European Philosophy & the Aftermath of Violence

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

European Philosophy & the Aftermath of Violence ARC Ethical Restoration Project References (European Philosophy and the aftermath of violence) 1 REFERENCES (EUROPEAN PHILOSOPHY & THE AFTERMATH OF VIOLENCE) Anderson, N. and Mansfield, N. 2011. Special Issue: Deconstructing Democracy. Derrida today 4(2). Anderson-Gold, Sharon and Muchnik, P., eds. 2009. Kant’s Anatomy of Evil. Cambridge University Press. Ang, Jennifer. 2010. Sartre and the Moral Limits of War and Terrorism. London: Routledge. Arendt, Hannah. 2003. Responsibility and Judgment. Ed. J. Kohn. New York: Schocken. ——. 1998. The Human Condition. 2nd ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. ——. 1994. Essays in Understanding. Ed. J. Kohn. New York: Schocken Books. ——. 1982. Lectures on Kant’s Political Philosophy. Ed. R Beiner. Brighton: Harvester. ——. 1978. The Jew as Pariah. Ed. R. Feldman. New York: Grove Press. ——. 1976. The Origins of Totalitarianism. San Diego: Harcourt Brace. ——. 1970. On Violence. San Diego: Harcourt Brace. ——. 1972. Crises of the Republic. New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich. ——. 1965. On Revolution. Harmondsworth: Penguin. ——. 1963. Eichmann in Jerusalem: A Report on the Banality of Evil. New York: Penguin. Hannah Arendt issue of Philosophical Topics, Vol.39, No.2, 2011. Aronson, R., Santoni, R., and Stone, R. 2003. ‘The New Orleans Session — March 2002.’ Sartre Studies International, 9(2): 9-27. Arthur, Paige. 2010. Unfinished Projects: Decolonization and the philosophy of Jean-Paul Sartre. London: Verso. Baiasu, Sorin, and Loriaux, Sylvie (eds.) 2016. Kantian Sincerity in Politics and International Relations: Between Theory and Practice. Routledge. Beauvoir, Simone de. 2010. The Second Sex. Trans. C. Borde and S. Malovany-Chevallier. New York: Knopf. ——. 2004. Philosophical Writings. Chicago: University of Illinois Press. ——. 1997. The Ethics of Ambiguity. Trans. B. Frechtman. Secaucus: Citadel. Bernstein, Richard J. 2002. Radical Evil: A Philosophical Interrogation. Cambridge: Polity. Bird, Greg and Short, Jonathan. 2013. ‘Community, Immunity, and the Proper an Introduction to the Political Theory of Roberto Esposito’. Angelaki 18 (3):1-12. Borradori, Giovanna. 2003. Philosophy in a Time of Terror: Dialogues with J. Habermas and Jacques Derrida. University of Chicago Press. Bowman, Elizabeth, and Stone, Robert V. 2005. ‘The Alter-Globalization Movement and Sartre’s Morality and History.’ Sartre Studies International 11(1-2): 265-85. Bowman, Elizabeth, and Stone, Robert V. 2004. ‘The end as present in the means in Sartre’s morality and history: birth and reinventions of an existential moral standard.’ Sartre Studies International. Vol.10, No.2. 1-28. Campbell, T. 2006. ‘Bios, Immunity, Life: The Thought of Roberto Esposito.’ Diacritics 36(2): 2- 22. —— 2006. ‘Interview: Roberto Esposito.’ Diacritics 36 (2): 49-56. Caputo, John D, Dooley, Michael, and Scanlon, M. J., Eds. 2001. Questioning God. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. Card, Claudia. 2010. Confronting Evils: terrorism, torture, genocide. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ——, ed. 2003. The Cambridge Companion to Simone de Beauvoir. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Caswell, Matthew. 2006. ‘The Value of Humanity and Kant’s Conception of Evil.’ Journal of the History of Philosophy. 44 (4): 635-63. Dallmayr, Fred. 2006. ‘An end to evil? Philosophical and political reflections.’ International Journal of Philosophy of Religion. 60: 169-86. ARC Ethical Restoration Project References (European Philosophy and the aftermath of violence) 2 Derrida, Jacques. 2013. The death penalty, Vol.1, Trans. Peggy Kamuf. University of Chicago Press. ——. 2005. Rogues: Two Essays on Reason. Trans. P.A. Brault and M. Naas. Stanford University Press. ——. 