue, that thinkers of different cultures and geographical regions, and of different historical periods, can come up with similar conclusions when addressing what is commonly known as the “human condition”. For example, Confucius’ “己所不欲,勿施于人” (Don’t do things to others that you don’t want done to yourself) is echoed, almost identically, in the Christian Bible, and Protagoras’ (490-420 B.C.) paradox rings very similar to the “two-argument” theory (两可论) of Deng Xi1 (邓 析, 545-501 B.C.), a Chinese philosopher of the Spring and Autumn Period.
    [Show full text]
  • Thinking About Liberty in Dark Times” Contents
    The Holberg Prize Seminar 2004, Holberg Prize Laureate Professor Julia Kristeva ”Thinking about liberty in dark times” Contents Award announcement 4 About the Ludvig Holberg Memorial Fund 5 Greetings from the Ludvig Holberg Memorial Fund 6 In honour of Julia Kristeva 7 Julia Kristeva’s acceptance speech at the state banquet on 3 December 2004 9 Kelly Oliver: In Honor of Julia Kristeva, Holberg Prize Laureate 13 Julia Kristeva: Thinking about liberty in dark times 20 Sara Beardsworth: Commentary: Freedom and Ethical Value 38 John Fletcher: The Semiotic and the Other: a response to Julia Kristeva 42 Atle Kittang: Liberty, Freedom, the Imaginary 50 Iréne Matthis: The concept of working through 54 Award announcement About the Ludvig Holberg Memorial Fund “The recipient of the Holberg International Memorial Prize for 2004 is The Ludvig Holberg Memorial Fund was established by the Norwegian Government Professor Julia Kristeva, Director of the Institute for the Study of Texts and for the purpose of annually awarding the Holberg International Memorial Prize for Documents at the University of Paris 7 - Denis Diderot. outstanding scholarly work in the fields of the arts and humanities, social sciences, law or theology. The prize is worth NOK 4. 5 million (about 520,000 Euro) and was In her path breaking book La Révolution du langage poétique (1974; Revolution in awarded for the first time on 3 December 2004 to Professor Julia Kristeva. Poetic Language, 1985) Julia Kristeva first advanced the theory that the process of signification in language is constituted by two different but interacting elements, the The Holberg Prize aims to increase society’s awareness of the value of research in symbolic and the semiotic, thus bringing the living body back into language.
    [Show full text]
  • Storytelling
    History and Theory 50 (May 2011), 203-209 © Wesleyan University 2011 ISSN: 0018-2656 FORUM: HOLBERG PRIZE SYMPOSIUM DOING DECENTERED HISTORY 2. STORYTELLING JOAN W. SCOTT ABSTRACT Natalie Davis is a quintessential storyteller in the way theorized by Walter Benjamin, Hannah Arendt, and Michel de Certeau. Her work decenters history not simply because it grants agency and so historical visibility to those who have been hidden from history or left on its margins, but also because her stories reveal the complexities of human experi- ence and so challenge the received categories with which we are accustomed to thinking about the world. Keywords: storytelling, narrative, history, Benjamin, Arendt, Certeau, Geertz “Le passé est une histoire que l’on conte.” —Natalie Zemon Davis1 It is a commonplace that historians are storytellers. So much so that the Gradu- ate Record Exam (the test taken by candidates for various university graduate programs in the United States) uses as one of its “issue questions” the following: “When we concern ourselves with the study of history, we become storytellers. Because we can never know the past directly but must construct it by interpreting evidence, exploring history is more of a creative enterprise than it is an objective pursuit. All historians are storytellers.”2 The question sets up a familiar opposition: between facts and interpretation, objective science and artistic creativity, reality and fiction. The best answers will try to negotiate some balance between these contradictory categories, arguing, for example, that interpretation is necessarily reined in by evidence, or that cre- ativity is also an attribute of science.
