Existence: an Unholy Trinity. an Account of Indeterminate Existence

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Existence: an Unholy Trinity. an Account of Indeterminate Existence City University of New York (CUNY) CUNY Academic Works All Dissertations, Theses, and Capstone Projects Dissertations, Theses, and Capstone Projects 2-2014 Existence: An Unholy Trinity. An account of Indeterminate Existence Salas Sanchez-Bennasar Graduate Center, City University of New York How does access to this work benefit ou?y Let us know! More information about this work at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu/gc_etds/105 Discover additional works at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu This work is made publicly available by the City University of New York (CUNY). Contact: [email protected] EXISTENCE: AN UNHOLY TRINITY An Account of Indeterminate Existence by Salas Sanchez-Bennasar A dissertation submitted to the Graduate Faculty in Philosophy in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy, The City University of New York 2014 ©2014 SALAS SANCHEZ-BENNASAR All Rights Reserved ii This manuscript has been read and accepted for the Graduate Faculty in Philosophy in satisfaction of the dissertation requirement for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. __________Arnold Koslow_____________ Date ______________ _____________________________________ Chair of Examining Committee _________Iakovos Vasiliou______________ Date ______________ _____________________________________ Executive Officer __________Graham Priest (Advisor)___________ ____________John Greenwood___________ ____________Rohit Parikh____________ ______________Stewart Shapiro___________ Supervisory Committee THE CITY UNIVERSITY OF NEW YORK iii Abstract EXISTENCE: AN UNHOLY TRINITY An Account of Indeterminate Existence by Salas Sanchez-Bennasar Advisor: Professor Graham Priest What is it for something to exist? This dissertation provides an answer to this question by giving a philosophical theory of existence in which the concept of existence in understood as a complex tri- partite notion. The account of existence defended here is arrived at by taking into consideration past philosophical theories of existence, the everyday and scientific uses of the notion, and also philosophical considerations about the nature of reality. There are three conditions that are central to existence: spatiotemporality, mind-independence, and being a member of the quantificational domain of a true and complete scientific description about the world. To exist is to satisfy all three conditions. It is false that something exists if and only if it for each condition, it fails to satisfy it. And, therefore, we get a third case: if an entity satisfies some but not all of the conditions, then it is neither true nor false that it exists, so what follows is an account of indeterminate existence. For some entities, our best theoretical sharpening of our conception of existence still fails to determine whether they exist or not. iv After arguing for each of the three conditions thoroughly, I strengthen the case for my theory of existence by explaining the consequences of its application. I provide several examples. Finally, I focus on the development of a philosophy of mathematics that takes into account that, given our theory of existence, it is neither true nor false that mathematical entities exist. v ACKNOWLEDGMENTS Working with Graham Priest has been a rich, invigorating and maturing experience without which I would have not been able to complete this work. Graham Priest has been a role model and an enabler of my academic training (and my travels and appreciation of Australian wine) above and beyond the requirements of duty. For all of this, I am forever grateful to him. I also want to thank the two readers of this work, Arnold Koslow and Stewart Shapiro, who read through the chapters and gave me invaluable feedback and advice. Stewart Shapiro’s book Thinking about Mathematics was my introduction to the philosophy of mathematics as an undergraduate in London, many years before I met him in person, so his influence has been formative for me. Working with him in person has made this influence enduring. Overall, the encouragement, insights and patience of my committee make me feel very fortunate. I am also grateful to the rest of the examining committee for agreeing to be part of this project: John Greenwood and Rohit Parikh. I also thank my family, who have helped me throughout the years and have encouraged me, supported me, listened and been there for me: my mother, Marga Bennasar Félix, who was my first philosophy teacher; Ramón Sánchez Ramón, to whom I owe my philosophical up-bringing; Josh Dulberger for his kind care and sharp observations; Ellen Dulberger, for her close and constant support; and Sergeant, who kept me company and grounded me during the writing. vi TABLE OF CONTENTS Abstract iv Acknowledgments vi Introduction 1 0.1. Motivating thoughts 2 0.2. Structure 4 Chapter 1: The Linguistic Condition 9 1.1. The Concept of Existence 10 1.1.1. The Problem of Being, Existence and the Concept of Existence 10 1.1.2. Conditions for Existence 17 1.2. The NeoFregean Project 19 1.2.1. Syntax to Semantics 23 1.2.2. Semantics to Existence 29 1.3. The Quinean Condition 33 1.3.1. Against the Sufficiency of the Condition 38 1.3.1.a. Quine 38 1.3.1.b. Other Arguments: A Plausible Best Theory? 