2004. Roudinesco, Elisabeth. For What Tomorrow ... A Dialogue. Trans. J. Fort. Stanford University Press. ——. 2002a. Acts of Religion. Ed. Gil Anidjar. London: Routledge. ——. 2002b. ‘Ethics and Politics Today.’ Negotiations: Interventions and Interviews, 1971-2001. Trans. Elizabeth Rottenberg. Stanford: Stanford University Press. 295-314. ——. 2001. On Cosmopolitanism and Forgiveness. Trans. M. Dooley and M. Hughes. London: Routledge. ——. 2001a. The Work of Mourning. Eds. Pascale-Anne Brault and Michael Naas. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. ——. 2001b. On Cosmopolitanism and Forgiveness. Trans. Mark Dooley and Michael Hughes. London: Routledge. ——. 2000. Of Hospitality: Anne Dufourmantelle Invites Jacques Derrida to Respond. Trans. Rachel Bowlby. Stanford: Stanford University Press. ——. 1992. ‘Force of Law: the “Mystical Foundation of Authority”.’ Deconstruction and the Possibility of Justice. Eds. Drucilla Cornell, Michel Rosenfeld, and David Gray Carlson. New York: Routledge. 3-67. Descartes, René. 1989. The Passions of the Soul. Trans. S. H. Voss. Indianapolis: Hackett. Deutscher, Penelope. 2010, ‘Reproductive Politics, Biopolitics and Auto-immunity: From Foucault to Esposito.’ Bioethical Inquiry 7: 217-226. Esposito, Roberto 2013, ‘Community, Immunity, Biopolitics’, Z. Hanafi trans., Angelaki: Journal of the Theoretical Humanities 18 (3): 83-90. —— 2012, ‘Freedom and Immunity.’ In Terms of the Political: Community, Immunity, Biopolitics, edited by Lemm V., 47-56. Fordham University Press. —— 2012, ‘Immunization and Violence.’ In Terms of the Political: Community, Immunity, Biopolitics, edited by Lemm V., 57-66. Fordham University Press. —— 2012, ‘Immunitary Democracy.’ In Terms of the Political: Community, Immunity, Biopolitics, edited by Lemm V., 37-46. —— 2011. Immunitas: the protections and negations of life. Cambridge: Polity. —— 2010, Communitas: The Origin and Destiny of Community. T. Campbell trans., Stanford University Press, California. —— 2008. Bios: biopolitics and philosophy. Trans. Timothy Campbell. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. —— and Campbell, Timothy. 2006. ‘The Immunization Paradigm.’ Diacritics 36 (2): 23-48. European Journal of Social Theory. Special Issue on post-traumatic societies. 11(3): 2008. Farneti, R 2011, ‘The Immunitary Turn in Current Talk on Biopolitics: on Roberto Esposito’s Bios.’ Philosophy and Social Criticism 37(8): 955-962. Fiasse, Gaëlle, 2012. ‘Revisting Jankélévitch’s Dichotomy: Between Excusing the Ignorant and Forgiving the Wicked.’ Philosophy Today 56(1): 3-15. Formosa, Paul. 2009. ‘Kant on the Limits of Human Evil.’ Journal of Philosophical Research 34: 189-214. Frederic, N 2010. ‘The Birth of Immunopolitics.’ Parrhesia 10: 31-38. Freire, P. 2005. Pedagogy of the Oppressed. M. B. Ramos, Trans. New York: Continuum. Freidman, S. S., ed. 1993. Holocaust Literature: A Handbook of Critical, Historical and Literary Writings. London: Greenwood Press. Haddad, Samir. 2014. Derrida and the inheritance of Democracy. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. Hartouni, Valerie. 2012. Visualizing atrocity: Arendt, evil, and the optics of thoughtlessness. New York: New York University Press. ARC Ethical Restoration Project References (European Philosophy and the aftermath of violence) 3 Jankélévitch, Vladimir. 2005. Forgiveness. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Kant, Immanuel. 1996a. Practical Philosophy. Trans. M. J. Gregor. Cambridge University Press. ——. 1996b. Religion and Rational Theology. Trans. A. W. Wood and G. di Giovanni. Cambridge University Press. Keenan, A. 1994. ‘Promises, Promises: The Abyss of Freedom and the Loss of the Political in the Work of Hannah Arendt.’ Political Theory: An International Journal of Political Philosophy 22(2): 297-322. Kierkegaard, Søren. 1941. Thoughts on Crucial Situations in Human Life: Three Discourses on Imagined Occasions. Trans. David F. Swenson. Minneapolis: Augsburg. Kristeva, Julia, and Rice, Alison. 2002. ‘An interview.’ Modern Language Association 117(2): 278- 95. —— 2010. Hatred and Forgiveness. Trans. J. Herman. New York: Columbia University Press: 191-94. —— 2002. Intimate Revolt: the Powers and Limits of Psychoanalysis. J. Herman trans., New York: Columbia University Press. —— 2001. Hannah Arendt: Life is a Narrative. Toronto: University of Toronto Press. —— 1989. Black Sun: Depression and Melancholia. Trans. L.S. Roudiez. New York: Columbia University Press. Kruks, Sonia. 2013. Simone de Beauvoir and the politics of ambiguity. Oxford: Oxford University Press. La Caze, Marguerite. 2013. ‘At first blush: The politics of guilt and shame.’ Parrhesia: A Journal of Critical Philosophy 18: 85-99. ——. 2013. Wonder and Generosity: Their Role in Ethics and Politics. New York: SUNY. ——. 2011a. ‘Terrorism and Trauma: Negotiating Derridean “autoimmunity”.’ Philosophy and Social Criticism. 37(5): 605-20. ——. 2011b ‘The Miraculous Power of Forgiveness and the Promise.’ Action and Appearance: Explorations in Hannah Arendt, Ed. A. Yeatman, P. Hansen, M. Zolkos, and C. Barbour, London: Continuum. ——. 2010. ‘The Judgement of the Statesperson.’ Power, Judgment and Political Evil: In Conversation with Hannah Arendt. Edited by A. Schaap, D. Celermajer and V. Karalis, Farnham: Ashgate. ——. 2009. ‘Derrida: Opposing Death Penalties.’ Derrida Today 2 (2): 186-199. ——. 2007. ‘Sartre integrating Ethics and Politics: The Case of Terrorism.’ Parrhesia 3: 43-53. Lemm, Vanessa 2013. ‘Nietzsche, Einverleibung and the Politics of Immunity.’ International Journal of Philosophical Studies 21(1): 3-19. —— 2012, ‘Introduction: Biopolitics and Community in Roberto Esposito’, in Lemm V (ed.), Terms of the Political: Community, Immunity, Biopolitics, Fordham University Press: 1-13. Levi, Primo. 1959. If This Is a Man. Trans. Stuart Woolf. London: Orion Press. Lewis, Michael. 2013. ‘Of (Auto-)Immune Life: Derrida, Esposito,
Recommended publications
  • What Does It Mean to Make-Up the Mind (Οὕτω Διανοεῖσθε)? Justin Murphy
    parrhesia 29 · 2018 · 163-189 what does it mean to make-up the mind (οὕτω διανοεῖσθε)? justin murphy Under what conditions can thought and speech participate meaningfully in sys- temic political transformations? In my view, two bodies of late twentieth-century thought stand out as the most advanced efforts to answer this question. Gilles De- leuze and Michel Foucault, in their own registers and of course with very differ- ent accents, both suggest substantial but complicated roles thinking and speaking might have to play in any viable future project of emancipatory politics. Given the idealistic associations and connotations of such terms as thinking and speaking, it is no surprise that both figures have been charged with similar crimes: individual- ism, aestheticism, or escapism, all of which are typically implied to render their bodies of work unhelpful for projects of organized, collective political change.1 In the present historical moment of the so-called age of information, we are now in a better position than ever to understand the ways in which mere thought and speech are unable to generate politically significant emancipatory dynamics. In modern global capitalism, it has never seemed more clear that what is called free- dom of speech and the public exchange of ideas is perfectly consistent with the perpetuity and even intensification of oppressive institutional dynamics. Yet, I wish to suggest that in this rightful disillusionment with mere thought and speech lies an opportunity for improving our understanding of the unique conditions under which certain types of thought and speech might be keys to unlocking new forms of emancipatory politics today, in the context of what Deleuze called “con- trol societies.”2 If it is true that Foucault and Deleuze are two of the most advanced thinkers of this question—and yet even they remain uncleared of charges relating to political triviality—then it would seem that the surest way to advance the question would be to begin at the edges of where they left off.
