Diamond Source: Philosophy, Vol

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Diamond Source: Philosophy, Vol Royal Institute of Philosophy Throwing Away the Ladder Author(s): Cora Diamond Source: Philosophy, Vol. 63, No. 243 (Jan., 1988), pp. 5-27 Published by: Cambridge University Press on behalf of Royal Institute of Philosophy Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3750493 Accessed: 19-11-2015 13:34 UTC Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/ info/about/policies/terms.jsp JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Royal Institute of Philosophy and Cambridge University Press are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Philosophy. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 130.88.20.147 on Thu, 19 Nov 2015 13:34:10 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions ThrowingAway the Ladder CORA DIAMOND Whetherone is readingWittgenstein's Tractatus or his laterwritings, one must be struckby his insistencethat he is not puttingforward philosophicaldoctrines or theses;or byhis suggestion that it cannot be done,that it is onlythrough some confusion one is in aboutwhat one is doingthat one could takeoneself to be puttingforward philosophical doctrinesor theses at all. I thinkthat there is almost nothingin Wittgensteinwhich is of value and whichcan be graspedif it is pulled awayfrom that view of philosophy. But thatview of -philosophy is itself somethingthat has to be seen firstin the Tractatus if it is to be understoodin itslater forms, and inthe Tractatus it is inseparablefrom whatis centralthere, the distinction between what can be said and what can onlybe shown. Now whatabout that distinction? Peter Geach has writtenthat it has itssource in 'thegreat works of Frege', in Frege'sdiscussion of contrasts likethat between function and object.The differencebetween function and objectcomes out in language,but Frege, as is wellknown, held that thereare insuperableproblems in any attemptto put thatdifference properlyinto words. We cannotproperly speaking say what the differ- enceis, butit is reflectedin featuresof language; and whatholds of the differencebetween function and objectholds too of otherdistinctions oflogical category. Geach is rightthat we can bestunderstand what the Tractatusholds about sayingand showingif we go back to Fregeand thinkabout what the saying/showing distinction in itsorigin looks like there.Geach actuallymakes a strongerclaim: he saysthat 'a greatdeal of the Tractatusis best understoodas a refashioningof Frege'sfunc- tion-and-argumentanalysis in orderto remove[from it the] mistaken treatmentof sentencesas complexnames'.I That last pointof Geach's, abouthow to understandthe Tractatus, splitsinto two points if you think about it. Wittgensteinis trying to hold on to Frege'sinsight that there are distinctionsof logical category, like thatbetween functions and objects,or betweenfirst and secondlevel I P. T. Geach, 'Sayingand Showingin Fregeand Wittgenstein',Essays on Wittgensteinin Honour of G. H. von Wright,Jaakko Hintikka (ed.), Acta PhilosophicaFennica 28 (1976) (Amsterdam:North-Holland), 54-55, 64. Philosophy63 1988 5 This content downloaded from 130.88.20.147 on Thu, 19 Nov 2015 13:34:10 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Cora Diamond functions,which cannot be put intowords but whichare reflectedin distinctionsbetween the signs for what is in one categoryand thesigns forwhat is in the other.He wantsto hold on to that,and at the same timeto getrid of the assimilation of sentences to propernames. So for Wittgensteina sentence will count as a whollydifferent sort of linguistic itemfrom a propername or any otherkind of name. But if you are holdingon to Frege'sinsight that fundamental differences in kindsof linguisticexpression are the way fundamentaldifferences in reality showthemselves, differences in realitythat cannot be putinto words- and if you are also saying,against Frege, that sentences are a wholly differentlinguistic category from any kind of name, thatwill make sense if you are also sayingthat there are featuresof realitythat can come out onlyin sentences,in theirbeing the particularkind of sign theyare, in contrastwith names. Here, then,is how Geach's pointsplits into two: (1) In the Tractatustreatment of Frege'sinsight, sentences are no longerassimilated to complexnames. (2) Makingthat break, separating sentences off that way from names, is linkedwith the possibilityof treatingthe distinctivefeatures of sentencesas reflectionsof featuresof reality,features that can onlybe reflectedin sentencesand thatcannot themselves be said to be features of reality.Such a treatmentof sentenceswould