41 1.3.1.c. Other arguments: Indispensability 45 1.3.2. The Necessity of the Condition, Qualified: 49 1.4. The Present Suggestion: The Linguistic Condition 51 vii Chapter 2: The Spatiotemporality Condition 59 2.1. Causal efficacy v. spatiotemporality 60 2.1.1. The Nature of Causation 62 2.1.2. Everything that is Causally Efficacious is Spatiotemporal 67 2.1.2. Everything Spatiotemporal is Causally Efficacious 71 2.1.3. Dropping Causal Efficacy 73 2.2. Everything that Exists is Spatiotemporal 75 2.2.1. Ockham’s Razor 79 2.3. The Criterion is not Sufficient 99 2.3.1. Counterexamples 100 2.3.2. There are Three Aspects of Existence 102 Chapter 3: The Independence Condition 104 3.1. Mind-independence: a definition 105 3.1.1. Mind-Independence v. Objectivity 110 3.2. Mind-Independence is a Necessary Condition for Existence 120 3.2.1. Some positions against realism 123 3.2.2. Objection: Azzouni 136 3.3. Mind-independence is not a sufficient condition for existence 141 3.3.1. Mathematical entities are mind-independent 142 3.3.1.a. Applicability 142 3.3.1.b. Apriority 146 3.3.2. Another counterexample to the sufficiency claim 150 Chapter 4: Application of the theory 153 4.1. Application 154 4.2. Indeterminately existing entities 158 viii 4.3. Objections and replies 169 4.3.1. Indeterminate existence? 169 4.3.2. Possible-world semantics 171 4.3.3. The scarcity of nonexistent entities 176 4.3.4. Azzouni: No criteria for existence 177 4.3.5. Quantifier Variance? 186 4.3.6. Sider Against Vague Existence 188 4.3.7. Fictional Entities 192 Chapter 5: Mathematics 197 5.1. The truth-value of mathematical statements 198 5.1.1. A Semantic Interpretation 201 5.2. Knowledge of mathematics? 211 5.2.1. Math is true 212 5.2.2. Math is neither true nor false 214 5.3. The application of mathematics 215 5.3.1. Applying a neither true nor false discourse 215 5.3.2. Applying a true discourse 229 Concluding thoughts 233 Bibliography 237 ix Chapter 0: Introduction What is there? Quine, “On What There Is” (From a Logical Point of View 1) What is there? Quine claimed that the answer is very easy: Everything. But I don’t think that’s correct. Some things don’t exist. People, trees, Venus and electrons exist. But Indiana Jones, Vulcan and phlogiston don’t exist. And what about numbers and other mathematical entities? What about abstract entities? And intersubjective entities, like money or countries? These questions easily force one into the question: What is existence? What does it mean for something to exist? That is the starting point of this dissertation. The account of existence defended here is arrived at by taking into consideration past philosophical theories of existence, the everyday and scientific uses of the notion, and also philosophical considerations about the nature of reality. The result is a philosophical theory of existence that is an improvement on previous attempts, for it combines valuable insights of many other theories together with current use into one complex account. 1 I argue here that existence is best understood as a tri-partite notion: to exist is to satisfy all three conditions. It is false that something exists if and only if for each condition, it fails to satisfy it. And, therefore, we get a third case: if an entity satisfies some but not all of the conditions, then it is neither true nor false that it exists, so what follows is an also account of indeterminate existence. These are the three conditions for existence: a. Theoretical Commitment: Something is a theoretical commitment if and only if it is part of the quantificational domain of a true and complete scientific description of the world. b. Spatiotemporality: Something is spatiotemporal if and only if it is in space and/or time. c. Mind-independence: Something is mind-independent if and only if it is such that its existence (if it exists) and nature do not depend on what any mind judges it to be. In this introduction I explain in broad strokes how I think about existence, doing my best to motivate the general results. I specify how the dissertation argues for the theory and give a quick run-down of chapters, in order to give the reader a clear roadmap of what’s to come. 0.1. Motivating thoughts There is something peculiar about the question “Do numbers exist?”. Ask the layman and she will probably brush off the question altogether. A common non-philosophical impression is that it is the wrong kind of question to ask about numbers—it is met with bafflement more than anything.