    [Show full text]
  • Critical Inquiry As Virtuous Truth-Telling: Implications of Phronesis and Parrhesia ______
    ______________________________________________________________________________ Critical Inquiry as Virtuous Truth-Telling: Implications of Phronesis and Parrhesia ______________________________________________________________________________ Austin Pickup, Aurora University Abstract This article examines critical inquiry and truth-telling from the perspective of two comple- mentary theoretical frameworks. First, Aristotelian phronesis, or practical wisdom, offers a framework for truth that is oriented toward ethical deliberation while recognizing the contingency of practical application. Second, Foucauldian parrhesia calls for an engaged sense of truth-telling that requires risk from the inquirer while grounding truth in the com- plexity of human discourse. Taken together, phronesis and parrhesia orient inquirers to- ward intentional truth-telling practices that resist simplistic renderings of criticality and overly technical understandings of research. This article argues that truly critical inquiry must spring from the perspectives of phronesis and parrhesia, providing research projects that aim at virtuous truth-telling over technical veracity with the hope of contributing to ethical discourse and social praxis. Keywords: phronesis, praxis, parrhesia, critical inquiry, truth-telling Introduction The theme of this special issue considers the nature of critical inquiry, specifically methodological work that remains committed to explicit goals of social justice and the good. One of the central concerns of this issue is that critical studies have lost much of their meaning due to a proliferation of the term critical in educational scholarship. As noted in the introduction to this issue, much contemporary work in education research that claims to be critical may be so in name only, offering but methodological techniques to engage in critical work; techniques that are incapable of inter- vening in both the epistemological and ontological formations of normative practices in education.
    [Show full text]
  • 3 Reading Arendt's on Revolution After the Fall of the Wall
    3 READING ARENDT’S ON REVOLUTION AFTER THE FALL OF THE WALL Dick Howard* RESUMO – O artigo revisita a obra de Hannah ABSTRACT – The article revisits Hannah Arendt’s Arendt On Revolution e os eventos históricos da On Revolution and the historical events of the revolução americana, de forma a reformular os American revolution so as to recast what Arendt chamados “problemas da época”. Embora todo ator called “the age’s problems”. Although every político reivindique que as suas políticas sejam a political actor claims that its policies are the encarnação da vontade unida da nação em uma incarnation of the united will of the nation in a democracia, abre-se a porta da antipolítica na democracy, the door to antipolitics is opened if the medida em que a natureza simbólica – e portanto symbolic – and therefore contested – nature of the contestada – do povo soberano é reduzida à sua sovereign people is reduced to its temporary reality. realidade temporária. Tal é a lição crucial a ser That is the crucial lesson to be drawn still today extraída ainda hoje da obra The Origins of from The Origins of Totalitarianism, which can be Totalitarianism, que pode ser lida como uma read as an attempt to think the most extreme tentativa de pensar a expressão mais extrema da expression of antipolitics. antipolítica. PALAVRAS-CHAVE – Antipolítica. Arendt. Demo- KEY WORDS – Antipolitics. Arendt. Democracy. cracia. Revolução. Revolution. Introduction: From where do you speak, comrade? Two decades after the fall of the Wall seemed to announce – by default, as an unexpected gift – the triumph of democracy, optimism appears at best naïve, at worst an ideological manipulation of the most cynical type.
