Part III Mathesis Universalis and Charateristica Universalis

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Part III Mathesis Universalis and Charateristica Universalis Part III Mathesis universalis and charateristica universalis Chapter 8 The “merely mechanical” vs. the “scab of symbols”: seventeenth century disputes over the criteria of mathematical rigor Douglas M. Jesseph Abstract This paper deals with seventeenth-century understandings of rig- orous demonstration. Although there was a widely-shared concept of rigor that has its origins in classical Greek sources, philosophers in the early mod- ern period were divided over how to characterize the ultimate foundation for mathematics. One group (whom I term the “geometric foundationalists”) held that seeming physical concepts such as space, body and motion, were prop- erly foundational. The other group (whom I call “algebraic foundationalists”) claimed that the true foundations of mathematics must be abstract notions of quantity which were the subject of algebra, or even a more general math- esis universalis that encompassed all reasoning about number and measure. The geometric foundationalists faced the objection that they had introduced “merely mechanical” or insufficiently abstract principles into the foundations of mathematics. In contrast, the algebraic foundationalists needed to rebut the accusation that they based mathematics on a “scab of symbols”, or empty no- tation divorced from anything real or substantial. I argue that this episode offers some useful insights into general questions about foundations, and can help us understand what is at stake in disputes over foundational issues, as well as how such disputes rise to prominence and then fade away. 8.1 Introduction One of the things that philosophers find most intriguing about mathematics is the rigor of its demonstrations. A properly developed mathematical theory is one which starts with clearly conceived and well-understood first princi- ples, then unfolds via deductively valid inferences to reach conclusions that, however outr´e or surprising they may seem to untutored common sense, are 273 274 Douglas M. Jesseph every bit as secure as the first principles on which they depend. This picture of mathematics has convinced many philosophers that it is the pinnacle of hu- man intellectual achievement, something that can serve as a bulwark against the challenges of skepticism, and whose deductive structure might serve as a model for philosophical theorizing. We can see this dynamic at work in the famous anecdote concerning Thomas Hobbes’s discovery of mathematics as related by his friend John Aubrey: He was forty years old before he looked on geometry; which happened accidentally. Being in a gentleman’s library Euclid’s Elements lay open, and ’twas the forty-seventh proposition in the first book. He read the proposition. “By God,” said he, “this is impossible!” So he reads the demonstration of it, which referred him back to such a proof; which referred him back to another, which he also read. Et sic deinceps, that at last he was demonstratively convinced of that truth. This made him in love with geometry. (Aubrey 1898, p. 322) As my concern here is with the interaction between philosophy and math- ematics in the seventeenth-century, it is fitting to begin with an anecdote involving Hobbes, even if his mathematical misadventures featured numerous outrageously poor attempts to solve such problems as the squaring of the circle or the duplication of the cube.1 The issue I wish to discuss concerns seventeenth-century understandings of what it is that makes mathematical (and perhaps more specifically geo- metric) demonstrations rigorous. Although there was a widely-shared general characterization of rigor that has its origins in classical Greek approaches to the philosophy of mathematics, philosophers and mathematicians in the early modern period were divided over whether the ultimate foundation for math- ematics should be sought in seemingly physical concepts such as space, body and motion, or in more abstract notions of quantity which were the subject of algebra, or perhaps a more general mathesis universalis that encompassed all reasoning about number and measure. Those who sought to ground the whole of mathematics in concepts such as space and motion had to confront the objection that they had introduced “merely mechanical” or insufficiently abstract principles into the foundations of mathematics. On the other