5. the Arrow of Time

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

5. the Arrow of Time 5. l The arrow of time Précis. Many purported arrows do not establish asymmetries of time itself, but dynamical asymmetries can, with the help of the representation view. The ‘arrow of time’ is shorthand for time asymmetry. The idea appears to have been born in Trinity College, Cambridge in the early twentieth century. Trinity philosopher John McTaggart (1908, p.474) remarks on it in the conclusion to his famous discussion of the reality of time, asking, “what is that quality, and is it a greater amount of it which determines things to appear as later, and a lesser amount which determines them to appear as earlier, or is the reverse true?” The phrase itself was coined by Trinity physicist Arthur S. Eddington: “I shall use the phrase ‘time’s arrow’ to express this one-way property of time which has no analogue in space. It is a singularly interesting property from a philosophical standpoint.” (Eddington 1928, p.69) What is this ‘one-way property’ of time, and what evidence is there that time has it? Arrow Example Thermodynamic Dissipating gas Radiation Expanding electromagnetic waves Quantum measurement Dynamical state reduction Cosmological Cosmic expansion T-violation Kaon quark flavour mixing Spacetime Intrinsic temporal orientation Causal/Dependency Causes leading to effects Figure 5.1: Some arrows of time. 115 Figure 5.1 summarises a few existing responses.1 Some of these arrows may be related. Others are quite different from one another. And, there are likely many more! Caution is needed: the possibility of illusion looms. Many things presents the powerful appearance of being asymmetric in time to our naïve human senses, when in fact they are not. For example, a book will slide to a stop on a tabletop, but never the reverse: it does not spontaneously begin sliding! But when that experience is carefully described as dynamical systems, we find that it invariably omits degrees of freedom in a way that hides the true temporal symmetry. This chapter will present a framework for determining whether there is a phys- ical arrow of time. I begin by identifying some of the ways the arrow of time can fall short of establishing it. It can happen by resorting to heuristics, relying on boundary conditions, or by describing a physical system with missing information. Each can lead to a powerful explanation of our asymmetric experiences, but does not establish any asymmetry of time itself. My thesis is that the promising road to an arrow draws on the asymmetries of a dynamical theory. This possibility is afforded by a link between the symmetries of spacetime and those of a dynamical theory, which I call the representation view. In Section 5.1 will set out our aim, to determine what kind of evidence is require to establish a physical arrow of time. Section 5.2 will then review some prominent attempts that are widely agreed to fall short of a physical arrow of time, including radiation, thermodynamic, cosmological, quantum, and causal arrows. Section 5.3 presents what I take to be the royal road to a physical arrow, through the representation of time translations in a dynamical theory. Finally, I respond to a prominent critique of this approach to the arrow due to Huw Price in Section 5.4. 5.1 The arrow of time itself According to Price (2011, p.292), understanding the arrow of time requires answering a number of questions: “Is time anisotropic at all, and how could we tell if it is? What 1Eddington himself adopted a strategy similar to that of Boltzmann; for the latter, see Section 5.2.2. 116 could constitute good grounds for taking it to be so, and do we have such grounds?” I will attempt to these questions them in this chapter, would first like to highlight a general principle that they inspire: Spacetime-Evidential Link: An account of the asymmetries of spacetime must identify both a sense in which spacetime itself is asymmetric, as well as some plausible empirical evidence that supports that asymmetry. The difficulty we face in the special case of temporal symmetry is to link it to experience, so that we stand a chance of giving reasonable empirical evidence for or against it. In his seminal book Time’s Arrow and Archimedes’ point, Price (1996, p.16) characterises the difficulty in a picturesque way: think of time as a table that is asymmetric in shape. Whether or not ‘time itself’ is asymmetric is then a conceptually different question from whether the development of a state over time — analogous to the food and drinks forming the ‘content’ of the table — occurs in an asymmetric way, as in Figure 5.2. Figure 5.2: Price’s Table: the asymmetry of the table, like the asymmetry of time, is distinct from the asymmetric placement of its contents. The