    [Show full text]
  • The Ancients and the Postmoderns. Fredric Jameson. London & New York: Verso Press, 2015
    The Ancients and the Postmoderns. Fredric Jameson. London & New York: Verso Press, 2015. Pp. 306 (cloth). Reviewed by Julian Murphet, University of New South Wales Late Jameson, a nebulous authorial entity I date from the publication of Brecht and Method (1998), has now eclipsed in sheer bulk and volume those other, older Jamesons (the mighty young scholar-Turk who wrote the mesmerizing sequence from Sartre (1961) to the essays collected in the two-volume Ideologies of Theory (1988); and the august theorist of the postmodern who spanned the period from the Adorno book, Late Marxism (1990), through to the assembled musings of The Cultural Turn (1998)—who to this day remain better known and more often cited than this extraordinarily prolific elder Jameson. One reason for that is that it has been difficult to reduce the later Jameson to anything like a consistent argumentative claim or position. If the early Jameson had stood for “taking Continental Theory seriously” and “always historicizing,” and the mid-career Jameson had inveigled us to “scan the cultural signs of the present for evidence of their underlying economic logic,” this later Jameson remains a more opaque thinker, though there is evidence of some persistent themes and motifs, and one underlying material fact. This latter—that “late Jameson” is exclusively a property of Verso Press, and has therefore been curated by a singular editorial agenda—bears some consideration. For whereas the other Jamesons built their formidable reputations in the established University presses (Princeton, Cornell, Yale, California, Duke, Indiana, Columbia), the likely absence of any rigorous process of academic peer review in the later Jameson volumes signals a retreat from those testing (and often exasperating) trials that mark lesser careers in the business.
    [Show full text]
  • 1. Decentering History 199 the Death Penalty Was Possible in Cases of Murder and a Heinous Crime Like Witch- Craft, but Was by No Means Regularly Pronounced
    History and Theory 50 (May 2011), 188-202 © Wesleyan University 2011 ISSN: 0018-2656 FORUM: HOLBERG PRIZE SYMPOSIUM DOING DECENTERED HISTORY 1. DECENTERING HISTORY: LOCAL STORIES AND CULTURAL CROSSINGS IN A GLOBAL WORLD NATALIE ZEMON DAVIS ABSTRACT This essay was first presented at the 2010 Ludwig Holberg Prize Symposium in Bergen, Norway, where I, as the prize recipient, was asked to describe my work and its import for our period of globalization. The essay first traces the interconnected processes of “decen- tering” history in Western historiography in the half century after World War II: the move to working people and “subaltern classes”; to women and gender; to communities defined by ethnicity and race; to the study of non-Western histories and world or global history, in which the European trajectory is only one of several models. Can the historian hold onto the subjects of “decentered” social and cultural history, often local and full of concrete detail, and still address the perspectives of global history? To suggest an answer to this question, I describe my own decentering path from work on sixteenth-century artisans in the 1950s to recent research on non-European figures such as the Muslim “Leo Africanus” (Hasan al-Wazzan). I then offer two examples in which concrete cases can serve a global perspective. One is a comparison of the literary careers of Ibn Khaldun and Christine de Pizan in the scribal cultures on either side of the Mediterranean in the late fourteenth and early fifteenth centuries. The other is the transmission and transformation of practices of divination, healing, and detection from Africa to the slave communities of Suriname in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries.