then be radically differentfrom Frege's, but could neverthelessbe said to be deeply Fregeanin spiritand inspiredby Frege. Geach himselfgives some detail of what is involvedin Wittgenstein's gettingrid of the assimilation of sentences to names;but he has rather less on what I have just been talkingabout: the applyingof Frege's insightto sentencesby taking their distinctive and essentialcharacteris- ticsto be thereflection of something in thenature of things that cannot be putinto words.2 But now to getback to whereI wasat thebeginning: ifwe wantto knowwhy Wittgenstein thinks that there cannot (in some sense)be philosophicaldoctrines, we needto see theapparent doctrines of the Tractatusas theywill look ifwe go furtherdown the road that Geach pointsout as a road. That is, we need to see whatkind of sign Wittgensteintook a sentenceto be and how,by being that kind of sign, itcan showthings that cannot be said. Butthere is somethingthat has to be donefirst. And one convenientway of doing it is togo backto Geach. I haveso farfollowed Geach in his wayof putting the Frege insight. As he puts it, variousfeatures of realitycome out in languagebut it cannotbe said in languagethat reality has thosefeatures. Geach is here followingboth Frege and Wittgensteinin an importantrespect. Witt- 2 Hans Sluga also touchesbriefly on the point; see Sluga, GottlobFrege (London: Routledgeand Kegan Paul, 1980), 144. 6 This content downloaded from 130.88.20.147 on Thu, 19 Nov 2015 13:34:10 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Throwing Away the Ladder genstein,throughout the Tractatus, when he speaksabout what shows itselfbut cannotbe said, speaksof thesethings as featuresof reality. Thereis, he says, what cannotbe put into words. Propositionsand realityhave something in commonthat cannot be putinto words. Even the linguisticform 'what cannotbe put into words',the words 'das Unsagbare', 'das Undenkbare'-such ways of talkingrefer, or must seemto, to featuresof reality that cannot be putin wordsor captured in thought.Frege, in speakingof the distinction between first and second level functions,describes it as foundeddeep in the natureof things;3 and itis evidentthat he wouldsay exactly the same about the distinction betweenfunction and object.There is a questionhow to takethis sort of talk:the use ofwords like 'reality', 'the nature of things', 'what there is' and so on, in specifyingwhat cannot be putinto words. The problemis particularlyacute in Wittgenstein,given the passage at theend of the Tractatus(6.54): 'whoeverunderstands me eventuallyrecognizes [my propositions]as nonsensical,when he has used them-as steps-to climbup beyondthem. (He must,so to speak,throw away the ladder afterhe has climbedup it.)' The problemis how seriouslywe can take thatremark, and in particularwhether it can be appliedto thepoint (in whateverway it is put) thatsome features of reality cannot be put into words. Let me illustratethe problem this way. One thingwhich according to the Tractatusshows itself but cannotbe expressedin languageis what Wittgensteinspeaks of as thelogicalform of reality. So itlooks as ifthere is thiswhatever-it-is, the logical form of reality, some essential feature ofreality, which reality has all right,but which we cannotsay or think thatit has. Whatexactly is supposedto be leftof that,after we have thrownaway the ladder?Are we goingto keep the idea thatthere is somethingor otherin realitythat we gestureat, howeverbadly, when we speak of 'the logical formof reality',so that it, what we were gesturingat, is therebut cannotbe expressedin words? That is what I want to call chickeningout. What counts as not chickeningout is thenthis, roughly: to throwthe ladder away is, among otherthings, to throwaway in theend theattempt to takeseriously the languageof 'featuresof reality'.To read Wittgensteinhimself as not chickeningout is to say thatit is not,not really, his viewthat there are featuresof realitythat cannot be put intowords but showthemselves. Whatis his viewis thatthat way of talking may be usefulor evenfor a timeessential, but it is in theend to be letgo ofand honestlytaken to be realnonsense, plain nonsense, which we arenot in theend to thinkof as I GottlobFrege, 'Function and Concept',Translations from the Philosoph- ical Writingsof GottlobFrege, P. T. Geach and Max Black (eds) (Oxford: Basil Blackwell,1952), 41. 7 This content downloaded from 130.88.20.147 on Thu, 19 Nov 2015 13:34:10 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Cora Diamond correspondingto an ineffabletruth. To speakof featuresof realityin connectionwith what shows itself in languageis to use a veryodd kind of figurativelanguage.