link that I propose involves a shift of focus in the description of time, from a temporal ‘axis’ or coordinate variable to the more structural, functionalist perspective of time translations. Price himself often adopts e former, writing for example that, “the contents of the block universe appear to be arranged asymmetrically with respect to the temporal axis” (Price 1996, p.17). But, as I argued in Chapter2, time is much more than that: it has rich relational, topological, and other structural properties described 117 by a structure called the time translations, with elements of the form t time shift by two hours, rather than time coordinates like t two o’clock. I will correspondingly interpret the statement that ‘time has an arrow’ to mean that the structure of time encoded by the translations T has an asymmetry, in that t 7! −t is not an automorphism of time translations. And, to replace Price’s notion of the ‘contents’ of time, I will refer to a representation of time translations ' : T ! Aut¹Mº amongst the automorphisms of a state space M, which determines a notion of time evolution among physical states. As I argued in Chapter4, this is part of what it means to be a ‘dynamical’ theory, called the representation view. As a result, the very meaning of a dynamical theory encodes the structure of time translations and their symmetries. Price’s table is not quite the right analogy for the representation view. Given a representation of time translations, the structure of time is projected down onto state space through like the shadow of a tabletop on the floor (Figure 5.3). This suggests that, by studying dynamical asymmetries in a representation of time translations, it is possible to infer an asymmetry or arrow of time itself. That is the approach that I will argue for in this chapter. I will discuss its formulation in detail in Section 5.3. But let me begin with a review of some competing ‘arrows’ of time. Figure 5.3: The structure of time is projected onto a state space by a representation, the way the structure of a table is projected onto the floor by its shadow. 118 5.2 Arrows that misfire We begin with a brief discussion of five well-known approaches to time asymmetry: radiation, thermodynamics, cosmology, quantum measurement, and causation. I will argue that, at least in their current formulations, these approaches do not yet past muster as accounts of the arrow of time, for one of the following two reasons: 1. Heuristics: making essential use of an informal extra-theoretical judgement, which is not explained in any well-supported physics; or 2. Boundary conditions: identifying an asymmetry with a particular temporal devel- opment, by postulating special initial or boundary conditions that force it. My discussion of these particular arrows will in some respects refine the discussion of Price (1996), with whom I agree about these arrows. However, I will diverge from Price’s account in Section 5.3. 5.2.1 The radiation arrow An oscillating charge is associated with an outgoing shell of electromagnetic radiation, which expands with phase velocity equal to the speed of light.2 The phenomenon is analogous to the circular ripples of a water wave when a stone is dropped in a pond. However, like the ripples in a pond, we never seem to observe this radiation in the reverse form of an inward-collapsing shell, as illustrated in Figure 5.4. Is this an arrow of time? The question was discussed in a correspondence between Planck (1897) and Boltzmann (1897), and then more famously in a debate between Ritz (1908) and Ein- stein (1909) in the journal Physikalische Zeitschrift. It has recently generated renewed philosophical interest.3. The phenomenon is particularly puzzling because the laws of 2Thomson (1907, p.217) gave an early derivation of this result, which he identified as analogous to the mechanism producing “Röntgen radiation” or X-rays. 3Popper (1958) seems to have arrived at a similar idea independently. Davies (1977, Chapter 5), Zeh (2007, Chapter 2), and Price (1996, Chapter 3) give classic discussions. Compare also the Ritz-like position of Frisch (2000, 2005, 2006) to the responses of North (2003), Price (2006) and Earman (2011). 119 - Figure 5.4: An expanding radiation shell (left) is easily produced from an oscillating charge, while a collapsing one (right) is not. electromagnetism are time reversal invariant: both the outgoing radiation wave and its time reverse are possible! Ritz argued that the observed asymmetry is due to an additional time asymmetric law of nature, while Einstein maintained that it is just a matter of special boundary conditions: roughly speaking, one would have to begin with a ring of charges oscillating in perfect unison in order to produce a collapsing circular wave, just like a water wave.
