Causal Finitism and the Kalaam Argument
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
Finitism, Divisibility, and the Beginning of the Universe: Replies to Loke and Dumsday
This is a preprint of an article whose final and definitive form will be published in the Australasian Journal of Philosophy. The Australasian Journal of Philosophy is available online at: http://www.tandf.co.uk/journals/. FINITISM, DIVISIBILITY, AND THE BEGINNING OF THE UNIVERSE: REPLIES TO LOKE AND DUMSDAY Stephen Puryear North Carolina State University Some philosophers contend that the past must be finite in duration, because otherwise reaching the present would have involved the sequential occurrence of an actual infinity of events, which they regard as impossible. I recently developed a new objection to this finitist argument, to which Andrew Ter Ern Loke and Travis Dumsday have replied. Here I respond to the three main points raised in their replies. Keywords: Space, time, continuity, infinity, creation 1. Introduction Some philosophers argue that the universe must have had a beginning, because otherwise reaching the present would have required something impossible, namely, the occurrence or ‘traversal’ of an actually infinite sequence of events. But this argument faces the objection that actual infinities are traversed all the time: for example, whenever a finite period of time elapses [Morriston 2002: 162; Sinnott-Armstrong 2004: 42–3]. Let us call these the finitist argument and the Zeno objection. In response to the Zeno objection, the most ardent proponent of the finitist argument in our day, William Lane Craig [Craig and Sinclair 2009: 112–13, 119; cf. Craig and Smith 1993: 27–30], has taken the position that ‘time is logically prior to the divisions we make within it’. On this view, time divides into parts only in so far as we divide it, and thus divides into only a finite number of parts. -
Thomas Aquinas' Argument from Motion & the Kalām Cosmological
University of Central Florida STARS Honors Undergraduate Theses UCF Theses and Dissertations 2020 Rethinking Causality: Thomas Aquinas' Argument From Motion & the Kalām Cosmological Argument Derwin Sánchez Jr. University of Central Florida Part of the Philosophy Commons Find similar works at: https://stars.library.ucf.edu/honorstheses University of Central Florida Libraries http://library.ucf.edu This Open Access is brought to you for free and open access by the UCF Theses and Dissertations at STARS. It has been accepted for inclusion in Honors Undergraduate Theses by an authorized administrator of STARS. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Recommended Citation Sánchez, Derwin Jr., "Rethinking Causality: Thomas Aquinas' Argument From Motion & the Kalām Cosmological Argument" (2020). Honors Undergraduate Theses. 858. https://stars.library.ucf.edu/honorstheses/858 RETHINKING CAUSALITY: THOMAS AQUINAS’ ARGUMENT FROM MOTION & THE KALĀM COSMOLOGICAL ARGUMENT by DERWIN SANCHEZ, JR. A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Honors in the Major Program in Philosophy in the College of Arts and Humanities and in the Burnett Honors College at the University of Central Florida Orlando, Florida Fall Term 2020 Thesis Chair: Dr. Cyrus Zargar i ABSTRACT Ever since they were formulated in the Middle Ages, St. Thomas Aquinas’ famous Five Ways to demonstrate the existence of God have been frequently debated. During this process there have been several misconceptions of what Aquinas actually meant, especially when discussing his cosmological arguments. While previous researchers have managed to tease out why Aquinas accepts some infinite regresses and rejects others, I attempt to add on to this by demonstrating the centrality of his metaphysics in his argument from motion. -
Epistemic Humility, Arguments from Evil, and Moral Skepticism
