Herbert Spencer

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Herbert Spencer 00 iCNJ !CT> ft HERBERT SPENCER HERBERT SPENCER THE MAN AND HIS WORK BY HECTOR MACPHERSON Author of Thomas Carlyle and Adam Smith SECOND EDITION LONDON CHAPMAN AND HALL LIMITED 1901 DtU I <7D to Edinburgh : T. and A. CONSTABLE, Printers Her Majesty PREFACE A PHILOSOPHIC thinker of the first rank is always known by the amount of literature which his writings call forth. Descartes, Locke, Spinoza, Hume, Kant, Hegel these in their respective spheres were epoch-makers. From the philosophic germs which they scattered have sprung whole libraries of controversial literature. In like manner Mr. Herbert Spencer has paid the penalty of his great philosophic fame. As an epoch-maker, he, too, has had to pass through the fire of hostile criticism. For a great number of years his philo sophy has been the battle-ground of controversialists who, differing in many ways among themselves, have united in their attempts to discredit a system of thought which threatened to destroy long- cherished opinions and stereotyped beliefs. One result of this has been that to the general public the Synthetic Philosophy, embedded as it has been in the works of critics, has necessarily appeared in VI this a fragmentary form. My object in writing reader book has been to present to the general can Spencerism in lucid, coherent shape. Nothing but take the place of Mr. Spencer s own writings, mastery of these demands an amount of leisure are no means and philosophic enthusiasm which by widespread. Until after the first negotiations had been entered upon for the publication of this work Mr. Spencer was unaware that it was in contemplation, but since he has been informed of my design I have had his approval. I must add that Mr. Spencer has not seen a sentence of this work before publication, either in manuscript or in proof. He has been anxious that I should not be influenced by any criticisms he might pass. He has taken a kindly interest in the undertaking, and responded to my request for certain materials. The book is by no means a slavish re production of Mr. Spencer s writings. Taking my stand upon the fundamental ideas of the Synthetic Philosophy, I have used them in my own way to interpret and illustrate the great evolutionary process. While, therefore, Mr. Spencer has been in full sympathy with the aim of the book, he does not stand committed to the detailed treatment of the subject. The work has indeed been a labour PREFACE vii of love. Should it induce the reader to study Spencerism as expounded by the master himself, my reward will be ample. I should be lacking in gratitude did I not express my obligations to the elaborate work of Mr. John Fiske, entitled Outlines of Cosmic Philosophy. No student of Spencer can afford to neglect Mr. Fiske s book, which it would be difficult to rival in point of lucidity and intellectual ability. I am also indebted to Professor Hudson of California for his admirable book, Introduction to the Philo sophy of Herbert Spencer. In the philosophic and economic parts of the book, I have drawn upon a few paragraphs in my Thomas Carlyle and Adam Smith. Knowledge of a philosopher s system of thought is greatly helped by knowledge of the philosopher himself, and in this respect I have been exceedingly fortunate. The recollection of my personal relations with Mr. Spencer will ever be to me a priceless possession. HECTOR MACPHERSON. EDINBURGH, April 1900. CONTENTS CHAP. PAGE I. EARLY LIFE, ...... 1 II. INTELLECTUAL ENVIRONMENT, . .17 III. EVOLUTION OF THE EVOLUTION THEORY, . 38 IV. PERSONAL CHARACTERISTICS, . 52 V. THE COSMOS UNVEILED, . ... 64 VI. THE EVOLUTION OF LIFE, .... 82 JTHE EVOLUTION OF MIND, ... 103 ECONOMIC EVOLUTION OF SOCIETY, . 122 IX. T^E POLITICAL EVOLUTION OF SOCIETY, . 143 IE ETHICAL EVOLUTION OF SOCIETY, . 165 XI. THE EVOLUTION OF RELIGION, . 185 XII. THE PHILOSOPHIC ASPECT OF SPENCERISM, . 196 XIII. THE RELIGIOUS ASPECT OF SPENCERISM, . 210 CHAPTER I EARLY LIFE CARLYLE has remarked that the history of the world is in the main the history of its great men. There is profound truth in the saying, though in his anti pathy to a purely scientific treatment of civilisation Carlyle used his great man theory in fantastic and misleading fashion. The intellectual contribution which each century makes to the progress of the world takes its hue from the dominating influence of its leading thinkers. True greatness is epoch- making. If we wish to discover the place of a thinker in the great evolutionary chain, we must apply th"* epoch-making test. The mind of the great mail is like an overflowing reservoir which makes for itself new channels and fertilises hitherto unknown tracts of thought. Or to use a biological simile, the sociological effects produced by the great man resemble the changes caused in the fauna