Recommended publications
  • The Second Law of Thermodynamics Forbids Time Travel
    Cosmology, 2014, Vol. 18. 212-222 Cosmology.com, 2014 The Second Law Of Thermodynamics Forbids Time Travel Marko Popovic Department of Chemistry and Biochemistry, Brigham Young University, Provo, UT 84602, USA Abstract Four space-time coordinates define one thermodynamic parameter - Volume. Cell/ organism growth is one of the most fundamental properties of living creatures. The growth is characterized by irreversible change of the volume of the cell/organism. This irreversible change of volume (growth of the cell/organism) makes the system irreversibly change its thermodynamic state. Irreversible change of the systems thermodynamic state makes impossible return to the previous state characterized by state parameters. The impossibility to return the system to the previous state leads to conclusion that even to artificially turn back the arrow of time (as a parameter), it is not possible to turn back the state of the organism and its surroundings. Irreversible change of thermodynamic state of the organism is also consequence of the accumulation of entropy during life. So even if we find the way to turn back the time arrow it is impossible to turn back the state of the thermodynamic system (including organism) because of irreversibility of thermodynamic/ physiologic processes in it. Keywords: Time travel, Entropy, Living Organism, Surroundings, Irreversibility Cosmology, 2014, Vol. 18. 212-222 Cosmology.com, 2014 1. Introduction The idea of time travel has fascinated humanity since ancient times and can be found in texts as old as Mahabharata and Talmud. Later it continued to be developed in literature (i.e. Dickens' “A Christmas Carol”, or Twain's “A Connecticut Yankee in King Arthur's Court”…).
    [Show full text]
  • The Arrow of Time Volume 7 Paul Davies Summer 2014 Beyond Center for Fundamental Concepts in Science, Arizona State University, Journal Homepage P.O
    The arrow of time Volume 7 Paul Davies Summer 2014 Beyond Center for Fundamental Concepts in Science, Arizona State University, journal homepage P.O. Box 871504, Tempe, AZ 852871504, USA. www.euresisjournal.org [email protected] Abstract The arrow of time is often conflated with the popular but hopelessly muddled concept of the “flow” or \passage" of time. I argue that the latter is at best an illusion with its roots in neuroscience, at worst a meaningless concept. However, what is beyond dispute is that physical states of the universe evolve in time with an objective and readily-observable directionality. The ultimate origin of this asymmetry in time, which is most famously captured by the second law of thermodynamics and the irreversible rise of entropy, rests with cosmology and the state of the universe at its origin. I trace the various physical processes that contribute to the growth of entropy, and conclude that gravitation holds the key to providing a comprehensive explanation of the elusive arrow. 1. Time's arrow versus the flow of time The subject of time's arrow is bedeviled by ambiguous or poor terminology and the con- flation of concepts. Therefore I shall begin my essay by carefully defining terms. First an uncontentious statement: the states of the physical universe are observed to be distributed asymmetrically with respect to the time dimension (see, for example, Refs. [1, 2, 3, 4]). A simple example is provided by an earthquake: the ground shakes and buildings fall down. We would not expect to see the reverse sequence, in which shaking ground results in the assembly of a building from a heap of rubble.
    [Show full text]
  • Mathematical Languages Shape Our Understanding of Time in Physics Physics Is Formulated in Terms of Timeless, Axiomatic Mathematics
    comment Corrected: Publisher Correction Mathematical languages shape our understanding of time in physics Physics is formulated in terms of timeless, axiomatic mathematics. A formulation on the basis of intuitionist mathematics, built on time-evolving processes, would ofer a perspective that is closer to our experience of physical reality. Nicolas Gisin n 1922 Albert Einstein, the physicist, met in Paris Henri Bergson, the philosopher. IThe two giants debated publicly about time and Einstein concluded with his famous statement: “There is no such thing as the time of the philosopher”. Around the same time, and equally dramatically, mathematicians were debating how to describe the continuum (Fig. 1). The famous German mathematician David Hilbert was promoting formalized mathematics, in which every real number with its infinite series of digits is a completed individual object. On the other side the Dutch mathematician, Luitzen Egbertus Jan Brouwer, was defending the view that each point on the line should be represented as a never-ending process that develops in time, a view known as intuitionistic mathematics (Box 1). Although Brouwer was backed-up by a few well-known figures, like Hermann Weyl 1 and Kurt Gödel2, Hilbert and his supporters clearly won that second debate. Hence, time was expulsed from mathematics and mathematical objects Fig. 1 | Debating mathematicians. David Hilbert (left), supporter of axiomatic mathematics. L. E. J. came to be seen as existing in some Brouwer (right), proposer of intuitionist mathematics. Credit: Left: INTERFOTO / Alamy Stock Photo; idealized Platonistic world. right: reprinted with permission from ref. 18, Springer These two debates had a huge impact on physics.