    [Show full text]
  • Prof. Dr. Dr. Jörg Monar Recteur/Rector 13 November 2019 OPENING CEREMONY ACADEMIC YEAR 2019-2020 Dear President of The
    Prof. Dr. Dr. Jörg Monar Recteur/Rector 13 November 2019 OPENING CEREMONY ACADEMIC YEAR 2019-2020 ALLOCUTION PROMOTION HANNAH ARENDT Dear President of the European Council, Dear President of the Administrative Council, Mijnheer de Gouverneur, Mijnheer de Burgermeester, Your Excellencies, Dear Friends and Colleagues, Ladies and Gentlemen, Dear Students, One of the most well-known and often-cited concepts of political anthropology is Aristotle’s classification of the human being as a ζῷον πολιτικόν, as a “political animal” or perhaps better, “living being”, in his Πολιτικά written around 330 BC. According to him - who we can regard as the father of political science - it is only through man being part of a political community, the πόλις, that he can fully realise his nature and potential. The history of mankind has shown, and our world of today keeps showing, that this political dimension of our existence accounts for much of what we have been able to achieve as humans in terms of social, legal, scientific, economic, organisational and even the moral progress, well beyond the horizons of the Greek city-states which formed the basis of Aristotle’s analysis. Yet at the same time this political dimension has also all too often been a pathway to the abysses of human nature, to unrestrained barbarism and the infliction of boundless suffering by some on their fellow human beings. │Hannah Arendt – PATRONNE OF THE PROMOTION 2019-2020] 2 How can it happen, how can it be explained that what belongs to our essence, what accounts for so much of the positive potential of our living together, the political dimension of our existence, can turn into the large-scale destruction of values and lives, the generation of evils poisoning an entire generation or more? In 1933 a 26-year old, intellectually wide awake and strongly-willed young researcher, Hannah Arendt, was confronted with one of those turns of politics into hell, arguably one if not the most calamitous in history, the coming into power of the Nazi regime in Germany.
    [Show full text]
  • Exploring Liquid Modernity, Material Feminisms, Care of the Self, and Parrhesia
    Journal of critical Thought and Praxis Iowa state university digital press & School of education ________________________________________________________________________________________________________ Volume 6 Issue 1 Everyday Practices of Social Justice Article 2 Working Towards Everyday Social Justice Action: Exploring Liquid Modernity, Material Feminism, Care of the Self, and Parrhesia Lauren P. Hoffman Follow this and additional works at: http://lib.dr.iastate.edu/jctp/vol6/iss1/ This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Digital Repository @ Iowa State University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Journal of Critical Thought and Praxis by an authorized editor of Digital Repository @ Iowa State University Journal of Critical Thought and Praxis 2017, Vol. 6, No. 1, 1-17 Working Towards Everyday Social Justice Action: Exploring Liquid Modernity, Material Feminisms, Care of the Self, and Parrhesia Lauren P. Hoffman* Lewis University The purpose of this paper is to explore the difficulty many critically prepared educators and leaders experience when wanting to translate their social justice knowledge into everyday social justice practices. Even though these individuals are critically conscious and want to critically act, many become overwhelmed with the enormity of the neoliberal crisis, tend to fear actually acting against or speaking up in the face of injustice, and may become cynical in terms of even believing in the possibility of any type of educational and social transformation. To address this reticence, the postmodern and posthuman concepts of liquid modernity (Bauman, 2006, 2007) material feminisms (Barad, 2007,2008), care of the self and parrhesia (Foucault, 2001, 2005, 2011) were presented to educational leadership doctoral students as ideas to explicitly challenge their issues of fear and cynicism.
