Interpreting Epidemiologic Evidence: Strategies for Study Design and Analysis

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Interpreting Epidemiologic Evidence: Strategies for Study Design and Analysis Datu Dr Andrew Kiyu 24/6/2013 Importance of topic INTERPRETATION OF EPIDEMIOLOGIC EVIDENCE: • Epidemiology success stories have led to improved policy and Truth, Chance and Biases practice. • However, observational epidemiology has: – methodologic limitations that Dr Andrew Kiyu – affect the ability to infer causation. (MBBS, MPH, DrPH, AM, FACE) Consultant Epidemiologist • The major challenge of : Sarawak Health Department • dealing with the data deluge and Email address: [email protected] – uncovering true causal relationships from – the millions and millions of observations that are Sibu Clinical Research Seminar background noise. RH Hotel, Sibu • Date: 24 June 2013 Increased consumer awareness and education • Source: NCI's Epidemiology and Genomics Research Program sponsored a workshop entitled” T rends in 21st Century Epidemiology- From Scientific Discoveries to Population Health Impact “ on 12-13 December 2012 at 1 http://epi.grants.cancer.gov/workshops/century-trends/ 2 “Interpretation of Epidemiologic Evidence” Osteoporosis as a Health Issue Producer of • The US Surgeon General estimates that one out of every two Epidemiologic Evidence women over the age of 50 will have an osteoporosis-related fracture in their lifetime. • In addition, 20% of those affected by osteoporosis are men with 6% of white males over the age of 50 suffering a hip fracture. Personal level Population level • It is estimated that the national direct care costs for osteoporotic fractures is US$12.2 to 17.9 billion per year in 2002 dollars, with costs rising. • This cost is comparable to the Medicare expense for coronary heart disease ($11.6 billion) (Thom et al 2006) Consumer of • John A Sunyecz. The use of calcium and vitamin D in the management of osteoporosis. Therapeutics and Clinical Risk Management 2008:4(4) 827–836 at http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC2621390/pdf/TCRM-4-827.pdf Epidemiologic Evidence 3 4 The Use of Calcium and vitamin D in the Anlene advertisement Management of Osteoporosis (2004, 2008) Therapeutics and Clinical Risk Management 2008:4(4) 827–836 at http://www.surgeongeneral.gov/library/rep http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC2621390/pdf/TCRM-4-827.pdf orts/bonehealth/OsteoBrochure1mar05.pd f 5 6 http://adsoftheworld.com/files/images/anlene_spine.jpg Sibu Research Seminar 2013 1 Datu Dr Andrew Kiyu 24/6/2013 Calcium Supplements Increase Heart Attack Risk by 86 Percent (Heart 2012) • New research published in the journal Heart has confirmed the findings of two controversial studies on calcium supplementation and heart attack risk published in the British Medical Journal last year, and which found a 24-27% increased risk of heart attack for those who took 500 mg of elemental calcium a day.[1] [2] • The results of this newest review, involving 24,000 people between the ages of 35 and 64, were even more alarming. Those participants who took a regular calcium supplement increased their risk of Flow Galindez. Fight Osteoporosis with two glass of Anlene everyday. Sunday, April 3, 2011. having a heart attack by 86% versus those who took no calcium supplements at all. http://angsawariko.blogspot.com/2011/04/fight-osteoporosis-with-two-glass-of.html • Conclusions: Increasing calcium intake from diet might not confer significant cardiovascular benefits, while calcium supplements, which might raise MI risk, should be taken with caution. 