hand, proponents of a mathesis universalis needed to rebut the accusation that, in doing so, they based the whole science on a “scab of symbols,” or a jumble of empty notation divorced from anything real or substantial. I begin with a brief overview of the classical Greek point of view on the subject, as exemplified in the works of Euclid and his neo-Platonist commenta- tor Proclus Diadochus. I then consider the “geometric foundationalism” pro- pounded by Isaac Newton and Isaac Barrow (among others), which seeks to ground all of mathematic in fundamental geometric notions. I will then inves- 1 For an account of Hobbes’s failed campaign for mathematical glory, see Jesseph (1999) 8 Criteria of mathematical rigor 275 tigate the “algebraic foundationalism” put forward by John Wallis, Descartes, and others. In the end, I think this episode offers some useful insights into general questions about foundations, and it can help us understand what is at stake in disputes over foundational issues, as well as how such disputes rise to prominence and then fade away. 8.2 Euclid, Proclus, and the Classical Point of View Classical Greek authors took pure mathematics to consist of two essentially different subjects: arithmetic on the one hand and geometry on the other.2 The applied mathematical sciences, which include such things as astronomy, music, optics, mechanics, were taken to differ from the pure sciences because the pure part is – to quote Proclus – “concerned with intelligibles only,” while the applied part of mathematics “work[s] with perceptibles and [is] in contact with them” (Proclus 1970, p. 31). Classically conceived, then, the pure sciences of geometry and arithmetic are distinguished from one another by having different objects. The object of arithmetic is discrete quantity (“number” or ἀριθμός in the Greek), while the object of geometry is continuous quantity (“magnitude” or μέγεθος in Greek). Thus understood, the two branches of pure mathematics can be developed in separate ways and there is no question of attempting to “reduce” one to the other or to show that one is in some sense the genuine foundation of all mathematics. This pluralistic approach to the philosophy of mathematics does not presume or require that the different mathematical sciences be reduced to some underlying foundational science. This does not, however, imply that classical authors always conceived of the two branches of mathematics as of equal importance. Proclus took the view that, although pure geometry was entirely independent of arithmetic, geome- try nevertheless “occupies a place second to arithmetic,” because (in keeping with his neo-Platonist epistemology) everything knowable must ultimately be expressed in terms of commensurable ratios (Proclus 1970, p. 39). The princi- pal point here is that classical authors saw no relation of dependence between the truths of arithmetic and the truths of geometry. This becomes clearer in the presentation of the theory of ratios in Euclid’s Elements. Book V develops the theory of proportions in the context of con- tinuous magnitudes, and Book VII offers an account of ratio and proportion as applied to discrete quantities or “numbers” (ἀριθμόι). It was, of course, well understood in the ancient world that the theory of proportions in Book 2 On the Greek classification of the geometrical sciences, see Heath (1931), Klein (1968, Part I) and Knorr (1981) 276 Douglas M. Jesseph VII could be taken as just a special case of the theory developed in Book V. Aristotle remarked that it might seem that the proportion alternates for things as numbers and as lines and as solids and as times – as once it used to be proved separately, though it is possible for it to be proved of all cases by a single demonstration. But because all these things – numbers, lengths, times, solids – do not constitute a single named item and differ in sort from one another, it used to be taken separately (Posterior Analytics 74a 18-22) Thus, rather than assuming that there is one underlying notion of proportion that applies equally to continuous magnitudes and discrete multitudes, the tradition in Greek geometry was to develop the two theories separately. This simply reflects, and indeed reinforces, the notion that geometry and arithmetic are autonomous sciences. Given that they are separate sciences, arithmetic and geometry will have to have separate first principles. The first principles of a demonstrative science were traditionally distinguished