Jonathan L. Kvanvig c02.tex V1 - June 4, 2009 11:16am Page 17 2 Epistemic Humility, Arguments from Evil, and Moral Skepticism Daniel Howard-Snyder Many arguments from evil at least tacitly rely on something like the following line of thought: The Inference. On sustained reflection, we don’t see how any reason we know of would justify God in permitting all the evil in the world; ¹ FN:1 therefore, there is no reason that would justify God. The conclusion is frequently more nuanced: ‘‘it is very likely that there is no such reason’’ or ‘‘more likely than not’’ or ‘‘more likely than it otherwise would be’’. Some critics reject the premise: we do see how some reason would justify God. These are the theodicists. Others accept the premise but reject the conclusion: the evidence or non-evidential warrant for God’s existence is much better than the evidence for no justifying reason. These are the natural theologians and Reformed epistemologists. Some critics, however, insist that even if the premise is true and even if there isn’t better evidence or non-evidential warrant for God’s existence, we should For comments on previous drafts, I thank Michael Almeida, Nick Beckstead, Michael Bergmann, Rebecca Copenhaver, Trent Dougherty, Robert Epperson, Frances Howard- Snyder, Hud Hudson, Shieva Kleinschmidt, Christian Lee, Wes Morriston, Michael Murray, Robert Pasnau, Alexander Pruss, Michael Rea, John Schellenberg, Michael Tooley, Ryan Wasserman, Dennis Whitcomb, and three anonymous referees. ¹ Three notes in one. (1) The theistic God is the God in question here. At a minimum, this God has enough power and knowledge to prevent evil, and is unsurpassable in moral goodness. -
Aristotelian Finitism
Synthese DOI 10.1007/s11229-015-0827-9 S.I. : INFINITY Aristotelian finitism Tamer Nawar1 Received: 12 January 2014 / Accepted: 25 June 2015 © Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015 Abstract It is widely known that Aristotle rules out the existence of actual infinities but allows for potential infinities. However, precisely why Aristotle should deny the existence of actual infinities remains somewhat obscure and has received relatively little attention in the secondary literature. In this paper I investigate the motivations of Aristotle’s finitism and offer a careful examination of some of the arguments con- sidered by Aristotle both in favour of and against the existence of actual infinities. I argue that Aristotle has good reason to resist the traditional arguments offered in favour of the existence of the infinite and that, while there is a lacuna in his own ‘logi- cal’ arguments against actual infinities, his arguments against the existence of infinite magnitude and number are valid and more well grounded than commonly supposed. Keywords Aristotle · Aristotelian commentators · Infinity · Mathematics · Metaphysics 1 Introduction It is widely known that Aristotle embraced some sort of finitism and denied the exis- tence of so-called ‘actual infinities’ while allowing for the existence of ‘potential infinities’. It is difficult to overestimate the influence of Aristotle’s views on this score and the denial of the (actual) existence of infinities became a commonplace among philosophers for over two thousand years. However, the precise grounds for Aristo- tle’s finitism have not been discussed in much detail and, insofar as they have received attention, his reasons for ruling out the existence of (actual) infinities have often been B Tamer Nawar [email protected] 1 University of Oxford, 21 Millway Close, Oxford OX2 8BJ, UK 123 Synthese deemed obscure or ad hoc (e.g. -
ABSTRACT Ut Omnes Unum Sint: Examining the Presence of The
ABSTRACT Ut Omnes Unum Sint: Examining the Presence of the Catholic Intellectual Tradition at a Baptist University Carmen M. Galvan Director: Dr. Barry Hankins, Ph.D. of History This research collected firsthand accounts of faith and teaching from both Catholic and non-Catholic faculty at Baylor University in order to prove that Baylor has intentionally sought and hired additional Roman Catholic faculty in order to strengthen the university’s religious identity. The appeal of Catholics was found to be the Catholic intellectual tradition, which holds that faith be integrated with learning in all aspects of academia. The research revealed four major commonalities of Baylor’s Catholic hiring: 1) the university hiring process, 2) the integration of faith and learning in the classroom, 3) the positive and/or negative experiences faculty have had at Baylor, and 4) the faculty’s perspective of Baylor 2012 and its future. UT OMNES UNUM SINT: EXAMINING THE PRESENCE OF THE CATHOLIC INTELLECTUAL TRADITION AT A BAPTIST UNIVERSITY By Carmen M. Galvan Waco, Texas May 2012 TABLE OF CONTENTS PREFACE ……………………………………………………………………………. iii ACKNOWLEDGMENTS …………………………………………………………… iv DEDICATION ………………………………………………………………………... v Chapter 1. INTRODUCTION ……………………………………………………………. 