7 • Heart 2012;9 8:920e925. doi:10.1136/heartjnl-2011-301345 at http://heart.bmj.com/content/98/12/920.full.pdf+html 8 How to read a paper Greenhalgh T, Taylor R. BMJ 1997 1. The Medline database. BMJ 1997;315:180-183 (19 July). http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC2127107 2. Getting your bearings (deciding what the paper is about). BMJ 1997;315:243-246 (26 July). http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC2127173 3. Assessing the methodological quality of published papers. BMJ 1997;315:305-308 (2 August). http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC2127212 4. Statistics for the non-statistician. I: Different types of data need different statistical tests. BMJ 1997;315:364- 366 (9 August). http://www.pubmedcentral.nih.gov/picrender.fcgi?artid=2127256&blobtype=pdf 5. How to read a paper: Statistics for the non-statistician. II: "Significant" relations and their pitfalls. BMJ 1997;315:422-425 (16 August). http://www.pubmedcentral.nih.gov/picrender.fcgi?artid=2127270&blobtype=pdf 6. Papers that report drug trials. BMJ 1997;315:480-483 (23 August). http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC2127321 7. Papers that report diagnostic or screening tests. BMJ 1997;315:540-543 (30 August). NOT ACADEMIC EXERCISE OR A http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC2127365 8. Papers that tell you what things cost (economic analyses). BMJ 1997;315:596-599 (6 September). ‘HOW TO’ SESSION http://www.pubmedcentral.nih.gov/picrender.fcgi?artid=2127419&blobtype=pdf 9. Papers that summarise other papers (systematic reviews and meta-analyses). BMJ 1997;315:672-675 (13 September). http://www.pubmedcentral.nih.gov/picrender.fcgi?artid=2127461&blobtype=pdf 10. Papers that go beyond numbers (qualitative research). BMJ 1997;315:740-743 (20 September). http://www.pubmedcentral.nih.gov/picrender.fcgi?artid=2127518&blobtype=pdf 9 10 http://eprints.mdx.ac.uk/2981/1/Developing_a_framework_for_critiquing_health_research.pdf Natalie Wolchover, (Life's Little Mysteries Staff Writer). What If Humans Had Eagle Vision? 11 Date: 24 February 2012. at http://www.lifeslittlemysteries.com/2184-humans-eagle-vision.html 12 Sibu Research Seminar 2013 2 Datu Dr Andrew Kiyu 24/6/2013 Unpublished evidence Publication bias Published evidence Producers Of Epidemiologic Policymakers Legal Evidence Scientist Truth Health & medicine Public Journal decision to Pseudoscience accept Researcher decision whether to submit Which parts to publish for publication Junk science Study design analysis EVIDENCE Epidemiologic research/ Epidemiologic Interpretation methods Scientific method paradigm How scientific decisions are arrived at 14 Evidence Evidence • Evidence is and includes everything that is used to • Research findings are defined (for the purpose of reveal and determine the truth, and therefore is this paper) as presumed to be true and related to a case – any relationship reaching formal statistical • Scientific evidence is evidence which serves to either significance. support or counter a scientific theory or hypothesis. – Such evidence is expected to be empirical evidence and in accordance with scientific method • However, “Negative” research is also very useful (Ioannidis. 2005) • Empirical evidence is a source of knowledge • John P.A Ioannidis. Why most published research findings are false. PLoS Medicine. August 2005; acquired by means of observation or vol2;Issue 8. p0696-0701 experimentation • Ref: http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Evidence • http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Scientific_evidence 15 16 • http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Empirical_evidence Scientific evidence Absence of evidence is not evidence of absence • By convention a P value greater than 5% (P>0.05) is called “not • As Bradford Hill (1965) said nearly 50 years ago: significant.” – “All scientific work is incomplete—whether it be • Randomised controlled clinical trials that do not show a observational or experimental. significant difference between the treatments being compared are often called “negative.” • All scientific work is liable to be upset or modified by advancing knowledge. • This term wrongly implies that the study has shown that there is no difference, whereas • That does not confer upon us a freedom to – usually all that has been shown is an absence of evidence of – ignore the knowledge we already have, or a difference. – to postpone the action that it appears to demand at a • These are quite different statements. given time.” • Source: Douglas G Altman, J Martin Bland. Statistics notes: Absence of evidence is not evidence of absence. BMJ 1995;311:485 at http://www.bmj.com/content/311/7003/485 • Bradford Hill A. 1965. The environment and disease: association or causation? Proc R Soc Med 58:295–300. 