Recommended publications
  • Charity and Error-Theoretic Nominalism Hemsideversion
    Published in Ratio 28 (3), pp. 256-270, DOI: 10.1111/rati.12070 CHARITY AND ERROR-THEORETIC NOMINALISM Arvid Båve Abstract I here investigate whether there is any version of the principle of charity both strong enough to conflict with an error-theoretic version of nominalism about abstract objects (EN), and supported by the considerations adduced in favour of interpretive charity in the literature. I argue that in order to be strong enough, the principle, which I call “(Charity)”, would have to read, “For all expressions e, an acceptable interpretation must make true a sufficiently high ratio of accepted sentences containing e”. I next consider arguments based on (i) Davidson’s intuitive cases for interpretive charity, (ii) the reliability of perceptual beliefs, and (iii) the reliability of “non-abstractive inference modes”, and conclude that none support (Charity). I then propose a diagnosis of the view that there must be some universal principle of charity ruling out (EN). Finally, I present a reason to think (Charity) is false, namely, that it seems to exclude the possibility of such disagreements as that between nominalists and realists. Nominalists about abstract objects have given remarkably disparate answers to the question: how, if there are no abstract objects, should we view statements that seem to involve purported reference to or quantification over such objects?1 According to the 1 I define nominalism as the view not merely that there are no abstract objects, but also that nothing is an abstract object, contra certain “noneists” like Graham Priest (2005), who accept the Arvid Båve error-theoretic variant of nominalism (EN), these statements should be taken at face value, both semantically and pragmatically, i.e., taken both as literally entailing that there are abstract objects, and also as used and interpreted literally by ordinary speakers.
    [Show full text]
  • Quantified Modality and Essentialism
    Quantified Modality and Essentialism Saul A. Kripke This is the accepted version of the following article: Kripke, S. A. (2017), Quantified Modality and Essentialism. Noûs, 51: 221-234. doi: 10.1111/nous.12126, Which has been published in final form at https://doi.org/10.1111/nous.12126. 1 Quantified Modality and Essentialism1 Saul A. Kripke It is well know that the most thoroughgoing critique of modal logic has been that of W.V. Quine. Quine’s position, though uniformly critical of quantified modal systems, has nevertheless varied through the years from extreme and flat rejection of modality to a more nearly moderate critique. At times Quine urged that, for purely logico-semantical reasons based on the problem of interpreting quantified modalities, a quantified modal logic is impossible; or, alternatively, that it is possible only on the basis of a queer ontology which repudiates the individuals of the concrete world in favor of their ethereal intensions. Quine has also urged that even if these objections have been answered, modal logic would clearly commit itself to the metaphysical jungle of Aristotelian essentialism; and this essentialism is held to be a notion far more obscure than the notion of analyticity upon which modal logic was originally to be based. 1 There is a long story behind this paper. It was written for a seminar given by Quine himself in the academic year 1961/2, and discussed in class over a period of several weeks. Some years later, I was surprised to hear from Héctor-Neri Castañeda that it had received wider circulation among philosophers.
    [Show full text]
  • How to Adopt a Logic
    How to adopt a logic Daniel Cohnitz1 & Carlo Nicolai2 1Utrecht University 2King’s College London Abstract What is commonly referred to as the Adoption Problem is a challenge to the idea that the principles for logic can be rationally revised. The argument is based on a reconstruction of unpublished work by Saul Kripke. As the reconstruction has it, Kripke essentially extends the scope of William van Orman Quine’s regress argument against conventionalism to the possibility of adopting new logical principles. In this paper we want to discuss the scope of this challenge. Are all revisions of logic subject to the regress problem? If not, are there interesting cases of logical revisions that are subject to the regress problem? We will argue that both questions should be answered negatively. FIRST DRAFT 1 1 Introduction What is commonly referred to as the Adoption Problem is a challenge to the idea that the principles for logic can be rationally revised. The argument is based on a reconstruction of unpublished work by Saul Kripke.1 As the reconstruction has it, Kripke essentially extends the scope of William van Orman Quine’s regress argument (Quine, 1976) against conventionalism to the possibility of adopting new logical principles. In this paper we want to discuss the scope of this challenge. Are all revisions of logic subject to the regress problem? If not, are there interesting cases of logical revisions that are subject to the regress problem? We will argue that both questions should be answered negatively. Kripke’s regress does not arise for all rules of inference and not even for the adoption of those rules that are of relevance for the discussion of the rational revisability of logic.