1 Purpose of Thesis A Rift of Religion 2. METHODOLOGY …………………………………………………………… 12 Selection Process Data Collection, Coding, and Analysis 3. HIRING OF ROMAN CATHOLICS AT BAYLOR UNIVERSITY………… 21 Administrative Interviews Commitment to Faith 4. CATHOLIC INTELLECTUAL TRADITION AT BAYLOR UNIVERSITY .. 32 Tradition of Faith in the Classroom Catholic Faculty in a Baptist Environment Conclusion BIBLIOGRAPHY…………………………………………………………………….... 45 ii PREFACE “But you’re Catholic … why are you going to a Baptist university?” Right after my choice of major, this question of spiritual identity was one of the most common I heard as an entering freshman at Baylor University. -
Evolutionary Argument Against Naturalism?” International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 69.3 (2010): 193–204
1 On Plantinga on Belief in Naturalism1 Troy Cross Introduction Naturalism, according to Alvin Plantinga, is the thesis “that there is no such person as God or anything at all like God” (2011b, 435; see also, 2002a, 1; 2011a, vix), and one could be forgiven for thinking that what Plantinga calls his “Evolutionary Argument Against Naturalism”, or “EAAN”, which he has refined and defended for over two decades, is an argument against that thesis (1991, 1993, 2002a, 2002b, 2011a, 2011b). But that would be a mistake. The conclusion of the EAAN is not about the truth of naturalism but about the rationality of believing naturalism to be true: it is that one cannot rationally and reflectively believe that contemporary evolutionary theory is correct about our origins while also believing that neither God nor anything like God exists.2 The difference between truth and rational belief is important here. Consider Moore’s paradoxical sentence: “I don’t believe it’s raining but as a matter of fact it is” (Moore, 209). Nothing prevents that sentence, or others like it, from being true. If you 1 For instructive conversations on this topic I am indebted to John Bang, George Bealer, Mark Bedau, Eliyah Cohen, Bryan Cross, Augie Faller, Emma Handte, Elad Gilo, Nick Gigliotti, John Hare, Jordan Horowitz, Paul Hovda, Alexander Pruss, Margaret Scharle, Derek Schiller, Mackenzie Sullivan, and Carol Voeller. I also wish to thank audiences at Reed College and the University of Nebraska Omaha where I presented early versions of some of this material. Anthony Nguyen gave me many helpful comments on a draft. -
St. Thomas Summer Seminars in Philosophy of Religion And
Recent PhDs and current graduate students in philosophy, theology, or religious studies are invited to apply to participate in the 2010 St. Thomas Summer Seminar in Philosophy of Religion and Philosophical Theology. The 2010 St. Thomas Summer Seminar in Philosophy of Religion and Philosophical Theology June 15—July 2, 2010 University of Saint Thomas, Saint Paul, Minnesota TOPICS AND SPEAKERS ORGANIZED BY THE EPISTEMOLOGY OF THE EPISTEMOLOGY OF RELIGIOUS BELIEF DISAGREEMENT Dean Zimmerman Alvin Plantinga (Notre Dame) and Roger White (M.I.T.) and (Rutgers) Richard Feldman (Rochester) Thomas Kelly (Princeton) Michael Rota SCIENCE AND RELIGION REDUCTIONISM AND THE (University of St. Thomas) Alvin Plantinga (Notre Dame) and PHILOSOPHY OF BIOLOGY Elliott Sober (UW-Madison) Alan Love (University of Minnesota) THE COSMOLOGICAL ARGUMENT WRITING FOR AUDIENCES Alexander Pruss (Baylor) and OUTSIDE THE ACADEMY Peter van Inwagen (Notre Dame) Peter Kreeft (Boston College) THE PROBLEM OF EVIL Peter van Inwagen (Notre Dame) and Evan Fales (University of Iowa) http://www.stthomas.edu/philosophy/templeton/project.html Twenty participants will be selected; each will receive a stipend of $2,800 and will be provided with accommodations and meals for the duration of the seminar. CONTACT APPLICATION DEADLINE: Dr. Michael Rota Applications must be received by December 1, 2009 St. Thomas Philosophy of Religion Project For information on how to apply, go to http://www.stthomas.edu/philosophy/templeton/project.html. Department of Philosophy, JRC 241 University of St. Thomas This program is funded by a generous grant from the John Templeton Foundation. 2115 Summit Avenue Saint Paul, MN 55105-1096 Email: [email protected] . -
From Restricted to Full Omniscience