17 19 Sibu Research Seminar 2013 3 Datu Dr Andrew Kiyu 24/6/2013 PPV of Research Findings for Various Combinations of Power (1 − β), Ratio of Why Most Published Research Findings True to Not-True Relationships (R), and Bias (u) Are False by John P. A. Ioannidis (2005) 1 − β R u Practical Example PPV 0.80 1:1 0.10 Adequately powered RCT with little bias and 1:1 pre- 0.85 • The probability that a research claim is true may study odds depend on: 0.95 2:1 0.30 Confirmatory meta-analysis of good quality RCTs 0.85 1. study power and bias, 0.80 1:3 0.40 Meta-analysis of small inconclusive studies 0.41 0.20 1:5 0.20 Underpowered, but well-performed phase I/II RCT 0.23 2. the number of other studies on the same 0.20 1:5 0.80 Underpowered, poorly performed phase I/II RCT 0.17 question, 0.80 1:10 0.30 Adequately powered exploratory epidemiological study 0.20 • and, most importantly, 0.20 1:10 0.30 Underpowered exploratory epidemiological study 0.12 0.20 1:1,000 0.80 Discovery-oriented exploratory research with massive 0.0010 3. the ratio of true-to-no-relationships among the testing relationships probed in each scientific field. 0.20 1:1,000 0.20 As in previous example, but with more limited bias (more 0.0015 standardized) – Ioannidis JPA (2005) Why most published research findings are false. PLoS Med 2(8): e124. R = the ratio of the number of “true relationships” to “no relationships” among those tested in the field U = the proportion of probed analyses that would not have been “research findings,” but nevertheless end up presented and reported as such, because of bias The estimated PPVs (positive predictive values) are derived assuming α = 0.05 for a single study.
Recommended publications
  • Theistic Critiques of Atheism William Lane Craig Used by Permission of in the Cambridge Companion to Atheism, Pp
    Theistic Critiques Of Atheism William Lane Craig Used by permission of In The Cambridge Companion to Atheism, pp. 69-85. Ed. M. Martin. Cambridge Companions to Philosophy. Cambridge University Press, 2007. SUMMARY An account of the resurgence of philosophical theism in our time, including a brief survey of prominent anti-theistic arguments such as the presumption of atheism, the incoherence of theism, and the problem of evil, along with a defense of theistic arguments like the contingency argument, the cosmological argument, the teleological argument, and the moral argument. THEISTIC CRITIQUES OF ATHEISM Introduction The last half-century has witnessed a veritable revolution in Anglo-American philosophy. In a recent retrospective, the eminent Princeton philosopher Paul Benacerraf recalls what it was like doing philosophy at Princeton during the 1950s and '60s. The overwhelmingly dominant mode of thinking was scientific naturalism. Metaphysics had been vanquished, expelled from philosophy like an unclean leper. Any problem that could not be addressed by science was simply dismissed as a pseudo-problem. Verificationism reigned triumphantly over the emerging science of philosophy. "This new enlightenment would put the old metaphysical views and attitudes to rest and replace them with the new mode of doing philosophy." [1] The collapse of the Verificationism was undoubtedly the most important philosophical event of the twentieth century. Its demise meant a resurgence of metaphysics, along with other traditional problems of philosophy which Verificationism had suppressed. Accompanying this resurgence has come something new and altogether unanticipated: a renaissance in Christian philosophy. The face of Anglo-American philosophy has been transformed as a result.