    [Show full text]
  • Evil and the Ontological Disproof
    City University of New York (CUNY) CUNY Academic Works All Dissertations, Theses, and Capstone Projects Dissertations, Theses, and Capstone Projects 9-2017 Evil and the Ontological Disproof Carl J. Brownson III The Graduate Center, City University of New York How does access to this work benefit ou?y Let us know! More information about this work at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu/gc_etds/2155 Discover additional works at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu This work is made publicly available by the City University of New York (CUNY). Contact: [email protected] EVIL AND THE ONTOLOGICAL DISPROOF by CARL BROWNSON A dissertation submitted to the Graduate Faculty in Philosophy in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy, City University of New York 2017 1 © 2017 CARL BROWNSON All Rights Reserved ii Evil and the Ontological Disproof by Carl Brownson This manuscript has been read and accepted for the Graduate Faculty in Philosophy in satisfaction of the dissertation requirement for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. Date Graham Priest Chair of Examining Committee Date Iakovos Vasiliou Executive Officer Supervisory Committee: Stephen Grover, advisor Graham Priest Peter Simpson Nickolas Pappas Robert Lovering THE CITY UNIVERSITY OF NEW YORK iii ABSTRACT Evil and the Ontological Disproof by Carl Brownson Advisor: Stephen Grover This dissertation is a revival of the ontological disproof, an ontological argument against the existence of God. The ontological disproof, in its original form, argues that God is impossible, because if God exists, he must exist necessarily, and necessary existence is impossible. The notion of necessary existence has been largely rehabilitated since this argument was first offered in 1948, and the argument has accordingly lost much of its force.
    [Show full text]
  • Accepting a Logic, Accepting a Theory
    1 To appear in Romina Padró and Yale Weiss (eds.), Saul Kripke on Modal Logic. New York: Springer. Accepting a Logic, Accepting a Theory Timothy Williamson Abstract: This chapter responds to Saul Kripke’s critique of the idea of adopting an alternative logic. It defends an anti-exceptionalist view of logic, on which coming to accept a new logic is a special case of coming to accept a new scientific theory. The approach is illustrated in detail by debates on quantified modal logic. A distinction between folk logic and scientific logic is modelled on the distinction between folk physics and scientific physics. The importance of not confusing logic with metalogic in applying this distinction is emphasized. Defeasible inferential dispositions are shown to play a major role in theory acceptance in logic and mathematics as well as in natural and social science. Like beliefs, such dispositions are malleable in response to evidence, though not simply at will. Consideration is given to the Quinean objection that accepting an alternative logic involves changing the subject rather than denying the doctrine. The objection is shown to depend on neglect of the social dimension of meaning determination, akin to the descriptivism about proper names and natural kind terms criticized by Kripke and Putnam. Normal standards of interpretation indicate that disputes between classical and non-classical logicians are genuine disagreements. Keywords: Modal logic, intuitionistic logic, alternative logics, Kripke, Quine, Dummett, Putnam Author affiliation: Oxford University, U.K. Email: [email protected] 2 1. Introduction I first encountered Saul Kripke in my first term as an undergraduate at Oxford University, studying mathematics and philosophy, when he gave the 1973 John Locke Lectures (later published as Kripke 2013).
    [Show full text]
  • Possibilities and Paradox: an Introduction to Modal and Many-Valued Logic
    Possibilities and Paradox: An Introduction to Modal and Many-Valued Logic. By J.C. BEALL and BAS C. VAN FRAASSEN. Oxford University Press, 2003. xv + 233 pp. $29.95 paper Non-classical logics play a prominent role in many areas of philosophy nowadays—philosophy of mind, metaphysics, and philosophy of language, to mention a few. Unfortunately, much of the discussion of non-classical sys- tems has been confined to highly specialized publications and has therefore been inaccessible to the philosophy undergraduate student. Until recently, there were only a few books on the market suitable for the beginner (one of them is Graham Priest’s excellent An Introduction to Non-Classical Logic, Cambridge University Press, 2001). Given the importance of the topic, an- other good textbook on non-classical logics would be very welcome. Beall and van Fraassen have helped to fill this gap in the current liter- ature with their new and detailed introduction to modal and many-valued logics. Possibilities and Paradox exposes, in an accessible way, the basic concepts and techniques of a variety of non-classical systems, including stan- dard modal, conditional, intuitionistic, relevance, and paraconsistent logic. All that is required from the reader is familiarity with elementary classical logic. The stated aim of the book “is to give students a basic grounding in philosophical logic, in a way that connects with motivations they derive from elsewhere in philosophy” (p. ix). Indeed the text is very successful in achieving this goal: it covers a wide range of technical material with- out neglecting philosophical issues associated with the development of such systems.