Recommended publications
  • Logic in Action: Wittgenstein's Logical Pragmatism and the Impotence of Scepticism
    This is the final, pre-publication draft. Please cite only from published paper in Philosophical Investigations 26:2 (April 2003), 125-48. LOGIC IN ACTION: WITTGENSTEIN'S LOGICAL PRAGMATISM AND THE IMPOTENCE OF SCEPTICISM DANIÈLE MOYAL-SHARROCK UNIVERSITY OF GENEVA 1. The Many Faces of Certainty: Wittgenstein's Logical Pragmatism So I am trying to say something that sounds like pragmatism. (OC 422) In his struggle to uncover the nature of our basic beliefs, Wittgenstein depicts them variously in On Certainty: he thinks of them in propositional terms, in pictorial terms and in terms of acting. As propositions, they would be of a peculiar sort – a hybrid between a logical and an empirical proposition (OC 136, 309). These are the so-called 'hinge propositions' of On Certainty (OC 341). Wittgenstein also thinks of these beliefs as forming a picture, a World-picture – or Weltbild (OC 167). This is a step in the right (nonpropositional) direction, but not the ultimate step. Wittgenstein's ultimate and crucial depiction of our basic beliefs is in terms of a know-how, an attitude, a way of acting (OC 204). Here, he treads on pragmatist ground. But can Wittgenstein be labelled a pragmatist, having himself rejected the affiliation because of its utility implication? But you aren't a pragmatist? No. For I am not saying that a proposition is true if it is useful. (RPP I, 266) Wittgenstein resists affiliation with pragmatism because he does not want his use of use to be confused with the utility use of use. For him, it is not that a proposition is true if it is useful, but that use gives the proposition its sense.
    [Show full text]
  • Koethe, University of Wisconsin
    Philosophical Investigations 26:3 July 2003 ISSN 0190-0536 On the ‘Resolute’ Reading of the Tractatus1 John Koethe, University of Wisconsin It is customary to divide Wittgenstein’s work into two broad phases, the first culminating in the Tractatus, and the second comprising the writings that began upon his return to philosophy in 1929 and cul- minating in the Investigations. It is also commonly assumed that the Tractatus propounds various doctrines concerning language and rep- resentation, doctrines which are repudiated in the later work, and often criticized explicitly. One problem with this view of the Trac- tatus is Wittgenstein’s claim in 6.54 that its propositions are “non- sensical,”2 a claim which on its face is at odds with the idea that they present substantive philosophical theories. The usual way of handling this problem is to assume that the claim is not to be taken literally, that the sentences of the Tractatus are not nonsense in the sense of mere gibberish, but are intended somehow to engender in the attentive reader a grasp of certain important aspects of the rela- tionship between language and the world. Beginning with her seminal paper “Throwing Away the Ladder,” Cora Diamond has proposed reading the Tractatus in a way that takes literally 6.54’s claim of the book’s nonsensicality, and rejects the idea that its sentences represent a kind of elevated nonsense intended to 1. This is a revised version of a paper originally presented at a symposium on the resolute reading of the Tractatus at the 1999 Central Division meetings of the Amer- ican Philosophical Association in New Orleans.
    [Show full text]
  • CRITICAL NOTICE Why We Need Ordinary Language Philosophy
    CRITICAL NOTICE Why We Need Ordinary Language Philosophy Sandra Laugier, Translated by Daniela Ginsberg, The University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 2013, pp. 168, £ 24.50. ISBN-13: 978-0-226-47054-2 (cloth). Reviewed by Derek A. McDougall Originally published in French in the year 2000, the English version of Sandra Laugier’s short book of 10 Chapters plus an Introduction and Conclusion, has a 7 page Preface, 9 pages of Notes, a brief Bibliography and 121 pages of actual text. The reading of Wittgenstein and Austin that she provides is distinctly Cavellian in character. Indeed, Stanley Cavell in a dust-cover quote, remarks that her work is already influential in France and Italy, exciting as it does a new interest in ‘language conceived not only as a cognitive capacity but also as used, and meant, as part of our form of life’. Cavell goes on to say that this new translation is not merely welcome but indispensable, and has at least the capacity to alter prevailing views about the philosophy of language, so affecting what we have come to think of as the ‘analytic-continental divide’. Toril Moi of Duke Uni., in another dust-cover quote, states that Laugier’s reading of Wittgenstein-Austin-Cavell shows how their claim that ‘to speak about language is to speak about the world is an antimetaphysical revolution in philosophy that tranforms our understanding of epistemology and ethics.’ She concludes with the thought that anyone who wishes to understand what ‘ordinary language philosophy’ means today should read this book. This is a large claim to make, and anyone who is inclined to read Wittgenstein and Austin strictly in their own terms, and with their own avowed intentions - where discernible - steadily in view, is almost bound to conclude that it is simply not true.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 5. Language: Private, Public, Solitary, Shared on the Received