    [Show full text]
  • The Epistemology of Science: Acceptance, Explanation, and Realism
    THE EPISTEMOLOGY OF SCIENCE: ACCEPTANCE,EXPLANATION, AND REALISM Finnur Dellsen´ A dissertation submitted to the faculty of the University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Department of Philosophy in the College of Arts and Sciences. Chapel Hill 2014 Approved by: Marc B. Lange John T. Roberts Matthew Kotzen Ram Neta William G. Lycan c 2014 Finnur Dellsen´ ALL RIGHTS RESERVED ii ABSTRACT FINNUR DELLSEN:´ The Epistemology of Science: Acceptance, Explanation, and Realism. (Under the direction of Marc B. Lange) Natural science tells a story about what the world is like. But what kind of story is this supposed to be? On a popular (realist) view, this story is meant to provide the best possible explanations of the aspects of the world with which we are all acquainted. A realist also thinks that the story should in some sense provide explanations that are probable in light of our evidence, and that these explanations ought to fit together into a coherent whole. These requirements turn out to be surprisingly hard to satisfy given the received view of how scientific theories are evaluated. However, I argue that if scientific theories are eval- uated comparatively rather than absolutely for explanatory purposes – optimifically rather than satisficingly – then we can provide a fully realist view of the connections between explanation, probability, and coherence. It is one thing to say what science’s story of the world ought ideally be like, it is another to say that the story as it is actually being told lives up to this ideal.
    [Show full text]
  • Reasons Against Belief: a Theory of Epistemic Defeat
    REASONS AGAINST BELIEF: A THEORY OF EPISTEMIC DEFEAT by Timothy D. Loughlin A DISSERTATION Presented to the Faculty of The Graduate College at the University of Nebraska In Partial Fulfillment of Requirements For the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy Major: Philosophy Under the Supervision of Professor Albert Casullo Lincoln, Nebraska May, 2015 REASONS AGAINST BELIEF: A THEORY OF EPISTEMIC DEFEAT Timothy D. Loughlin, Ph.D. University of Nebraska, 2015 Adviser: Albert Casullo Despite its central role in our cognitive lives, rational belief revision has received relatively little attention from epistemologists. This dissertation begins to fill that absence. In particular, we explore the phenomenon of defeasible epistemic justification, i.e., justification that can be lost as well as gained by epistemic agents. We begin by considering extant theories of defeat, according to which defeaters are whatever cause a loss of justification or things that somehow neutralize one's reasons for belief. Both of these theories are both extensionally and explanatorily inadequate and, so, are rejected. We proceed to develop a novel theory of defeat according to which defeaters are reasons against belief. According to this theory, the dynamics of justification are explained by the competition between reasons for and reasons against belief. We find that this theory not only handles the counter-examples that felled the previous theories but also does a fair job in explaining the various aspects of the phenomenon of defeat. Furthermore, this theory accomplishes this without positing any novel entities or mechanisms; according to this theory, defeaters are epistemic reasons against belief, the mirror image of our epistemic reasons for belief, rather than sui generis entities.
    [Show full text]
  • Empiricism and the Very Idea of “Buddhist Science” Commentary On
    Empiricism and the Very Idea of “Buddhist Science” Commentary on Janet Gyatso, Being Human in a Buddhist World: An Intellectual History of Medicine in Early Modern Tibet Evan Thompson Department of Philosophy University of British Columbia 2016 Toshide Numata Book Award Symposium Center for Buddhist Studies University of California, Berkeley Since the nineteenth century, one of the striking features of the Buddhist encounter with modernity has been the way both Asian Buddhists and Western Buddhist converts have argued that Buddhism not only is compatible with modern science but also is itself “scientific” or a kind of “mind science.” In our time, the most prominent exponent of this idea is Tenzin Gyatso, the Fourteenth Dalai Lama. At a recent Mind and Life Institute Dialogue on “Perception, Concepts, and the Self,” which took place in December 2015 at the Sera Monastery in India, the Dalai Lama interjected during the opening remarks to clarify the nature of the dialogue. The dialogue, he stated, was not between Buddhism and science, but rather was between “Buddhist science and modern science.” The idea of “Buddhist science” is central to the Dalai Lama’s strategy in these dialogues. His overall aim is to work with scientists to reduce suffering and to promote human flourishing. But his purpose is also to preserve and strengthen Tibetan Buddhism in the modern world. This requires using science to modernize Buddhism while protecting Buddhism from scientific materialism. A key tactic is to show—to both the scientists and the Tibetan Buddhist monastic community—that Buddhism contains its own science and that modern science can learn from it.