    [Show full text]
  • 1.1 PHILOSOPHY AS OPEN-ENDED QUESTIONING Reaching Back To
    1 WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY? 1.1 PHILOSOPHY AS OPEN-ENDED QUESTIONING Reaching back to ancient Greece, a common ploy in addressing the question “What is philosophy?” is to provide a linguistic account, noting that the original Greek words philos and sophia combined can be understood as ‘love of Wisdom’. However, this ploy is evasive, because the moment that any two philosophers begin to expound on the relevant meanings of these two terms, they are likely as not to part ways. th A more recent ploy—notably pursued in the 20 century by the philosopher Ludwig Wittgenstein and (in a somewhat different form) by the pragmatist Richard Rorty (following Jacques Derrida)—is to give a deflationary account of philosophy. Wittgenstein’s idea was that philosophical problems are pseudo-problems that arise when we take language out of context. Imagine, for example, that one were to ask of a dancer “is that move a checkmate?”, as if the term ‘checkmate’ made sense out of the context of its use in chess. For Rorty, the idea was that philosophy is defined only by the fact that philosophical writing tends to concern itself with other philosophical writing: All that ‘philosophy’ as a name for a sector of culture means is ‘talk of Plato, Augustine, Descartes, Kant, Hegel, Fichte, Russell . and that lot’. Philosophy is best seen as a kind of writing. It is delimited, as is any literary genre, not by form or matter, but by tradition.. (Rorty, R., 1979, “Philosophy as a Kind of Writing: An Essay on Derrida”, New Literary History 10: 228-239.) An irony of both of these deflationary accounts of philosophy is that the accounts themselves purport to do more than what they claim philosophy can do—they purport to make a case for a particular point of view.
    [Show full text]
  • Graham Priest's 'Dialetheism'
    GRAHAM PRIEST’S ‘DIALETHEISM’— IS IT ALTHOGETHER TRUE? Lorenzo Peña SORITES Nº 7 Novembre 1996 ISSN 1135-1349 pp. 28-56 Contents: 01.— True Contradictions 02.— Are true contradictions in between complete truth and complete falsity? 03.— Avoiding ineffability and the need for strong negation 04.— Set Theory 05.— Conjunctive Assertion 06.— Motion 07.— Juridical and deontic logic 08.— Other grounds for true contradictions 09.— The Confinement Policy and Using DS 10.— Conclusion §1.— True Contradictions Graham Priest’s book In Contradiction (Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff, 1987) is a bold and well argued-for defense of the existence of true contradictions. Priest’s case for true contradictions — or «dialetheias», as he calls them — is by no means the only one in contemporary analytical philosophy, let alone in philosophy tout court. In some sense, other defenses of the existence of true contradictions are less philosophically «heterodox» than his is, since, unlike Priest’s orientation, other approaches are closer to prevailing ideas in mainstream («Quinean») analytical philosophy, whereas Priest’s leanings are strongly anti- realist, and not distant from the logical empiricism of the thirties. However, such issues seem to me almost immaterial for the chief arguments in Priest’s book. Much of what he says can be accepted from a wide variety of philosophical outlooks. And most of it seems to me right and important. Other among his arguments are less cogent, and yet can be modified and thus rendered far more convincing. Even when that is not so, weaker — less sweeping, but more plausible — arguments can be put in their place.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Stances, Voluntarism, Relativism Martin Kusch §1. Introduction in This
    1 Stances, Voluntarism, Relativism Martin Kusch §1. Introduction In this paper I want to explore two ideas put forward and defended in Bas van Fraassen’s The Empirical Stance (2002) (=ES) as well as in some related papers. The first idea is that many philosophical positions are best rendered not as “doctrines” but as “stances,” that is, as sets, systems or bundles of values, emotions, policies, preferences, and beliefs. (To avoid torturous repetition, I shall refer to sets of values, emotions, policies and preferences as “VEPPs”.) The second idea is a form of epistemology that van Fraassen calls “epistemic voluntarism.” It is based on the rejection of two received views: that principles of rationality determine which philosophical positions and scientific paradigms we must adopt, and that epistemology is (akin to) a descriptive-explanatory (scientific) theory of cognition. I shall relate the stance-idea and epistemic voluntarism to debates over (epistemic) relativism. §2. Stances ES seeks to renew empiricism. According to van Fraassen, empiricism is first and foremost a “rebellion” against metaphysics. This is because “metaphysicians interpret what we initially understand into something hardly anyone understands, and then insist that we cannot do without that“ (2002: 3). Take the question “Does the world exist?“ To answer this question, metaphysicians use a technical concept of world. David Lewis for instance holds that a world simply is “the sum of all things spatio-temporally related to a given thing” (2002: 10). How does Lewis arrive at this result? Why is the mingle-mangle of things more or less distantly related to me “a world?” As ES sees it, Lewis simply “postulates” how “world” is to be understood and that it exists.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction: at the Intersection of Truth and Falsity