    Chapter 5. Language: private, public, solitary, shared On the received reading of Ludwig Wittgenstein's Philosophical Investigations1, the book contains an argument purporting to show the impossibility of a private language. There has been a lively debate, however, on how the relevant notion of a private language is to be understood, and what considerations should be taken to rule it out. Some have understood Wittgenstein to mean that a language must be something that several speakers actually share, while others take him to mean that a language must be something that they could, in principle, share. Or, slightly differently put, on one view, speaking a language presupposes the actual existence of a linguistic community upholding certain shared standards of meaning and correctness, while on the other view, it only presupposes that such a community might have existed. These views have come to be known as the ‘community view’ and the ‘solitary speaker’ view, respectively.2 Furthermore, supporters of the community view tend to think that the discussion about privacy holds a central place in Wittgenstein’s later philosophy, whereas those who support the solitary speaker view usually see its bearings as limited to the issue of the privacy of experience. 1 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1958). References to this work will be indicated with the abbreviation PI followed by paragraph number. 2 Rather than two monolithic positions, what we have here is a spectrum of views ranging between two extremes. To mention but a few examples: the best-known formulations of the community view are to be found in Norman Malcolm, “Following a Rule” in his book Nothing is Hidden (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1986), as well as in his essay “Wittgenstein on Language and Rules” in Wittgensteinian Themes: Essays 1978-1989 (ed.
    [Show full text]
  • Between Realism and Rortianism
    Epistemology R R R By Cora Diamond yoe who reads aes oas essay reedo rely ad Trh R R R R R I. Conant and Rorty on realism: how Conant sets up the issue and how Rorty responds irs will desrie he dispe ewee Rory ad oa ao realis H R R R T room R R between R R R T H R R Realism 1. The thesis that the Thing-in-Itself is a condition of the possibility of knowledge T T Cora Diamond is Kenan Professor of Philosophy emerita at the University of Virginia. Her works have analyzed philosophical problems in many areas, including Witgenstein, Frege, Philosophy of Language, Ethics, Political Philosophy and Philosophy of Literature. Her notable works include “What Nonsense Might Be”, an analysis of Fregean nonsense, as well as numerous writings on all of Witgenstein’s lifetime work. She has also been noted for her writing on animal rights, including the article “Eating Meat and Eating People” published by Cambridge University Press. The Harvard Review of Philosophy vol.XXI 2014 HRP Vol 21.indd 56 12/1/14 8:56 AM R R 57 of appearances about the way the world is in itself. think knowledge Realism 2. The thesis
    [Show full text]
  • Wittgenstein and the Moral Life: Essays in Honor of Cora Diamond" Edited by A
    Swarthmore College Works Philosophy Faculty Works Philosophy 4-1-2008 Review Of "Wittgenstein And The Moral Life: Essays In Honor Of Cora Diamond" Edited By A. Crary Richard Thomas Eldridge Swarthmore College, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://works.swarthmore.edu/fac-philosophy Part of the Philosophy Commons Let us know how access to these works benefits ouy Recommended Citation Richard Thomas Eldridge. (2008). "Review Of "Wittgenstein And The Moral Life: Essays In Honor Of Cora Diamond" Edited By A. Crary". Ethics. Volume 118, Issue 3. 543-549. DOI: 10.1086/587764 https://works.swarthmore.edu/fac-philosophy/65 This work is brought to you for free by Swarthmore College Libraries' Works. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Faculty Works by an authorized administrator of Works. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Alice Crary, ed., Wittgenstein and the Moral Life: Essays in Honor of Cora Diamond Wittgenstein and the Moral Life: Essays in Honor of Cora Diamond by Alice Crary, Review by: Reviewed by Richard Eldridge Ethics, Vol. 118, No. 3, Symposium on Agency (April 2008), pp. 543-549 Published by: The University of Chicago Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.1086/587764 . Accessed: 17/02/2015 14:22 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive.