    [Show full text]
  • When Absence of Evidence Is Evidence of Absence: Rational Inferences from Absent Data
    Cognitive Science (2016) 1–13 Copyright © 2016 Cognitive Science Society, Inc. All rights reserved. ISSN: 0364-0213 print / 1551-6709 online DOI: 10.1111/cogs.12356 When Absence of Evidence Is Evidence of Absence: Rational Inferences From Absent Data Anne S. Hsu,a Andy Horng,b Thomas L. Griffiths,b Nick Chaterc aSchool of Electronic Engineering and Computer Science, Queen Mary, University of London bDepartment of Psychology, University of California cWarwick Business School, University of Warwick Received 8 March 2015; received in revised form 30 October 2015; accepted 7 December 2015 Abstract Identifying patterns in the world requires noticing not only unusual occurrences, but also unu- sual absences. We examined how people learn from absences, manipulating the extent to which an absence is expected. People can make two types of inferences from the absence of an event: either the event is possible but has not yet occurred, or the event never occurs. A rational analysis using Bayesian inference predicts that inferences from absent data should depend on how much the absence is expected to occur, with less probable absences being more salient. We tested this prediction in two experiments in which we elicited people’s judgments about patterns in the data as a function of absence salience. We found that people were able to decide that absences either were mere coincidences or were indicative of a significant pattern in the data in a manner that was consistent with predictions of a simple Bayesian model. Keywords: Absent data; Category learning; Rational analysis; Bayesian modeling 1. Introduction Bayesian inference prescribes how ideal rational agents make inferences.
    [Show full text]
  • Appeals to Evidence for the Resolution of Wicked Problems: the Origins and Mechanisms of Evidentiary Bias
    Policy Sci DOI 10.1007/s11077-016-9263-z RESEARCH ARTICLE Appeals to evidence for the resolution of wicked problems: the origins and mechanisms of evidentiary bias Justin O. Parkhurst1 Ó The Author(s) 2016. This article is published with open access at Springerlink.com Abstract Wicked policy problems are often said to be characterized by their ‘in- tractability’, whereby appeals to evidence are unable to provide policy resolution. Advo- cates for ‘Evidence Based Policy’ (EBP) often lament these situations as representing the misuse of evidence for strategic ends, while critical policy studies authors counter that policy decisions are fundamentally about competing values, with the (blind) embrace of technical evidence depoliticizing political decisions. This paper aims to help resolve these conflicts and, in doing so, consider how to address this particular feature of problem wickedness. Specifically the paper delineates two forms of evidentiary bias that drive intractability, each of which is reflected by contrasting positions in the EBP debates: ‘technical bias’—referring to invalid uses of evidence; and ‘issue bias’—referring to how pieces of evidence direct policy agendas to particular concerns. Drawing on the fields of policy studies and cognitive psychology, the paper explores the ways in which competing interests and values manifest in these forms of bias, and shape evidence utilization through different mechanisms. The paper presents a conceptual framework reflecting on how the nature of policy problems in terms of their complexity, contestation, and polarization can help identify the potential origins and mechanisms of evidentiary bias leading to intractability in some wicked policy debates. The discussion reflects on how a better understanding about such mechanisms could inform future work to mitigate or overcome such intractability.