    Introduction: At the Intersection of Truth and Falsity JC Beall ‘Now we will take another line of reasoning. When you follow two separate chains of thought, Watson, you will find some point of intersection which should approximate to the truth.’—Sherlock Holmes, in ‘The Disappearance of Lady Frances Carfax’. 1. TOWARDS THE INTERSECTION Suppose that we have (at least) two categories X and Y for any meaningful, declarative sentence A of our language.É Pending further information about X and Y, there seem to be four options for an arbitrary sentence A: » A is only in X » A is only in Y » A is in both X and Y » A is in neither X nor Y Whether each such ‘option’ is logically possible depends not only on our logic (about which more below) but on the details of X and Y. Suppose that X comprises all (and only) sentences composed of exactly six words, and Y those with exactly nineteen words. In that case, only the third option is ruled out: X and Y are exclusive—their intersection X ∩ Y is empty—since no A can be composed of exactly six words and also be composed of exactly nineteen words.Ê Despite being exclusive, X and Y are not exhaustive—their union X ∪ Y does not exhaust all sentences—since some A may fall into neither X nor Y. (Just consider ‘Max sat on Agnes’.) Consider another example. Let X comprise all sentences of your favourite novel and Y your all-time favourite sentences. In that case, exclusion is not ruled out; the intersection of X and Y may well be non-empty.
    [Show full text]
  • Is Motion “Contradiction's Immediate Existence”?
    IS MOTION “CONTRADICTION’S IMMEDIATE EXISTENCE”? Graham Stevens Philosophy, U. of Manchester Manchester, uk, m pl [email protected] Michael Rush Philosophy, U. of Birmingham Birmingham, uk, b15 2tt [email protected] A driving concern of Russell’s rejection of Idealism was his conviction that reality is free of contradictions. However, echoing the neo-Hegelians that Russell is usually taken successfully to have refuted, Graham Priest has argued that the analysis of motion provides a motivation to adopt dialetheism (the thesis that some contradictions may be true). Further- more, Priest argues that the Russellian account of motion as given in The Principles of Mathematics fails accurately to capture the phenomenon. In this paper we argue that Priest’s objections to Russell are neither new nor decisive. We show that even if one shares Priest’s concerns about the Russellian model there are alternatives inspired by Russell’s own con- temporaries that do not entail dialetheism. We conclude that not only are Priest’s objections to Russell unconvincing, but even one who shares Priest’s intuitions has no reason to resurrect the Hegelian account of motion: [M]otion itself is contradiction’s immediate existence. Something moves, not because at one moment it is here and at another there, but because at one and the same moment it is here and not here, because in this “here” it at once is and is not. The ancient dialecticians must be granted the contradictions that they pointed out in motion; but it does not follow that therefore there is no motion, but on the contrary, that motion is existent contradiction itself.
    [Show full text]
  • Retracted Date: 4 September 2020
    () - viva rium brill.com/viv Introduction Frédéric Goubier Université de Genève, Switzerland [email protected] Magali Roques Universität Hamburg, Germany Laboratoire d’études sur les Monothéismes, Centre national de la recherche scientique (), Paris, France [email protected] Available Online Date: 14 July 2017 Retracted Date: 4 September 2020 How does change work? If a thing moves from one state to another, when ex- actly does it start to be in its new state, and when does it cease to be in its former one? An easy answer would be that the last instant of a given state is immediately followed by the rst instant of the new state. But if time is con- ceived as a continuum, there is always a third instant between two instants; in other words, there are no two adjacent instants. One has therefore to decide whether change takes place at the last instant before the thing is in its new state, the rst instant at which it is in its new state, both the former and the latter, or neither ofRETRACTED them. The rst two options seem arbitrary, the third goes against the law of non-contradiction, and the fourth against the law of exclud- ed middle. And if there is no instant of change, how can there be change at all? The property of being an instant of change must be dened if we are to give an adequate description of it. The problem is not limited to the question of how to describe the instant of change. It also includes the question why a philosopher would prefer one description of the instant of change over the * We are grateful to all the contributors of the present volume.
    [Show full text]