into three classes: axioms, definitions, and postulates. Axioms or “common notions” apply to any science whatever and include such general principles as “things which are equal to the same thing are equal to one another” or “if equals be subtracted from equals, the remainders are equal” (Elements 1, Ax. 1, 3). These apply universally to any subject matter, but they are insufficiently specific to develop a particular science. Definitions are principles specific to a given science and set out the essential properties of the objects of that science. So, in the case of arithmetic we have the definition of a unit as “that by virtue of which each of the things that exist is called one,” and a number as “a collection of units” (Elements 7, Def. 1, 2). In the case of geometry, we require
Recommended publications
  • Reconciling Aesthetic Philosophy and the Cartesian Paradigm Taryn Sweeney IDVSA
    Maine State Library Digital Maine Academic Research and Dissertations Maine State Library Special Collections 2018 Aesthesis Universalis: Reconciling Aesthetic Philosophy and the Cartesian Paradigm Taryn Sweeney IDVSA Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalmaine.com/academic Recommended Citation Sweeney, Taryn, "Aesthesis Universalis: Reconciling Aesthetic Philosophy and the Cartesian Paradigm" (2018). Academic Research and Dissertations. 21. https://digitalmaine.com/academic/21 This Text is brought to you for free and open access by the Maine State Library Special Collections at Digital Maine. It has been accepted for inclusion in Academic Research and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Digital Maine. For more information, please contact [email protected]. AESTHESIS UNIVERSALIS: RECONCILING AESTHETIC PHILOSOPHY AND THE CARTESIAN PARADIGM Taryn M Sweeney Submitted to the faculty of The Institute for Doctoral Studies in the Visual Arts in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree Doctor of Philosophy November, 2018 ii Accepted by the faculty of the Institute for Doctoral Studies in the Visual Arts in partial fulfillment of the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. COMMITTEE MEMBERS Committee Chair: Don Wehrs, Ph.D. Hargis Professor of English Literature Auburn University, Auburn Committee Member: Merle Williams, Ph.D. Personal Professor of English University of Witwatersrand, Johannesburg Committee Member: Kathe Hicks Albrecht, Ph.D. Independent Studies Director Institute for Doctoral Studies in the Visual Arts, Portland iii © 2018 Taryn M Sweeney ALL RIGHTS RESERVED iv ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I owe a profound gratitude to my advisor, Don Wehrs, for his tremendous patience, sympathy, and acceptance of my completely un-academic self as I approached this most ambitious and academic of undertakings.
    [Show full text]
  • SWEDENBORG's PHILOSOPHY of CAUSALITY William Ross Woofenden
    SWEDENBORG'S PHILOSOPHY OF CAUSALITY William Ross Woofenden CHAPTER II SWEDENBORG DEVELOPS HIS OWN THEORY It was noted earlier1 that with the publication of his Principia (1734), Swedenborg's reputation as a scientist and natural philosopher was established in Europe. The work is a lengthy one, and the writing style leans toward the ornate. The first chapter, which runs to some fifty pages in English translation, is titled, perhaps a bit pompously, "The Means Leading to True Philosophy, and the True Philosopher." As might be expected, however, the chapter does state in full detail the presuppositions concerning causality held by the author at this time. For example, early in the chapter he states: The sign that we desire to be wise, is the wish to know the causes of things...Now the principal means which lead to truly philosophical knowledge are three in number—experience, geometry, and the power of reasoning...By philosophy we here mean the knowledge of the mechanism of our world, or of whatever in the world is subject to the laws of geometry; or which it is possible to unfold to view by experience, assisted by geometry and reason.2 The thought pattern of the British Empiricists is clearly echoed when, for example, Swedenborg writes: 1 Cf. p. 239 (supra). 2 Principia, Vol. I, p. 2 [1912 ed.]. 285 THE NEW PHILOSOPHY, April-June 1990 By experience we mean the knowledge of everything in the world of nature which is capable of being received by the senses.3 His second means to philosophical knowledge just as clearly reflects the impact of the Continental Rationalists.