    [Show full text]
  • Reading Arendt's on Revolution After the Fall of the Wall
    Keeping the Republic: Reading Arendt’s On Revolution after the Fall of the Wall Dick Howard Introduction: From where do you speak, comrade? Two decades after the fall of the Wall seemed to announce – by default, as an unexpected gift – the triumph of democracy, optimism appears at best naïve, at worst an ideological manipulation of the most cynical type. The hope was that the twin forms of modern anti-politics – the imaginary planned society and the equally imaginary invisible hand of the market place – would be replaced by the rule of the demos; citizens together would determine the values of the commonwealth. The reality was at first the ‘New World Order’ of George H.W. Bush; then the indecisive interregnum of the Clinton years; and now the crass take over of democratic rhetoric by the neo-conservatives of George W. Bush. ‘Man is born free, yet everywhere he is in chains,’ wrote Rousseau at the outset of The Social Contract; how this came about was less important, he continued, than what made it legitimate: that was what needed explanation. So it is today; what is it about democracy that makes it the greatest threat to its own existence? In this context, it is well to reread Hannah Arendt’s On Revolution, published in 1963. On returning recently to my old (1965) paperback edition, I was struck by the spare red and black design of the cover, which was not (as I thought for a moment) a subtle allusion to the conflict of communism and anarchism for the realization of ‘true’ democracy, but simply the backdrop against which the editor stressed these sentences: ‘With nuclear power at a stalemate, revolutions have become the principal political factor of our time.
    [Show full text]
  • The Limits of Nonviolence in Arendt's 'Civil Disobedience'
    From Resistance to Revolution: The Limits of Nonviolence in Arendt’s ‘Civil Disobedience’ Caroline Ashcroft Queen Mary University of London [email protected] Abstract: Arendt’s work on civil disobedience sets out an optimistic portrayal of the possibilities of such forms of action in re-energizing the spirit of American politics in the late twentieth century. Civil disobedience should not simply be tolerated, she argued, but incorporated into the legal structure of the American political system. Her work is usually seen to promote an idea of civil disobedience that is thus bound to existing constitutional principles and essentially nonviolent. However, by looking at Arendt’s discussion and critique of various practices of civil disobedience in 1960s and 1970s America, specifically in relation to the nonviolence movement influenced by Martin Luther King, and on the other side, the more militant Black Power movement, a different idea of civil disobedience emerges. This paper argues that whilst, for Arendt, civil disobedience within America certainly possesses the constitutionally restorative potential she assigns to it, in a broader sense – theoretically, globally, and even in terms of alternative ideologies within America – her conception of civil disobedience is in itself neither necessarily constitutional, nor nonviolent. It is, instead, a form of revolutionary action, whose limits are set only by politics itself, and specifically, Arendt’s criterion of publicity. Keywords: Hannah Arendt, Civil Disobedience, America, Publicity, Martin Luther King, James Forman 1 From Resistance to Revolution: The Limits of Nonviolence in Arendt’s ‘Civil Disobedience’ 1. The Legitimacy of Civil Disobedience Hannah Arendt famously saw in civil disobedience a means by which to reenergize the American political system: to restore to it its original spirit through the political actions of the people.