Religious Studies, Page 1 of 8. f Cambridge University Press 2010 doi:10.1017/S0034412510000144 From restricted to full omniscience ALEXANDERR.PRUSS Baylor University, One Bear Place #97273, Waco, TX 76798-7273 e-mail: [email protected] Abstract: Some, notably Peter van Inwagen, in order to avoid problems with free will and omniscience, replace the condition that an omniscient being knows all true propositions with a version of the apparently weaker condition that an omniscient being knows all knowable true propositions. I shall show that the apparently weaker condition, when conjoined with uncontroversial claims and the logical closure of an omniscient being’s knowledge, still yields the claim that an omniscient being knows all true propositions. Introduction Peter van Inwagen has argued that God does not know what we shall freely do.1 But van Inwagen does not embrace open-future views on which there is no fact of the matter about what we shall freely do. There is such a fact, but on van Inwagen’s view, God does not know it. Nonetheless, van Inwagen holds that God is omniscient, because, roughly speaking, God knows every true proposition that can be known. I shall show, however, that the statement that God knows every knowable truth, as well as the precise statement of van Inwagen’s ‘tentative’ account, have the consequence that God knows every true proposition, as long as we assume that God’s knowledge is closed under conjunction and tautological consequence, together with some uncontroversial claims and, in the case of van Inwagen’s account, the non-triviality claim that the account requires an om- niscient being to now know some contingent truths. -
The Consequence of the Consequence Argument∗
The Consequence of the Consequence Argument∗ Marco Hausmann Abstract The aim of my paper is to compare three alternative formal reconstructions of van Inwagen's famous argument for incompati- bilism. In the first part of my paper, I examine van Inwagen's own reconstruction within a propositional modal logic. I point out that, due to the expressive limitations of his propositional modal logic, van Inwagen is unable to argue directly (that is, within his formal framework) for incompatibilism. In the second part of my paper, I suggest to reconstruct van Inwagen's argument within a first-order predicate logic. I show, however, that even though this reconstruction is not susceptible to the same objection, this reconstruction can be shown to be inconsistent (given van Inwagen's own assumptions). At the end of my paper, I suggest to reconstruct van Inwagen's argument within a quantified counterfactual logic with propositional quantifiers. I show that within this formal framework van Inwagen would not only be able to argue directly for incompatibilism, he would also be able to argue for crucial assumptions of his argument. Keywords: free will, determinism, consequence argument, counter- factual logic 1 Introduction Incompatibilism, as I understand it, is the view that there is no free will if determinism is true. Peter van Inwagen has developed a much discussed argument for incompatibilism. His argument runs as follows: ∗This paper won the SOPhiA 2019 Best Paper Award at the Salzburg Conference for Young Analytic Philosophy, September 18{20, 2019. Kriterion { Journal of Philosophy, 2020, 34(4): 45{70. http://www.kriterion-journal-of-philosophy.org c 2020 The author 46 KRITERION { Journal of Philosophy, 2020, 34(4): 45{70 If determinism is true, then our acts are the consequences " of the laws of nature and events in the remote past. -
On Two Problems of Divine Simplicity by Alexander Pruss
7 On Two Problems of Divine Simplicity Alexander R. Pruss I. INTRODUCTION The doctrine of divine simplicity claims that there is no ontological composition in God of any sort, whether of matter and form, or of essence and accident, or of this attribute and that attribute considered as ontologically distinct. The doctrine is a traditional part of Christianity and Judaism, and can be argued to be a reasonable development of the monotheistic ideal of seeing a single entity at the root of reality. Thus Maimonedes (1956: Part I, Chapter 50) wrote that ‘[t]hose who believe that God is One, and has many attributes, declare the unity with their lips, and assume plurality in their thoughts’, which he said was as bad