    [Show full text]
  • Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, Three Hundred Years Later
    Quaderns d’Història de l’Enginyeria volum xvi 2018 GOTTFRIED WILHELM LEIBNIZ, THREE HUNDRED YEARS LATER Mª Rosa Massa-Esteve, Antoni Roca Rosell This paper presents the contributions of the present issue of Quaderns in the framework of the homage to Leibniz, three hundred years after his death. Leibniz was a multifaceted figure, devoted to study and analysis of Nature and society. His contributions are studied in this issue mostly from the pers- pective of mathematics, but we should be aware that, for Leibniz, mathema- tics was a powerful way to understand and to change the world. Mathematics was also a relevant component of technology. * * * LEIBNIZ AND THE INFINITE Eberhard Knobloch How did Leibniz handle the infinite in mathematics? Above all one has to study his Arithmetical quadrature of the circle etc. in order to answer to this question. Its last, still available version was written between June and September 1676. A new, bilingual, annotated Latin-German edition has just appeared. The paper mainly deals with theorems, thoughts, and explana- tions of this treatise putting them into the historical context (Kepler, Galileo, Grégoire de St. Vincent, Mengoli, Pardies, Johann Bernoulli, Euler). Four issues will be especially discussed: 1. Leibniz’s notions of infinitely small and infinite emphasizing his crucial distinction between the unbounded and bounded infinite. It sheds new light on the meaning of the fictionality of these fictitious quantities. 2. How did Leibniz demonstrate that a certain quantity is infinitely small or infinite? Three possibilities will be explained (definition, third proportional, trichotomy law). 3. Asymptotic spaces: What happens in the neighbourhood of the asymptote? Finite spaces are equated with infini- tely long spaces.
    [Show full text]
  • Theory and History of Ontology by Raul Corazzon | E-Mail: [email protected] Mathesis Universalis: the Search for a Universal Scienc
    12/7/2021 Mathesis Universalis: the Search for a Universal Science Theory and History of Ontology by Raul Corazzon | e-mail: [email protected] Mathesis Universalis: the Search for a Universal Science INTRODUCTION "Preliminary remark: It is never quite clear what (the modern concept of mathesis universalis as such exactly signifies, let alone how it may be defined. The expression itself (1) is a composite of the Greek μάθησεως latinized by transcription to mathesis, and the Latin universalis. The latinized mathesis, generally meaning, according to the dictionaries, learning / knowledge / science (= disciplina or scientia), (2) more specifically designates mathematic (= scientia mathematica), though it can even mean astrology. Hence the first and general sense of mathesis universalis signifies no more than universal science (disciplina universalis or scientia universalis). However – and this will be very important – since this "science" has a rather mathematical ring to it, we should on second thoughts take it to be an equivalent of s cientia mathematica universalis (3) (or generalis or communis: due to the underlying Greek terminology, there is no difference between universal, general, or common in antiquity – things will have changed by Leibniz' time at the latest, of course). This more specific meaning, i.e., universal (or general or common) mathematical science or universal mathematic, is essential, and more or less the bottom line for most occurrences of the expression, though it still remains very vague. However, the emphasis of this paper lies, with regard to the concept of mathesis universalis not so much on the historical details as on the more general systematical outlines. Therefore it should suffice to begin our work with an understanding of mathesis universalis that implies not much more than universal (or general or common) mathematical science, which of course still allows for a range of diverse meanings.
    [Show full text]
  • INTERNATIONAL CONGRESS 300 ANNIVERSARY GOTTFRIED WILHELM LEIBNIZ (Leipzig,1646 - Hannover,1716)
    INTERNATIONAL CONGRESS 300 ANNIVERSARY GOTTFRIED WILHELM LEIBNIZ (Leipzig,1646 - Hannover,1716) 21 - 22th January 2016 Organization Grup de Recerca d’Història de la Ciència i de la Tècnica (Proyecto HAR2013-44643-R) Departament de Matemàtiques de la Universitat Politècnica de Catalunya Organization Committee Joaquim Berenguer Mónica Blanco Guillermo Lusa Mª Rosa Massa Mary Sol de Mora Carles Puig-Pla Antoni Roca-Rosell Fàtima Romero Aims -To commemorate the 300th anniversary of the death of Leibniz from a mathematical point of view and from the area of history of science, analyzing his work and its impact. -To complete and / or expand the scientific training of future professionals in engineering and mathematics. -To transmit to participants the perception of mathematics as a useful, human, interdisciplinary, dynamic and heuristic science. Justification of the activity The year 2016 will mark the 300th anniversary of the death of one of the most important mathematicians of history, Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz. The Research Group of the History of Science and Technology, together with the Department of Mathematics at the Polytechnic University of Catalonia, wants to commemorate this anniversary by holding an international congress, bringing together all the tributes that the scientific community will make to him all over the world. Leibniz’s mathematical work includes numerous works on calculus, determinants, combinatorial and gambling. Understanding the mathematical thought of Leibniz is a very complex issue that requires not only the study of his mathematical texts, but also the related philosophical ones where he interpreted the processes of reasoning as algebra of thought, and also the analysis of the many letters and manuscripts recently edited.