    [Show full text]
  • Arendt's Violence/Power Distinction and SARTRE's Violence/Counter-Violence Distinction: the Phenomenology of Violence in Co
    CHAPTER SIX ARENDT’S VIOLENCE/POWER DISTINCTION AND SARTRE’S VIOLENCE/COUNTER-VIOLENCE DISTINCTION: THE PHENOMENOLOGY OF VIOLENCE IN COLONIAL AND POST-ColonIAL CONTEXTS Kathryn T. Gines The theme of violence can be traced throughout Hannah Arendt’s major political writings such as The Human Condition and On Revolution where she draws connections between war, violence, and necessity (or libera- tion from necessity); The Origins of Totalitarianism where she examines Europe’s uses of violence in concentration camps, as well as massacre and imperialism in Africa; and, of course, On Violence where she condemns the violence of the Black Power movement and of anti-colonialism. The essay that follows will take as its starting point the violence/power dis- tinction and then the appropriate uses of violence versus non-violence as presented in Arendt’s On Violence. I argue that this distinction between violence and power is misapplied in Arendt’s critique of Jean-Paul Sar- tre and Frantz Fanon’s analyses of anti-colonial revolutionary violence in Algeria. Arendt wrongly interprets Sartre and Fanon’s analyses of violence and counter-violence in The Wretched of the Earth and Critique of Dialecti- cal Reason and her critique of violence proves to be unbalanced. On my view, she rejects their analyses because they argue for the use of violence by the oppressed to overcome the violent system of colonialism. I con- tend that it is because they argue for revolutionary violence (or counter- violence) against their oppressors that Sartre and Fanon are accused of glorifying violence for violence’s sake. In the concluding section of the essay, I briefly consider the possibil- ity that while Arendt’s critique of anti-colonial violence is misguided, her analysis might prove helpful when applied to the post-colonial context in which former anti-colonial leaders fighting for independence strike out violently against the people.
    [Show full text]
  • Parrhesia 31 · 2019 Parrhesia 31 · 2019 · 1-16
    parrhesia 31 · 2019 parrhesia 31 · 2019 · 1-16 gaston bachelard and contemporary philosophy massimiliano simons, jonas rutgeerts, anneleen masschelein and paul cortois1 There are philosophers whose name sounds familiar, but who very few people know in more than a vague sense. And there are philosophers whose footprints are all over the recent history of philosophy, but who themselves have retreated somewhat in the background. Gaston Bachelard (1884-1962) is a bit of both. With- out doubt, he was one of the most prominent French philosophers in the first half of the 20th century, who wrote over twenty books, covering domains as diverse as philosophy of science, poetry, art and metaphysics. His ideas profoundly influ- enced a wide array of authors including Georges Canguilhem, Gilbert Simondon, Roland Barthes, Michel Foucault, Bruno Latour and Pierre Bourdieu. Up until the 1980s, Bachelard’s work was widely read by philosophers, scientists, literary theo- rists, artists, and even wider audiences and in his public appearances he incar- nated one of the most iconic and fascinating icons of a philosopher. And yet, surprisingly, in recent years the interest in Bachelard’s theoretical oeuvre seems to have somewhat waned. Apart from some recent attempts to revive his thinking, the philosopher’s oeuvre is rarely discussed outside specialist circles, often only available for those able to read French.2 In contemporary Anglo-Saxon philosophy the legacy of Bachelard seems to consist mainly in his widely known book Poetics of Space. While some of Bachelard’s contemporaries, like Georges Canguilhem or Gilbert Simondon (see Parrhesia, issue 7), who were profoundly influenced by Bachelard, have been rediscovered, the same has not happened for Bachelard’s philosophical oeuvre.
    [Show full text]
  • Kierkegaard on Socrates' Daimonion
    Kierkegaard on Socrates’ daimonion Citation for published version (APA): Sneller, R. (2020). Kierkegaard on Socrates’ daimonion. International Journal of Philosophy and Theology, 81(1), 87-100. https://doi.org/10.1080/21692327.2019.1649602 DOI: 10.1080/21692327.2019.1649602 Document status and date: Published: 01/01/2020 Document Version: Publisher’s PDF, also known as Version of Record (includes final page, issue and volume numbers) Please check the document version of this publication: • A submitted manuscript is the version of the article upon submission and before peer-review. There can be important differences between the submitted version and the official published version of record. People interested in the research are advised to contact the author for the final version of the publication, or visit the DOI to the publisher's website. • The final author version and the galley proof are versions of the publication after peer review. • The final published version features the final layout of the paper including the volume, issue and page numbers. Link to publication General rights Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. • Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the public portal for the purpose of private study or research. • You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain • You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the public portal.