    [Show full text]
  • Stanley Cavell and the Environmental Debate
    Un Poète Maudit: Stanley Cavell and the Environmental Debate TOMA! GRU"OVNIK ! ! ! O Lady! we receive but what we give, And in our life alone does the nature live: Ours is her wedding-garment, ours her shroud! And would we aught behold, of higher worth, Than that inanimate cold world allowed To the poor loveless ever-anxious crowd, Ah! from the soul itself must issue forth, A light, a glory, a fair luminous cloud Enveloping the Earth — And from the soul itself must there be sent A sweet and potent voice, of its own birth, Of all sweet sounds the life the element! SAMUEL TAYLOR COLERIDGE, Dejection: An Ode Images of landscapes and encounters with the natural world feature prominently throughout Stanley Cavell’s texts — so much so that Coleridge’s romantic visions of the natural environment (the cold, icy region through which the Mariner’s ship drifts) represent one of the cornerstones of Cavell’s understanding of “romanticism as work- ing out a crisis of knowledge,”1 and “skepticism [as] what romantic writers are locked in struggle against.”2 Indeed, skepticism as an interpretation of “metaphysical fini- tude” as “an intellectual lack”3 is seen by Cavell as something that has to be overcome !!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!! 1. Cavell, In Quest of the Ordinary: Lines of Skepticism and Romanticism (Chicago, IL: Chi- cago University Press, 1988), 52. 2. Cavell, Disowning Knowledge In Seven Plays of Shakespeare (Cambridge: Cambridge Uni- versity Press, 2003), 8. 3. Cavell, Must We Mean What We Say?: A Book of Essays (Cambridge: Cambridge Univer- sity Press, 1976), 263.
    [Show full text]
  • Wittgenstein on Rule Following: a Critical and Comparative Study of Saul Kripke, John Mcdowell, Peter Winch, and Cora Diamond
    Wittgenstein on Rule Following: A Critical and Comparative Study of Saul Kripke, John McDowell, Peter Winch, and Cora Diamond Samuel James Weir King’s College London MPhil in Philosophy 1 Abstract This thesis is a critical and comparative study of four commentators on the later Wittgenstein’s rule following considerations. As such its primary aim is exegetical, and ultimately the thesis seeks to arrive at an enriched understanding of Wittgenstein’s work through the distillation of the four commentators into what, it is hoped, can be said to approach a definitive interpretation, freed of their individual frailties. The thesis commences by explicating the position of Kripke’s Wittgenstein. He draws our attention to the ‘sceptical problem’ of how we are to resolve the apparently paradoxical situation that whilst we seem to use language meaningfully, there is no fact about us that constitutes our meaning one thing as opposed to something else, and consequently the possibility of our actually meaning anything seems to evaporate. Kripke interprets Wittgenstein as accepting the validity of the sceptical problem, but seeking to establish that the force of the problem is radically diminished because the justification which it has shown to be unobtainable is actually unnecessary for rule following to take place. McDowell tries to show that Kripke is mistaken when he views Wittgenstein as endorsing scepticism in this way, because he sees Kripke as failing to appreciate a section of Philosophical Investigations which suggests that one ought to reject the sceptical paradox by correcting the misunderstanding which gives rise to it. McDowell reads Wittgenstein’s claim as being that we mistakenly think we are caught in a dilemma which requires us either to endorse the sceptical paradox or to subscribe to a mythological picture of rule following; whereas, so the thought goes, we must reject the entire dilemma.
    [Show full text]
  • Hilary Putnam on Meaning and Necessity Anders Öberg
    Hilary Putnam on Meaning and Necessity Anders Öberg Dissertation presented at Uppsala University to be publicly examined in Geijersalen, Human- istiskt Centrum, Engelska parken, Uppsala. Saturday, December 3, 2011 at 13:15 for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. The examination will be conducted in English. Abstract Öberg, A. 2011. Hilary Putnam on Meaning and Necessity. Department of Philosophy. 166 pp. Uppsala. ISBN 978-91-506-2243-0. In this dissertation on Hilary Putnam's philosophy, I investigate his development regarding meaning and necessity, in particular mathematical necessity. Putnam has been a leading American philosopher since the end of the 1950s, becoming famous in the 1960s within the school of analytic philosophy, associated in particular with the philosophy of science and the philosophy of language. Under the influence of W.V. Quine, Putnam challenged the logical positivism/empiricism that had become strong in America after World War II, with influential exponents such as Rudolf Carnap and Hans Reichenbach. Putnam agreed with Quine that there are no absolute a priori truths. In particular, he was critical of the notion of truth by convention. Instead he developed a notion of relative a priori truth, that is, a notion of neces- sary truth with respect to a body of knowledge, or a conceptual scheme. Putnam's position on necessity has developed over the years and has always been connected to his important con- tributions to the philosophy of meaning. I study Hilary Putnam's development through an early phase of scientific realism, a middle phase of internal realism, and his later position of a natural or commonsense realism.