and flora of a country by the introduction of a new species. Think of the impoverishment which history would sustain by the obliteration of the names, say, A 2 HERBERT SPENCER not of Paul, Augustine, Calvin. Those thinkers only unlocked new forces in their day and generation, but even yet from their tombs they hold sway over the minds of countless thousands. Their specula tions formed the creeds of centuries, and their life passionate and yearning musings upon human and destiny find echo in the souls of some of the noblest of earth s sons. When the long night of authority and credulity was drawing to a close, when the sun of inquiry was dawning above the horizon, great thinkers arose who, from the moun tain-tops of science, foresaw the meridian glory of the Age of Reason. After the splendid work of Mr. John Morley, it is superfluous to dwell upon the achievements in the cause of enlightenment of the intellectual heroes of the Revolution epoch. The great constructive systems of the past had not only fallen before the assault of Reason, but had become cumberers of the ground. The decaying creeds of the past not only impeded the progress of thought, but were a barrier to social amelioration. Paths had to be cut through the jungle, and, in the name of humanity, abuses hoary with the sanctity of re ligion had to be attacked. For the pioneering work accomplished, humanity is everlastingly debtor to the bold thinkers of the Revolution epoch. Not content with the work of destruction, they set themselves to the task of construction. Humanity EARLY LIFE 3 cannot live on negation. Through the writings of Voltaire, Diderot, and the Encyclopaedists may be detected attempts to formulate a conception of man and his destiny which would take the place of the theologic conception which in pre-scientiflc times had done duty for ages as man s attempt to solve of idea the problem Existence ; indeed the of the Encyclopaedia rose out of the feeling that destruction needed to be supplanted by painstaking attempts to attain to a comprehensive, coherent theory of life, in which humanity would find at once intellectual satisfaction and emotional har mony. Out of dissatisfaction with mere negation grew not only the Encyclopaedia, but the imposing systems of Holbach and Helvetius. The time was not ripe for imposing philosophic systems, for the simple reason that knowledge of the universe and man had not gone far enough to be organised on a scientific basis. No system can endure which rests on premature generalisations and unverified speculations; unconsciously the Rationalists of the Revolution imported into their creed-making the unreliable methods of the Theologians. Still their failure on the constructive side should not lessen our admiration for the splendid work they did as liberators of humanity. They loosened the hold of decaying creeds; they cleared the dense forest of the to the thought ; they pointed way promised land of mental freedom and social progress. 4 HERBERT SPENCER After the French Revolution had spent its force, progressive thinkers became alive to the purely destructive nature of that movement on the in tellectual side. Among them was Comte a thinker whose great merits have not had adequate re cognition. Comte had the true sign of greatness intellectual vision. He was not content, like Hume and analytic thinkers generally, to resign himself to the gloom of the forest, or to smother the ever-recurring thoughts of man and his destiny in the petty butterfly attractions of an Epicurean philosophy. His great ambition was to provide a path and an ideal by which humanity would march boldly on to the expansive uplands and heights of truth. Comte s methods were distasteful to his English readers. His colossal egoism, his prefer ence for mediseval modes of thought, and his disparagement of individual liberty and reason, set on edge the critical teeth of many who sympathised with his high-souled endeavours. Destructive critics like Huxley used Comte in order to make sport for the Philistines. The fatal blow to Comte s influence came from the new idea of Evolution, which wrecked his p ilosophic system as it did the systems of Buckle and Mill. All three thinkers found themselves stranded because of their inability to incorporate the n w views which were to revolutionise philoso as phical well as scientific thought. Still, in spite of the ridicule of Huxley and the contemptuous I EARLY LIFE 5 treatment accorded to him in Prance and England, Comte deserves to be held in remembrance as a thinker of fine calibre, prophetic vision, fertile thought, and massiveness of mind. The dominating idea of the last half of the nine teenth century is Evolution an idea so far-reaching in its influence, so mesmeric in its power, that at its touch all other ideas crystallise round it and, as if by magic, yield to its potent sway.