    [Show full text]
  • Criminal Justice, False Certainty, and the Second Generation of Scientific Evidence
    The New Forensics: Criminal Justice, False Certainty, and the Second Generation of Scientific Evidence Erin Murphyt Accounts of powerful new forensic technologies such as DNA typing, data mining, biometric scanning, and electronic location tracking fill the daily news. Proponentspraise these techniques for helping to exonerate those wrongly accused, and for exposing the failings of a criminaljustice system thatpreviously relied too readily upon faulty forensic evidence like handwriting, ballistics, and hair and fiber analysis. Advocates applaud the introduction of a "new paradigm" for forensic evidence, and proclaim that these new techniques will revolutionize how the government investigates and tries criminal cases. While the new forensic sciences undoubtedly offer an unprecedented degree of certainty and reliability, these characteristicsalone do not necessarily render them less susceptible to misuse. In fact, as this Article argues, the most lauded attributes of these new forms of forensic evidence may actually exacerbate the Copyright © 2007 California Law Review, Inc. California Law Review, Inc. (CLR) is a California nonprofit corporation. CLR and the authors are solely responsible for the content of their publications. t Assistant Professor of Law, University of California, Berkeley, School of Law (Boalt Hall). J.D., Harvard Law School, 1999. I owe a tremendous debt of gratitude to David Sklansky for his infinite wisdom, patience, and insight, as well as to Frank Zimring, Eleanor Swift, Jan Vetter, Jonathan Simon, and Chuck Weisselberg. Dr. Montgomery Slatkin, Dr. Michael Eisen, and attorney Bicka Barlow also provided generous assistance. Special thanks to Andrea Roth, Todd Edelman, Tim O'Toole, and Eliza Platts-Mills for their invaluable contributions throughout the process.
    [Show full text]
  • Logic) 1 1.1 Formal Notation
    Universal generalization From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia Contents 1 Absorption (logic) 1 1.1 Formal notation ............................................ 1 1.2 Examples ............................................... 1 1.3 Proof by truth table .......................................... 2 1.4 Formal proof ............................................. 2 1.5 References ............................................... 2 2 Associative property 3 2.1 Definition ............................................... 3 2.2 Generalized associative law ...................................... 4 2.3 Examples ............................................... 4 2.4 Propositional logic .......................................... 7 2.4.1 Rule of replacement ..................................... 7 2.4.2 Truth functional connectives ................................. 7 2.5 Non-associativity ........................................... 7 2.5.1 Nonassociativity of floating point calculation ......................... 8 2.5.2 Notation for non-associative operations ........................... 8 2.6 See also ................................................ 10 2.7 References ............................................... 10 3 Axiom 11 3.1 Etymology ............................................... 11 3.2 Historical development ........................................ 12 3.2.1 Early Greeks ......................................... 12 3.2.2 Modern development ..................................... 12 3.2.3 Other sciences ......................................... 13 3.3 Mathematical
    [Show full text]
  • Nativism Empiricism and Ockhamweb
    Published in Erkenntnis, 80, 895-922 (2015). Please refer to the published version: http://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/s10670-014-9688-8 Nativism, Empiricism, and Ockham’s Razor Simon Fitzpatrick Department of Philosophy John Carroll University [email protected] Abstract This paper discusses the role that appeals to theoretical simplicity (or parsimony) have played in the debate between nativists and empiricists in cognitive science. Both sides have been keen to make use of such appeals in defence of their respective positions about the structure and ontogeny of the human mind. Focusing on the standard simplicity argument employed by empiricist-minded philosophers and cognitive scientists—what I call “the argument for minimal innateness”—I indentify various problems with such arguments—in particular, the apparent arbitrariness of the relevant notions of simplicity at work. I then argue that simplicity ought not be seen as a theoretical desideratum in its own right, but rather as a stand-in for desirable features of theories. In this deflationary vein, I argue that the best way of interpreting the argument for minimal innateness is to view it as an indirect appeal to various potential biological constraints on the amount of innate structure that can wired into the human mind. I then consider how nativists may respond to this biologized version of the argument, and discuss the role that similar biological concerns have played in recent theorizing in the Minimalist Programme in generative linguistics. 1. Introduction In the course
    [Show full text]
  • Reasoning from Paradigms and Negative Evidence
    John Benjamins Publishing Company This is a contribution from Pragmatics & Cognition 19:1 © 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company This electronic file may not be altered in any way. The author(s) of this article is/are permitted to use this PDF file to generate printed copies to be used by way of offprints, for their personal use only. Permission is granted by the publishers to post this file on a closed server which is accessible to members (students and staff) only of the author’s/s’ institute, it is not permitted to post this PDF on the open internet. For any other use of this material prior written permission should be obtained from the publishers or through the Copyright Clearance Center (for USA: www.copyright.com). Please contact [email protected] or consult our website: www.benjamins.com Tables of Contents, abstracts and guidelines are available at www.benjamins.com Reasoning from paradigms and negative evidence Fabrizio Macagno and Douglas Walton Universidade Nova de Lisboa, Portugal / University of Windsor, Canada Reasoning from negative evidence takes place where an expected outcome is tested for, and when it is not found, a conclusion is drawn based on the sig- nificance of the failure to find it. By using Gricean maxims and implicatures, we show how a set of alternatives, which we call a paradigm, provides the deep inferential structure on which reasoning from lack of evidence is based. We show that the strength of reasoning from negative evidence depends on how the arguer defines his conclusion and what he considers to be in the paradigm of negated alternatives.