as the case of Christians with their doctrine of the Trinity. While I disagree that the doctrine of the Trinity would violate the basic ideals of monotheism, Maimonedes may be right that the denial of the doctrine of simplicity would. However it is not my point here to argue for the doctrine of divine simplicity, but to defend it against two major objections. For, divine simplicity, like the complementary doctrine of the Trinity, does lead to intellectual difficulties. I want to consider two objections in particular, and argue that thinking in terms of an account of divine simplicity that was introduced by Graham Oppy (2003), and later independently developed by Bergmann and Brower (forthcoming)¹ as well as Pruss I am grateful to the audience for the discussion at my presentation at the Society of Christian Philosophers satellite session at the American Catholic Philosophical Association annual meeting in 2003. -
Gödel on Finitism, Constructivity and Hilbert's Program
Lieber Herr Bernays!, Lieber Herr Gödel! Gödel on finitism, constructivity and Hilbert’s program Solomon Feferman 1. Gödel, Bernays, and Hilbert. The correspondence between Paul Bernays and Kurt Gödel is one of the most extensive in the two volumes of Gödel’s collected works devoted to his letters of (primarily) scientific, philosophical and historical interest. It ranges from 1930 to 1975 and deals with a rich body of logical and philosophical issues, including the incompleteness theorems, finitism, constructivity, set theory, the philosophy of mathematics, and post- Kantian philosophy, and contains Gödel’s thoughts on many topics that are not expressed elsewhere. In addition, it testifies to their life-long warm personal relationship. I have given a detailed synopsis of the Bernays Gödel correspondence, with explanatory background, in my introductory note to it in Vol. IV of Gödel’s Collected Works, pp. 41- 79.1 My purpose here is to focus on only one group of interrelated topics from these exchanges, namely the light that ittogether with assorted published and unpublished articles and lectures by Gödelthrows on his perennial preoccupations with the limits of finitism, its relations to constructivity, and the significance of his incompleteness theorems for Hilbert’s program.2 In that connection, this piece has an important subtext, namely the shadow of Hilbert that loomed over Gödel from the beginning to the end of his career. 1 The five volumes of Gödel’s Collected Works (1986-2003) are referred to below, respectively, as CW I, II, III, IV and V. CW I consists of the publications 1929-1936, CW II of the publications 1938-1974, CW III of unpublished essays and letters, CW IV of correspondence A-G, and CW V of correspondence H-Z. -
The Regress Argument for Moral Skepticism
Sara Ash Writing Sample The Regress Argument for Moral Skepticism Introduction An important epistemological question about morality is whether we can be justified in believing any moral claim. Justification of moral beliefs is an important aspect of morality, because without reasons for believing moral claims, morality becomes unacceptably arbitrary. In this paper, I will present and explain the regress argument for moral justification skepticism. Afterward, I will present objections to some of the premises in the argument and accompanying responses to those objections. I conclude at the end of this paper that the regress argument, while valid, is probably not sound and therefore does not successfully undermine moral justification. The Infinite Regress Argument The infinite regress argument is an argument for general skepticism, but Walter Sinnott- Armstrong has adapted the argument to morality and suggests that “If the problems raised by these arguments cannot be solved at least in morality, then we cannot be justified in believing any moral claims” (9). This argument contains a series of conditionals whose consequents comprise disjunctions. By applying the rules of disjunctive syllogism and modus tollens, the argument is intended to show that none of the ways in which a person can be justified in believing a moral claim works. Sinnott-Armstrong’s clear and concise formulation of the infinite regress argument taken from his paper “Moral Skepticism and Justification” in the anthology Moral Knowledge?: New Readings in Moral Epistemology