    [Show full text]
  • “Religion in the Public Sphere” This Publication Is a Seminar Report from the Holberg Prize Seminar 2005
    The Holberg Prize Seminar 2005, Holberg Prize Laureate Professor Jürgen Habermas: “Religion in the Public Sphere” This publication is a seminar report from the Holberg Prize Seminar 2005 The main lecture at the seminar was held by the Holberg International Memorial Prize laureate 2005 Professor Jürgen Habermas. In addition to the main lecture four scholars were invited to give a lecture which theme was in relation to the topic of Jürgen Habermas’s lecture. These lectures had a timeframe of 30 minutes. All of the main lectures were commented by additional scholars, the comments had a timeframe of 10 minutes. The scholars were asked to contribute their papers as they where given at the seminar. Contents Award Announcement 4 About the Ludvig Holberg Memorial Fund 5 Greetings from the Ludvig Holberg Memorial Fund 6 Jürgen Habermas’s speech at the award seremony 30 November 2005 8 Jürgen Habermas: Religion in the public sphere. 10 Arne Johan Vetlesen: Faith in religion. Habermas’s post-secular search for Meaning and Solidarity. 22 Gunnar Skirbekk: The Critically Ambiguous Idea of a “Modernization of (Religious) Consciousness”. 27 Cristina Lafont: The Burdens of the Public Use of Reason. 32 Cathrine Holst: Secular Worries. 48 Helge Høibraaten: Post-metaphysical thought, religion and secular society. 52 Craig Calhoun: Religion, Secularism, and Public Reason. 64 Thomas M. Schmidt: The Discourse of Religion in the Post-Secular Society. 80 Jon Hellesnes: On Artificially Moralising the Morally Irrelevant. 90 Hauke Brunkhorst: Hard Times for Democracy. 92 Tore Lindholm: Challenging Habermas on the Moral Legitimacy of Religious Voices in Democratic Politics.
    [Show full text]
  • Agency at the Time of the Anthropocene New Literary History Vol
    Agency at the time of the Anthropocene New Literary History Vol. 45, pp. 1-18, 2014 “Et pourtant la Terre s’émeut” Michel Serres, Le contrat naturel How are we supposed to react when faced with a piece of news like this one from Le Monde on Tuesday, May 7 , 2013: “At Mauna Loa, on Friday May 3, the concentration of CO2 was reaching 399. 29 ppm”? How can we absorb the odd novelty of the headline: “The amount of CO 2 in the air is the highest it has been for more than 2.5 million years — the threshold of 400 ppm of CO2, the main agent of global warming, is going to be crossed this year”? Such an extension of both the span of deep history and the impact of our own collective action is made even more troubling by the subtitle in the same article, which quietly states: “The maximum permissible CO2 limit was crossed just before 1990”. So not only do we have to swallow the news that our very recent development has modified a state of affairs that is vastly older that the very existence of the human race (a diagram in the article reminds us that the oldest human tools are comparatively very recent!), but we have also to absorb the disturbing fact that the drama has been completed and that the main revolutionary event is behind us, since we have already crossed a few of the nine “planetary boundaries” considered by some scientists as the ultimate barrier not to overstep!1 I think that it is easy for us to agree that, in modernism, people are not equipped with the mental and emotional repertoire to deal with such a vast scale of events; that they have difficulty submitting to such a rapid acceleration for which, in addition, they are supposed to feel responsible while, in the meantime, this call for action has none of the traits of their older revolutionary dreams.
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae of Sara Beardsworth I
    CURRICULUM VITAE OF SARA BEARDSWORTH I. PROFESSIONAL AFFILIATION AND CONTACT INFORMATION Associate Professor, Department of Philosophy, Southern Illinois University, Carbondale,IL 62901-4505 Phone: (618) 453 7453 Email: [email protected] II. EDUCATION PhD Philosophy, University of Warwick, UK, 1988-1994 MA Philosophy, University of Sussex, UK, 1984-1986 BA(Hons) Archaeology, Institute of Archaeology, University of London, UK, 1977-1980 III. PROFESSIONAL EXPERIENCE 1994 (S) Instructor, History of ethics, University of Warwick, UK 1995 (F) Instructor, Phenomenology: Husserl and Heidegger, School of Historical, Philosophical, and Contemporary Studies, University of North London, UK 1995-1996 Lecturer in Continental Philosophy, School of