    [Show full text]
  • Post-Analytic Tractatus
    Post-Analytic Tractatus Edited by BARRY STOCKER ASHGATE © Barry Stocker 2004 Contents All rights reserved. No part ofthis publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise without the prior permission of the publisher. Published by List ofContributors vii Ashgate PublishingLimited Ashgate Publishing Company Gower House Suite 20 Introduction Croft Road 101Cherry Street Aldershot Burlington, VT 05401-4405 Life, Art, and Mysticism 5 HantsGU113HR USA Luitzen Egbertus Jan Brouwer England 2 Logic and Ethics as the Limits of the World 47 Ashgate website: http://www.ashgate.com I I Anthony Rudd British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data 3 To What Extent is Solipsism a Truth? 59 Post-analytic Tractatus Michael Kremer 1. Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 1889-1951. Tractatus Logico-philosophicus 4 Frege at Therapy 85 I. Stocker, Barry Kelly Dean Jolley 192 5 'Making Sense' of Nonsense: Conant and Diamond Read Library ofCongress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Wittgenstein's Tractatus 99 Post-analytic Tractatus / edited by Barry Stocker. Diarmuid Costello p.cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. 6 More Making Sense of Nonsense: From Logical Form to Forms ISBN0-7546-1297-X of Life 127 1. Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 1889-1951. Tractatus logico-philosophicus. 2. Logic, Symbolic Daniel D. Hutto and mathematical. 3. Language and languages--Philosophy. 4. Metaphysics. I. Stocker, Barry, 1966- 7 Saying and Showing: An Example from Anscombe 151
    [Show full text]
  • Our Toil Respite Only: Woolf, Diamond, and the Difficulty of Reality
    Our Toil Respite Only: Woolf, Diamond, and the Difficulty of Reality ❦ Karen Zumhagen-Yekplé There is nothing…that answers, or bears on, the problems of life. But the very fact that in these books, as we may imagine them, there are answers to every imaginable question can help us to transform our own desire for an answer to the problem of life. (Cora Diamond, “Introduction to ‘Having a Rough Story About What Moral Philosophy Is’” 129) In The Phantom Table, Ann Banfeld examines Virginia Woolf’s preoc- cupation—and that of Bloomsbury more generally—with the episte- mological questions raised in Cambridge philosophy during the frst quarter of the 20th century. The era that provides the context for her inquiry is one Banfeld places “squarely within the period of Russell, which ends with Wittgenstein’s ascendancy.” And yet, she continues, “this does not prevent the Tractatus [Logico-Philosophicus] from play- ing a role in our reconstruction of Bloomsbury’s intellectual world,” since its “conceptions, language and dominant metaphors fnd their counterparts in Woolf, not because she came under its infuence, but because she shared its ways of thinking” (9). Banfeld astutely posits these shared ways of thinking (the result of fortuitous, perhaps zeitgeistig philosophical kinship rather than any direct mutual infuence), and then lets them rest without pursuing them further. Such concerns, after all, fall outside the purview of her work in that book on Woolf’s engagement with Russell, Moore and Fry, and the philosophical background of Bloomsbury.
    [Show full text]
  • Language and World
    Language and World Papers of the 32nd International Wittgenstein Symposium August 9 – 15, 2009 Kirchberg am Wechsel Volume XVII Editors Volker A. Munz Klaus Puhl Joseph Wang Printed in cooperation with the Department for Culture and Science of the Province of Lower Austria Kirchberg am Wechsel, 2009 Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society Is the Resolute Reading Really Inconsistent?: Trying to Get Clear on Hacker vs. Diamond/Conant Michael Maurer, Vienna, Austria [email protected] For over two decades the Resolute Reading of the Trac- straightforward, garden variety, completely incomprehen- tatus has attempted to create an awareness of the fact that sible gibberish.” (Conant, 1989, 253) Therefore they have readings which traditionally focus on the topic of ineffability a completely different picture of the philosophical activity to are methodologically inconsistent and do not truly reveal which the author of the Tractatus was profoundly commit- the dialectical movement of Wittgenstein’s early master- ted in his work: his aim is not to show inexpressible deep piece. In what follows my intention is to shed light on the truths that represent the metaphysical features of reality, question of whether the Resolute Reading is methodologi- but to free the philosophically inclined reader from the cally inconsistent in itself, as is held by Peter Hacker, the illusory meaningfulness of such obsessive pictures. Throw- most influential opponent of this position. ing away the Tractarian ladder – after having undergone the dialectical process of climbing it – means to have fully dissolved the philosophical problems produced by the logic Two Paradigms for Reading the Tractatus of our language from within.
    [Show full text]