    [Show full text]
  • HYPOTHESIS: How Defining Nature of Time Might Explain Some of Actual Physics Enigmas P Letizia
    HYPOTHESIS: How Defining Nature of Time Might Explain Some of Actual Physics Enigmas P Letizia To cite this version: P Letizia. HYPOTHESIS: How Defining Nature of Time Might Explain Some of Actual Physics Enigmas: A possible explanation of Dark Energy. 2017. hal-01424099 HAL Id: hal-01424099 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-01424099 Preprint submitted on 3 Jan 2017 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Distributed under a Creative Commons Attribution - NonCommercial - ShareAlike| 4.0 International License SUBMITTED FOR STUDY January 1st, 2017 HYPOTHESIS: How Defining Nature of Time Might Explain Some of Actual Physics Enigmas P. Letizia Abstract Nowadays it seems that understanding the Nature of Time is not more a priority. It seems commonly admitted that Time can not be clearly nor objectively defined. I do not agree with this vision. I am among those who think that Time has an objective reality in Physics. If it has a reality, then it must be understood. My first ambition with this paper was to submit for study a proposition concerning the Nature of Time. However, once defined I understood that this proposition embeds an underlying logic.
    [Show full text]
  • Chaos, Dissipation, Arrow of Time, in Quantum Physics I the National Institute of Standards and Technology Was Established in 1988 by Congress to "Assist
    Chaos, Dissipation, Arrow of Time, in Quantum Physics i The National Institute of Standards and Technology was established in 1988 by Congress to "assist industry in the development of technology . needed to improve product quality, to modernize manufacturing processes, to ensure product reliability . and to facilitate rapid commercialization . of products based on new scientific discoveries." NIST, originally founded as the National Bureau of Standards in 1901, works to strengthen U.S. industry's competitiveness; advance science and engineering; and improve public health, safety, and the environment. One of the agency's basic functions is to develop, maintain, and retain custody of the national standards of measurement, and provide the means and methods for comparing standards used in science, engineering, manufacturing, commerce, industry, and education with the standards adopted or recognized by the Federal Government. As an agency of the U.S. Commerce Department's Technology Administration, NIST conducts basic and applied research in the physical sciences and engineering and performs related services. The Institute does generic and precompetitive work on new and advanced technologies. NIST's research facilities are located at Gaithersburg, MD 20899, and at Boulder, CO 80303. Major technical operating units and their principal activities are listed below. For more information contact the Public Inquiries Desk, 301-975-3058. Technology Services Manufacturing Engineering Laboratory • Manufacturing Technology Centers Program • Precision
    [Show full text]
  • Terminology of Geological Time: Establishment of a Community Standard
    Terminology of geological time: Establishment of a community standard Marie-Pierre Aubry1, John A. Van Couvering2, Nicholas Christie-Blick3, Ed Landing4, Brian R. Pratt5, Donald E. Owen6 and Ismael Ferrusquía-Villafranca7 1Department of Earth and Planetary Sciences, Rutgers University, Piscataway NJ 08854, USA; email: [email protected] 2Micropaleontology Press, New York, NY 10001, USA email: [email protected] 3Department of Earth and Environmental Sciences and Lamont-Doherty Earth Observatory of Columbia University, Palisades NY 10964, USA email: [email protected] 4New York State Museum, Madison Avenue, Albany NY 12230, USA email: [email protected] 5Department of Geological Sciences, University of Saskatchewan, Saskatoon SK7N 5E2, Canada; email: [email protected] 6Department of Earth and Space Sciences, Lamar University, Beaumont TX 77710 USA email: [email protected] 7Universidad Nacional Autónomo de México, Instituto de Geologia, México DF email: [email protected] ABSTRACT: It has been recommended that geological time be described in a single set of terms and according to metric or SI (“Système International d’Unités”) standards, to ensure “worldwide unification of measurement”. While any effort to improve communication in sci- entific research and writing is to be encouraged, we are also concerned that fundamental differences between date and duration, in the way that our profession expresses geological time, would be lost in such an oversimplified terminology. In addition, no precise value for ‘year’ in the SI base unit of second has been accepted by the international bodies. Under any circumstances, however, it remains the fact that geologi- cal dates – as points in time – are not relevant to the SI.