    [Show full text]
  • Parrhesia E Injusticias Epistémicas
    Parrhesia and epistemic injustices Parrhesia e injusticias epistémicas Gonzalo Lucas Gallego Universidad de Murcia [email protected] DOI: https://doi.org/10.15366/bp2017.17.015 Bajo Palabra. II Época. Nº17. 2017. Pgs: 309-328 Recibido: 15/01/2016 Aprobado: 26/10/2017 Resumen Abstract El presente trabajo acomete el aná- The present paper attempts to analyse lisis de las complejas relaciones entre the complex relationship between truth verdad y democracia a partir de la no- and democracy from the notion of pa- ción de parrhesia, tal y como esta fue rrhesia, as Foucault treated it during his rescatada por Michel Foucault durante last works. The Foucauldian approach sus últimos trabajos. La propuesta fou- establishes a stressing linkage on one caultiana predica una vinculación cons- another: there can be no democracy wi- titutiva, no exenta de tensiones, entre thout appealing to certain idea of truth, ambas: no puede haber democracia sin but the emergence of such truth invol- referencia a una cierta idea de verdad, ves the existence of a democratic space. pero la emergencia de tal verdad presu- Such space is constructed through the pone la existencia de un espacio demo- critic of every attempt to monopolize crático. La construcción de ese espacio the capacity of saying the truth. In this se realiza sobre la crítica a todo intento sense, the concept of epistemic injusti- de monopolizar la capacidad de decir la ce helps us to understand how political verdad. En este sentido, el concepto de and epistemic dimensions are interwo- injusticia epistémica nos ayuda a enten- ven in the democratic process.
    [Show full text]
  • Rachel Elizabeth Zuckert Department of Philosophy 5728 N. Kenmore
    Rachel Elizabeth Zuckert Department of Philosophy 5728 N. Kenmore Ave, 3N Northwestern University Chicago, IL 60660 Kresge 3-512 1880 Campus Drive home: (773) 728-7927 Evanston, IL 60208 work: (847) 491-2556 [email protected] Education: 2000 PhD, University of Chicago, Department of Philosophy and the Committee on Social Thought 1995 MA, University of Chicago, Committee on Social Thought 1992 B.A. (1), Oxford University (Philosophy and Modern Languages) 1990 B.A. (Summa Cum Laude; Highest Honors in Philosophy; Phi Beta Kappa), Williams College Areas of Specialization: Kant and eighteenth-century philosophy Aesthetics Areas of Competence: Early modern philosophy Nineteenth-century philosophy Feminist philosophy Languages: French German Academic Employment: 2018- Professor of Philosophy, Northwestern University; affiliated with the German Department 2008-18 Associate Professor of Philosophy, Northwestern University; affiliated with the German Department 2011-18 2006-2008 Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Northwestern University 2001-2006 Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Rice University 1999-2001 Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Bucknell University Zuckert 2 Publications: Books Kant on Beauty and Biology: An Interpretation of the Critique of Judgment, Cambridge University Press, 2007. Awarded the American Society for Aesthetics Monograph Prize (2008); reviewed in British Journal for the History of Philosophy, Comparative and Continental Philosophy, Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal, Journal of the History of Philosophy, Metascience, Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews, Review of Metaphysics, and subject of review essays in Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism and Kant Yearbook Herder’s Naturalist Aesthetics, Cambridge University Press, forthcoming (2019). Edited Volume Hegel on Philosophy in History, co-edited with James Kreines, Cambridge University Press, 2017.
    [Show full text]