Recommended publications
  • Evolution and Personality [1]
    Evolution and Personality [1] James Gibson Hume (1922) Classics in the History of Psychology An internet resource developed by Christopher D. Green , ISSN 1492-3173 (Return to C lassics i ndex ) Evolution and Personality [1] James Gibson Hume (1922) First published in Philosophical Essays Presented to John Watson (pp. 298-330). : Queen's University.[*] Posted October 2001 Spencer in his Data of Ethics treated his subject from several successive standpoints entitled, The Physical, The Biological, The Psychological, the Sociological. He also attempted to co-ordinate all these various stages into what he termed a Synthetic Philosophy. This would give a fifth standpoint, the Philosophical. These five terms might be used to describe several different types of evolutionary theory. Let us note how these arose, that is, let us trace the evolution of evolutionary theory. Physical Evolution. Early Greek speculation was dominated by this standpoint which found its culmination in the Atomists. Among these Empedocles is noteworthy. He is quoted in the article 'Evolution' in the Encyclopaedia Britannica by J. Sully and T. H. Huxley. After a general Cosmology dealing with the formation of the Cosmos from the four original elements, fire, air, earth, water, by love and discord (attraction and repulsion) he proceeds to treat of the first origin of plants and of animals including man. As the original elements entered into various combinations there arose curious aggregates, heads without [p. 299] necks, arms without shoulders. These got strangely combined. Men's heads on oxen's shoulders, heads of .oxen on men's bodies, etc. Most of these combinations could not survive and so disappeared.
    [Show full text]
  • 003B Alhoff 83
    Hist. Phil. Life Sci., 25 (2003), 83-111 ---83 Evolutionary Ethics from Darwin to Moore Fritz Allhoff Department of Philosophy, University of California, Santa Barbara, CA 93106, USA ABSTRACT - Evolutionary ethics has a long history, dating all the way back to Charles Darwin.1 Almost immediately after the publication of the Origin, an immense interest arose in the moral implications of Darwinism and whether the truth of Darwinism would undermine traditional ethics. Though the biological thesis was certainly exciting, nobody suspected that the impact of the Origin would be confined to the scientific arena. As one historian wrote, ‘whether or not ancient populations of armadillos were transformed into the species that currently inhabit the new world was certainly a topic about which zoologists could disagree. But it was in discussing the broader implications of the theory…that tempers flared and statements were made which could transform what otherwise would have been a quiet scholarly meeting into a social scandal’ (Farber 1994, 22). Some resistance to the biological thesis of Darwinism sprung from the thought that it was incompatible with traditional morality and, since one of them had to go, many thought that Darwinism should be rejected. However, some people did realize that a secular ethics was possible so, even if Darwinism did undermine traditional religious beliefs, it need not have any effects on moral thought.2 Before I begin my discussion of evolutionary ethics from Darwin to Moore, I would like to make some more general remarks about its development.3 There are three key events during this history of evolutionary ethics.
    [Show full text]
  • In Defense of Herbert Spencer
    SUBSCRIBE NOW AND RECEIVE CRISIS AND LEVIATHAN* FREE! “The Independent Review does not accept “The Independent Review is pronouncements of government officials nor the excellent.” conventional wisdom at face value.” —GARY BECKER, Noble Laureate —JOHN R. MACARTHUR, Publisher, Harper’s in Economic Sciences Subscribe to The Independent Review and receive a free book of your choice* such as the 25th Anniversary Edition of Crisis and Leviathan: Critical Episodes in the Growth of American Government, by Founding Editor Robert Higgs. This quarterly journal, guided by co-editors Christopher J. Coyne, and Michael C. Munger, and Robert M. Whaples offers leading-edge insights on today’s most critical issues in economics, healthcare, education, law, history, political science, philosophy, and sociology. Thought-provoking and educational, The Independent Review is blazing the way toward informed debate! Student? Educator? Journalist? Business or civic leader? Engaged citizen? This journal is for YOU! *Order today for more FREE book options Perfect for students or anyone on the go! The Independent Review is available on mobile devices or tablets: iOS devices, Amazon Kindle Fire, or Android through Magzter. INDEPENDENT INSTITUTE, 100 SWAN WAY, OAKLAND, CA 94621 • 800-927-8733 • [email protected] PROMO CODE IRA1703 CONTROVERSY In Defense of Herbert Spencer ✦ MAX HOCUTT n 1978, Liberty Fund published nineteenth-century intellectual giant Herbert Spencer’s Principles of Ethics in two volumes, with an introduction by Tibor R. IMachan. Spencer’s magnificent tome is full of wisdom and will be read with profit for generations. Machan’s brief introduction is more questionable. Calling it “Herbert Spencer: A Century Later,” Machan begins with some biographical details.