    [Show full text]
  • In the Experiments in Which Alpha-Activity Was Measured Using Collimators Directed at East and West
    Volume 1 PROGRESS IN PHYSICS January, 2010 “The Arrow of Time” in the Experiments in which Alpha-Activity was Measured Using Collimators Directed at East and West Simon E. Shnoll, Ilya A. Rubinsteiny, and Nikolai N. Vedenkiny Department of Physics, Moscow State University, Moscow 119992, Russia Inst. of Theor. and Experim. Biophysics, Russian Acad. of Sci., Pushchino, Moscow Region, 142290, Russia Puschino State University, Prospect Nauki 3, Pushchino, Moscow Region, 142290, Russia ySkobeltsin’s Institute of Nuclear Physics, Moscow State University, Moscow 119991, Russia E-mail: [email protected] In our previous paper (Shnoll and Rubinstein, Progress in Physics, 2009, v. 2, 83–95), we briefly reported about a phenomenon, which can be called the “arrow of time”: when we compared histograms constructed from the results of 239-Pu alpha-activity measurements that were obtained using West- and East-directed collimators, daytime series of the “eastern” histograms were similar to the inverted series of the following night, whereas daytime series of the “western” histograms resembled the inverted series of the preceding night. Here we consider this phenomenon in more detail. 1 Introduction As follows from all our past results, the fine structure of the spectrum of amplitude fluctuations (the shape of the corre- sponding histograms) is determined by the motion (orienta- tion) of the object studied (the laboratory) in relation to spa- tial inhomogeneities [2]. The spatial pattern (arrangement in space) of these inhomogeneities is stable: as the Earth ro- tates about its axis and moves along the circumsolar orbit, similar histogram shapes are realized repeatedly with the cor- responding periods (daily, near-monthly, yearly) [3, 4].
    [Show full text]
  • A Measure of Change Brittany A
    University of South Carolina Scholar Commons Theses and Dissertations Spring 2019 Time: A Measure of Change Brittany A. Gentry Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarcommons.sc.edu/etd Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Gentry, B. A.(2019). Time: A Measure of Change. (Doctoral dissertation). Retrieved from https://scholarcommons.sc.edu/etd/5247 This Open Access Dissertation is brought to you by Scholar Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Scholar Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Time: A Measure of Change By Brittany A. Gentry Bachelor of Arts Houghton College, 2009 ________________________________________________ Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements For the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy College of Arts and Sciences University of South Carolina 2019 Accepted by Michael Dickson, Major Professor Leah McClimans, Committee Member Thomas Burke, Committee Member Alexander Pruss, Committee Member Cheryl L. Addy, Vice Provost and Dean of the Graduate School ©Copyright by Brittany A. Gentry, 2019 All Rights Reserved ii Acknowledgements I would like to thank Michael Dickson, my dissertation advisor, for extensive comments on numerous drafts over the last several years and for his patience and encouragement throughout this process. I would also like to thank my other committee members, Leah McClimans, Thomas Burke, and Alexander Pruss, for their comments and recommendations along the way. Finally, I am grateful to fellow students and professors at the University of South Carolina, the audience at the International Society for the Philosophy of Time conference at Wake Forest University, NC, and anonymous reviewers for helpful comments on various drafts of portions of this dissertation.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Temporal Arrows in Space-Time Temporality
    Temporal Arrows in Space-Time Temporality (…) has nothing to do with mechanics. It has to do with statistical mechanics, thermodynamics (…).C. Rovelli, in Dieks, 2006, 35 Abstract The prevailing current of thought in both physics and philosophy is that relativistic space-time provides no means for the objective measurement of the passage of time. Kurt Gödel, for instance, denied the possibility of an objective lapse of time, both in the Special and the General theory of relativity. From this failure many writers have inferred that a static block universe is the only acceptable conceptual consequence of a four-dimensional world. The aim of this paper is to investigate how arrows of time could be measured objectively in space-time. In order to carry out this investigation it is proposed to consider both local and global arrows of time. In particular the investigation will focus on a) invariant thermodynamic parameters in both the Special and the General theory for local regions of space-time (passage of time); b) the evolution of the universe under appropriate boundary conditions for the whole of space-time (arrow of time), as envisaged in modern quantum cosmology. The upshot of this investigation is that a number of invariant physical indicators in space-time can be found, which would allow observers to measure the lapse of time and to infer both the existence of an objective passage and an arrow of time. Keywords Arrows of time; entropy; four-dimensional world; invariance; space-time; thermodynamics 1 I. Introduction Philosophical debates about the nature of space-time often centre on questions of its ontology, i.e.