    [Show full text]
  • The Origins of Descartes' Concept of Mind in the Regulae Ad Directionem Ingenii
    The Origins of Descartes' Concept of Mind in the Regulae ad directionem ingenii Author: Nathan Douglas Smith Persistent link: http://hdl.handle.net/2345/bc-ir:101348 This work is posted on eScholarship@BC, Boston College University Libraries. Boston College Electronic Thesis or Dissertation, 2010 Copyright is held by the author, with all rights reserved, unless otherwise noted. Boston College The Graduate School of Arts and Sciences Department of Philosophy THE ORIGINS OF DESCARTES’ CONCEPT OF MIND IN THE REGULAE AD DIRECTIONEM INGENII a dissertation by NATHAN D. SMITH submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy August 2010 © copyright by NATHAN DOUGLAS SMITH 2010 THE ORIGINS OF DESCARTES’ CONCEPT OF MIND IN THE REGULAE by Nathan D. Smith Adviser: Richard Cobb-Stevens The dissertation is primarily an historical and philosophical analysis of Descartes’ early, unpublished treatise on scientific method, the Regulae ad directionem ingenii. Ever since it first appeared—as a manuscript passed among a small circle of intellectuals—in the 1660’s, the text has been shrouded in mystery. When was it written? Why was it abandoned? What was the character of the original draft? We will attempt to answer these questions, but more importantly, our concern will be whether or not this text stands on its own as a significant contribution to the Cartesian corpus. Does it present a coherent picture of Descartes’ philosophical thought at a crucial point in its development? Recent commentators have made it clear that Descartes’ Regulae is a foundational text in his scientific career. It most fully develops Descartes’ early insights into scientific method and the nature of explanation.
    [Show full text]
  • The Transition to Calculus - Part II !
    August 24, 2000 The Transition to Calculus - Part II ! ! The Low Countries Frans van Schooten, (1615-1660), Netherlands, had succeeded his father as professor of mathematics at Leyden. Because the original by Descartes was difficult to read, Van Schooten made a careful and clear translation of Descartes’ La Geometrie into Latin, the preferred language of scholars. ! Partly the rea- son for this was so that his students could understand it. In 1659-1661, an expanded version was published. Geome- triaaRenatoDesCartes. Two additional additions appeared in 1683 and 1695. It is reasonable to say that although analytic geometry was introduced by Descartes, it was established by Schooten. Frans van Schooten (the father), professor at the engineering school connected with Leiden. The father was also a military engineer. He was trained in mathematics at Leiden, and he met Descartes there in 1637 and read the proofs of his Geometry. In Paris he collect manu- scripts of the works of Viete, and in Leiden he published Viete’s works. He published the Latin edition of Descartes’ Geometry. The much ex- panded second edition was extremely influential. He also made his own contributions, though modest, to mathematics, especially in his Exerci- tationes mathematicae, 1657. He trained DeWitt, Huygens, Hudde, and Heuraet. In the 1640’s (at least) he gave private lessons in mathematics in Leiden. Descartes recommended him to Constantijn Huygens as the tutor to his sons. Since the Huygens boys were coming to Leiden, Schooten decided to remain there. Descartes’ introduction opened to Schooten the circle of natural philosophers and mathematicians around Mersenne in Paris.