    [Show full text]
  • If All Knowledge Is Empirical, Can It Be Necessary?” Analytic and a Priori Statements Have Often Been Portrayed As Being Necessary
    IF ALL KNOWLEDGE IS EMPIRICAL, CAN IT BE NECESSARY? Ísak Andri Ólafsson April 2012 Department of Social Sciences Instructor: Simon Reginald Barker IF ALL KNOWLEDGE IS EMPIRICAL, CAN IT BE NECESSARY? Ísak Andri Ólafsson April 2012 Department of Social Sciences Instructor: Simon Reginald Barker Abstract This thesis is meant to examine whether there is an impossibility of non-empirically known truths. An attempt will be made to show that both analytic truths and a priori knowledge is inherently either empirical or meaningless. From that notion, a framework of a posteriori knowledge will be used to determine whether it is possible to know what constitutes as necessary knowledge. Epistemic luck will be shown to interfere with the justification of empirical truths and furthermore, that Gettier examples deny the equivalence of justified true beliefs as knowledge. A Kripkean notion will be applied to demonstrate the existence of necessary a posteriori truths, although it is impossible to know whether a posteriori truths are necessary or not. Finally, contextualism will be employed to argue against the high standard of knowledge that skepticism introduces. The conclusion is that within a framework of empiricism, there is a possibility of necessary a posteriori truths, even when using the high standard of knowledge the skeptical account introduces. It is however, impossible to know which truths are necessary and which are contingent. From there, a pragmatic account is used to conclude that there are only contingent truths. However, there is also a low standard of knowledge, which is introduced with the aid of contextualism, which can be used effectively to say that it is possible to know things in casual relations, although skeptical contexts that employ a high standard of knowledge still exist.
    [Show full text]
  • "Irrealism and the Genealogy of Morals"
    Irrealism and the genealogy of morals Richard Joyce Penultimate version of the article appearing in Ratio 26 (2013) 351-372 Abstract Facts about the evolutionary origins of morality may have some kind of undermining effect on morality, yet the arguments that advocate this view are varied not only in their strategies but in their conclusions. The most promising such argument is modest: it attempts to shift the burden of proof in the service of an epistemological conclusion. This paper principally focuses on two other debunking arguments. First, I outline the prospects of trying to establish an error theory on genealogical grounds. Second, I discuss how a debunking strategy can work even under the assumption that noncognitivism is true. 1. Introduction to moral debunking arguments A genealogical debunking argument of morality takes data about the origin of moral thinking and uses them to undermine morality. The genealogy could be ontogenetic (like Freud’s) or socio-historical (like Nietzsche’s or Marx’s), but the focus of recent attention has been the evolutionary perspective. ‘Debunking’ and ‘undermining’ are intentionally broad terms, designed to accommodate a number of different strategies and conclusions. Sharon Street’s debunking argument, for example, aims to overthrow moral realism, while leaving intact the possibility of non-objective moral facts (e.g., those recognized by a constructivist) (Street 2006). Michael Ruse’s earlier debunking argument often looks like it has the same aim as Street’s, though on occasions he appears to try for a stronger conclusion: that all moral judgements are false (Ruse 1986, 2006, 2009). My own debunking argument has an epistemological conclusion: that all moral judgements are unjustified (Joyce 2006, 2014).
    [Show full text]