    [Show full text]
  • The Origin of the Universe and the Arrow of Time
    The Origin of the Universe and the Arrow of Time Sean M Carroll Caltech, Pasadena, CA One of the most obvious facts about the universe is that the past is different from the future. The world around us is full of irreversible processes: we can turn an egg into an omelet, but can't turn an omelet into an egg. Physicists have codified this difference into the Second Law of Thermodynamics: the entropy of a closed system always increases with time. But why? The ultimate explanation is to be found in cosmology: special conditions in the early universe are responsible for the arrow of time. I will talk about the nature of time, the origin of entropy, and how what happened before the Big Bang may be responsible for the arrow of time we observe today. Sean Carroll is a Senior Research Associate in Physics at the California Institute of Technology. He received his Ph.D. in 1993 from Harvard University, and has previously worked as a postdoctoral researcher at the Center for Theoretical Physics at MIT and at the Institute for Theoretical Physics at the University of California, Santa Barbara, as well as on the faculty at the University of Chicago. His research ranges over a number of topics in theoretical physics, focusing on cosmology, field theory, particle physics, and gravitation. Carroll is the author of From Eternity to Here: The Quest for the Ultimate Theory of Time, an upcoming popular-level book on cosmology and the arrow of time. He has also written a graduate textbook, Spacetime and Geometry: An Introduction to General Relativity, and recorded a set of lectures on cosmology for the Teaching Company.
    [Show full text]
  • The Deadly Affairs of John Figaro Newton Or a Senseless Appeal to Reason and an Elegy for the Dreaming
    The deadly affairs of John Figaro Newton or a senseless appeal to reason and an elegy for the dreaming Item Type Thesis Authors Campbell, Regan Download date 26/09/2021 19:18:08 Link to Item http://hdl.handle.net/11122/11260 THE DEADLY AFFAIRS OF JOHN FIGARO NEWTON OR A SENSELESS APPEAL TO REASON AND AN ELEGY FOR THE DREAMING By Regan Campbell, B.F.A. A Thesis Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Master of Fine Arts in Creative Writing University of Alaska Fairbanks May 2020 APPROVED: Daryl Farmer, Committee Chair Leonard Kamerling, Committee Member Chris Coffman, Committee Member Rich Carr, Chair Department of English Todd Sherman, Dean College of Liberal Arts Michael Castellini, Dean of the Graduate School Abstract Are you really you? Are your memories true? John “Fig” Newton thinks much the same as you do. But in three separate episodes of his life, he comes to see things are a little more strange and less straightforward than everyone around him has been inured to the point of pretending they are; maybe it's all some kind of bizarre form of torture for someone with the misfortune of assuming they embody a real and actual person. Whatever the case, Fig is sure he can't trust that truth exists, and over the course of his many doomed relationships and professional foibles, he continually strives to find another like him—someone incandescent with rage, and preferably, as insane and beautiful as he. i Extracts “Whose blood do you still thirst for? But sacred philosophy will shackle your success, for whatsoever may be your momentary triumph or the disorder of this anarchy, you will never govern enlightened men.
    [Show full text]
  • Causality Is an Effect, II
    entropy Article Causality Is an Effect, II Lawrence S. Schulman Physics Department, Clarkson University, Potsdam, NY 13699-5820, USA; [email protected] Abstract: Causality follows the thermodynamic arrow of time, where the latter is defined by the direction of entropy increase. After a brief review of an earlier version of this article, rooted in classical mechanics, we give a quantum generalization of the results. The quantum proofs are limited to a gas of Gaussian wave packets. Keywords: causality; arrow of time; entropy increase; quantum generalization; Gaussian wave packets 1. Introduction The history of multiple time boundary conditions goes back—as far as I know—to Schottky [1,2], who, in 1921, considered a single slice of time inadequate for prediction or retrodiction (see AppendixA). There was later work of Watanabe [ 3] concerned with predic- tion and retrodiction. Then, Schulman [4] uses this as a conceptual way to eliminate “initial conditions” prejudice from Gold’s [5] rationale for the arrow of time and Wheeler [6,7] discusses two time boundary conditions. Gell–Mann and Hartle also contributed to this subject [8] and include a review of some previous work. Finally, Aharonov et al. [9,10] pro- posed that this could solve the measurement problem of quantum mechanics, although this is disputed [11]. See also AppendixB. This formalism has also allowed me to come to a conclusion: effect follows cause in the direction of entropy increase. This result is not unanticipated; most likely everything Citation: Schulman, L.S. Causality Is having to do with arrows of time has been anticipated. What is unusual, however, is the an Effect, II.
    [Show full text]