    [Show full text]
  • René Descartes' Foundations of Analytic Geometry
    U.U.D.M. Project Report 2013:18 René Descartes’ Foundations of Analytic Geometry and Classification of Curves Sofia Neovius Examensarbete i matematik, 15 hp Handledare och examinator: Gunnar Berg Juni 2013 Department of Mathematics Uppsala University Abstract Descartes' La Géométrie of 1637 laid the foundation for analytic geometry with all its applications. This essay investigates whether the classification of curves presented in La Géométrie, into geometrical and mechanical curves based on their construction as well as into classes based on their equations, limited the further development of analytic geometry as a field. It also looks into why Descartes' further classification was algebraic rather than geometrical; and how it was criticized and why. In order to answer these questions, the essay touches on the historical background to Descartes' works, provides an overview and analysis of the ideas put forward by Descartes, and describes the development of analytic geometry in the 150 years following the publication of La Géométrie. Content 1. Introduction .................................................................................................................................................. p. 3 2. Mathematical context i.The Mathematical Background to Descartes' works …........................................................................ p. 4 ii. Overview of the content of La Géometrie …..................................................................................... p. 6 3. The classification of curves i. The classification
    [Show full text]
  • Calculus Ratiocinator Vs Characteristica Universalis
    18/09/21, 17:41 Calculus Ratiocinator vs Characteristica Universalis Theory and History of Ontology by Raul Corazzon | e-mail: [email protected] Selected bibliography on Language as Calculus vs. Language as Universal Medium Bibliography 1. Blanché, Robert. 1970. La logique et son histoire d'Aristote à Russell. Paris: Armand Colin. See Chapter VIII. Leibniz 1. Situation de Leibniz 189; 2. Logique classique 193; 3. Lingua characteristica universalis 201; 4. Calculus ratiocinator 208-219. 2. Cocchiarella, Nino. 1988. "Predication versus membership in the distinction between logic as language and logic as calculus." Synthese no. 77:37-72. 3. Cohen, Jonathan. 1954. "On the Project of a Universal Character." Mind no. 63:49- 63. Reprinted in: Knowledge and Language. Selected Essays of L. Jonathan Cohen, Edited and with an introduction by James Logue, Dordrecht: Kluwer, 2002 pp. 1- 14. "During the last thirty years or so the practice has grown up among logicians of attributing the project of a universal character to Leibniz alone among seventeenth century thinkers. This attribution is to be found, for instance, in L. S. Stebbing’s Modern Introduction to Logic, (1) in Cohen and Nagel’s Introduction to Logic and Scientific Method, (2) in M. Black’s Nature of Mathematics, (3) in J. H. Woodger’s Axiomatic Method in Biology, (4) and in O. Neurath’s introductory article in the International Encyclopaedia of Unified Science. (5) And it dates, I suspect, from the publication of C. I. Lewis’s Survey of Symbolic Logic in 1918. Lewis mentioned that Leibniz acknowledged a debt in this connexion to Raymond Lully, Athanasius Kircher, George Dalgarno and John Wilkins.
    [Show full text]
  • The Mathematical Proportion and Its Role in the Cartesian Geometry
    TheThe mathematicalmathematical proportionproportion andand itsits rolerole inin thethe CartesianCartesian geometrygeometry Sandra Visokolskis National University of Córdoba This paper focuses on the conceptual history of the mathematical proportion. This very rich and varied in conceptual content notion has had and still today preserves a large and particularly controversial history. Has been shared by countless mathematicians, each under their own interpretation, and sometimes very dissimilar from each other, and curiously has not been exhaustively chronologized; among other things by their participation overlapped in many historical cases, due to his theoretical marginality. Indeed, while central in a few authors usually constitutes a tool for discovery and creativity, but not always has been recognized their relevance in a probative level of the results which contributes to its emergence. After a brief introduction regarding the use of the proportion in Greek Antiquity, I will concentrate in the case of Descartes and his discovery of the analytic geometry, and I will try to show how the current notion of proportion in the Cartesian France from 17th century and his own philosophical of understanding mathematics, allowed him to arrive at its results based on historical textual supports. The proportion in ancient Greece In the history of Western mathematics, the concept of proportion had a fluctuating history, a central one -especially in the Pythagoreans beginning- and others marginal, contributing in the latter cases as overlapped in the formal constitution of various notions that marked the mainstream of mathematical knowledge. Our goal is to highlight the importance attributed to proportions in their history, with emphasis on an episode for which their contribution was prominent but not very development highlighted by later historiography, evaluating their impact on the development of the analytic geometry in the hands of Descartes.