Historical, Philosophical, and Contemporary Studies, University of North London, UK 1996-1997 Visiting Assistant Professor, Department of Philosophy, Vanderbilt University 1997-1998 Visiting Research Fellowship, Goldsmith’s College, University of London, UK 1998-2004 Assistant Professor, Department of Philosophy, University of Memphis 2004— Assistant Professor, Department of Philosophy, Southern Illinois University Carbondale 2008— Associate Professor, Department of Philosophy, Southern Illinois University Carbondale IV. RESEARCH AND CREATIVE ACTIVITY A. Interests and Specialties: Nineteenth- and twentieth-century European philosophy Psychoanalysis Feminist philosophy Critical Theory Philosophy and literature B. Current Projects: “The Trauma of Torture: the Missing Affect and the Disappearance of Torturers,”
    [Show full text]
  • Hacking, Ian (1936-)
    Hacking, Ian (1936-) Reijula, Samuli samuli.reijula@helsinki.fi Theoretical Philosophy / TINT University of Helsinki, Finland Author manuscript version, 26 February 2021 final encyclopedia entry published in Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy∗ Article Summary Ian Hacking (born in 1936, Vancouver, British Columbia) is most well-known for his work in the philosophy of the natural and social sciences, but his contributions to philosophy are broad, spanning many areas and traditions. In his detailed case studies of the development of probabilistic and statistical reasoning, Hacking pioneered the naturalistic approach in the philosophy of science. Hacking’s research on social constructionism, transient mental illnesses and the looping effect of the human kinds make use of historical materials to shed light on how developments in the social, medical, and behavioral sciences have shaped our contemporary conceptions of identity and agency. Hacking’s other contributions to philosophy include his work on the philosophy of mathematics (Hacking 2014), philosophy of statistics, philosophy of logic, inductive logic (Hacking 1965; 1979; 2001) and natural kinds (Hacking 1991, 2007a). ∗https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/biographical/hacking-ian-1936/v-1 1 Hacking, Ian (1936-) 1 Naturalism in the philosophy of science Ian Hacking completed his first degree, a BA in mathematics and physics, at the University of British Columbia in 1956. He earned his PhD from Cambridge, where he studied under the direction of Casimir Lewy, a former student of Ludwig Wittgenstein (De Sousa 1992; Vagelli 2014). After holding various positions both in the US and in Europe, in 1982 he was granted a professorship at the University of Toronto.
    [Show full text]
  • WHAT MATHEMATICS HAS DONE to SOME and ONLY SOME PHILOSOPHERS Ian Hacking
    Hacking page 1 WHAT MATHEMATICS HAS DONE TO SOME AND ONLY SOME PHILOSOPHERS Ian Hacking 1 HOW IS PURE MATHEMATICS POSSIBLE? 2 JOHN STUART MILL 3 PLATO 4 LEIBNIZ 5 THE TERMS OF ART 6 DESCARTES 7 LAKATOS 8 WITTGENSTEIN 1 HOW IS PURE MATHEMATICS POSSIBLE? According to Bertrand Russell, ‘the question which Kant put at the beginning of his philosophy, namely “How is pure mathematics possible?” is an interesting and difficult one, to which every philosophy which is not purely sceptical must find an answer’.1 Russell exaggerated. Many philosophies that are not purely sceptical have had no interest in Kant’s question. It never even occurred to them, much less struck them as important. I shall not be invidious, but we quickly think of canonical Western philosophers of all periods who have not troubled themselves with mathematics at all. Hence the ‘some and only some’ of my title. But the spirit of Russell’s remark is right. A great many of the philosophers whom we still read have been deeply impressed by mathematics, and have gone so far as to tailor much of their philosophy to their vision of mathematical knowledge, mathematical reality, or, what I think is crucial, mathematical proof. Why do so many philosophies try to answer Kant’s question? And, incidentally, why do a great many not address it? We need not distinguish between Russell’s talk of philosophies and individual philosophers, so long as we examine only a few famous philosophers each of whom has defined a philosophy. I shall employ the very opposite of Myles Burnyeats’ skillful scholarship, for I am less concerned with philosophical texts or doctrines than with the broader question, of why a philosopher should have become obsessed by mathematics as a source of philosophical inspiration.
    [Show full text]