    [Show full text]
  • Is Leibniz a Precursor of Artificial Intelligence?
    Sybille Kramer Sybille Kdimer is professor for phi­ Freie Universitat Berlin, FE Philosophic losophy (epistemology, themy of mind) at the Institute for Philoso­ phy, Free University of Berlin. Her publications arc on rationalism, his­ Mind, Symbolism, Formalism: tory of formalization, philosophical aspects of Artificial Intelligence, Is Leibniz a Precursor of consciousness, metaphors, theory of melancholy, computer as a medium Artificial Intelligence? and media-theory. Kramer, S.: Mind, symbolism, formalism: Is Leibniz a computer is transferable to the human mind. What hap­ precursor of Artificial Intelligence'! pens within our mind is the unconscious working of a Knowl.Org. 23(1996)No.2, p.84-87, 31 refs. computer-like mechanism. Thus the computer is an ex­ The assumption that Gottfried Wilhelm Lcibniz is a precursor planative model of the human mind: the mind is a kind of of the idea of Artificial Intelligence is misleading. The argu­ computer. ment is to distinguish between epistcmc and mind, recognition But the idea of a functional analogy between the and cognition. Leibniz interpreted forma! symbolic operations as a mere epistemological instrument, but not as a description machine and the human mind, is not a rationalistic one. of what actually happens within the mind: Leibniz denied that More over: This assumption is inconsistent with the a machine can be used as an explanative model of cognition. rationalistic concept of the mind: Leibniz (II) - as before (Author) him Descartes (12) - explicitly excluded that a machine is of use as a model of the mind. If the association ofLeibniz with Artificial Intelligence is based on the assumption 1.
    [Show full text]
  • The Analytical Method in Descartes' Geometrie
    THE ANALYTICAL METHOD IN DESCARTES' GEOMETRIE GIORGIO ISRAEL Dipartimento di Matematica Università degli Studi di Roma 'La Sapienza' P.le A. Moro, 5 00185 - ROMA To describe La Géométrie as an essai of the Cartesian method, or as the application of the rules given in Discours de la méthode, has paradoxically contributed to an undervaluation of existing connections between this brilliant and famous essai and Descartes' philosophical work. In a way this is a paradox, considering the fact that this description of La Géométrie underlines the dependency of Descartes' only complete mathematical treatment on the method to follow «pour bien conduire sa raison et chercher la vérité dans les sciences » and on the metaphysical principles on which it is based. Nevertheless the connection between La Géométrie and the Cartesian method thus established appears weak. Because of this unsatisfactory situation, the essays dedicated to the study of this text appear to be split into 'philosophical-humanistic' analyses and 'scientific' analyses. Let us try to clarify the previous statement, beginning with the reasons why the connection between La Géométrie and the rules of Discours de la méthode appears weak.The fundamental reason lies in the vagueness of the methodological rules expressed in the Discours and summarized in the four famous rules governing the scientific thought, even if Leibniz' severity seems excessive when he compares them with common recipes and sums them up in the almost obvious rule: «sume quod debes, operare ut debes et habebis quod optas ».1 Nevertheless it is difficult to deny that those who aim at establishing a tight connection between the rules of the Discours and the contents of La Géométrie, by trying to demonstrate in some way 1 G.W.Leibniz, Die philosophischen Schriften von Leibniz , 7 voll., herausgeg.
    [Show full text]