    [Show full text]
  • There Is No Alternative: a Discursive Analysis of Past and Present
    There Is No Alternative: A Discursive Analysis of Past and Present By Senne Vandevelde Introduction There is no alternative, or in short: TINA. One would be hard pressed to find a phrase that is so ideologically charged and at the same time so widely used in the world of politics. To disprove it seems straightforward in all circumstances. The starting point of this dissertation is therefore unequivocal: there is always an alternative. Even if a given socio-economic framework does not permit alternatives, it is always possible to alter the framework itself. As such, TINA or any other argument in the same vein is considered to be absurd. Yet both the use of such arguments as well as their appeal have by no means diminished since they were popularised by Margaret Thatcher in the 1980s. On the contrary, with the advent of the sovereign debt crisis in Europe and the austerity policies that ensued, TINA has only grown in importance. However, several people who used TINA during this time have no political affiliation with Thatcher whatsoever. To illustrate, this dissertation studies TINA as it was inserted into the social democratic prime ministerial discourse in Greece and Spain (which were led by George Papandreou and José Luis Rodriguez Zapatero respectively). To find out what this insertion might mean for the Eurozone and Europe today, this dissertation first goes back in time to uncover the discursive history of TINA. While TINA as an expression was coined originally by Herbert Spencer in the middle of the nineteenth century and eventually became part of regular political discourse with Thatcher, the logic of no alternative has been a recurrent theme for generations of advocates of economic liberalism, a discourse which adheres to the free market, free trade and a minimal state.
    [Show full text]
  • 3-Sem-Core-Classical-Sociological
    MULTIPLE CHOICE QUESTIONS SO3CRT03 CLASSICAL SOCIOLOGICAL THEORIES 1. In the history of the development of sociology, ------- is known as a period of remarkable intellectual development and change in philosophical thought. A. Industrial revolution B. Period of enlightenment C. Urbanization D. Religious change 2. The theorists who were most directly and positively influenced by the enlightenment thinking were A. Auguste Comte and Durkheim B. Saint Simon and Durkheim C. Karl Marx and Karl Manheim D. Alexis de Tocqueville and Karl Marx 3. The most extreme form of opposition to Enlightenment ideas was ------ A. French Catholic counterrevolutionary philosophy B. Suffrage Movement C. Orthodox Believers’ Movement D. Western European Union Philosophy 4. One of the prominent leaders of the French Catholic counterrevolutionary philosophy was A. Louis de Bonald B. Lewis Coser C. William Hopkins D. Karl Marx 5. ------------ was greatly influenced by Montesquieu’s ‘The Spirit of the Laws’ A. Machiavelli B. Auguste Comte C. Donald Stevenson D. Alexis de Tocqueville 6. Who coined the term Sociology A. Herbert Spencer B. Saint – Simon C. Auguste Comte D. Karl Marx 7. The scientific view developed by Auguste Comte is known as A. Philosophical science B. Positive philosophy C. Negative philosophy D. Scientific philosophy 8. Auguste Comte initially called Sociology ---------- A. Social dynamics B. Social system C. Social physics D. Social science 9. ‘The Law of Three Stages’ is an idea developed by A. Herbert Spencer B. Auguste Comte C. Karl Marx D. George Simmel 10. Comte developed the Law of Three Stages in his work ---- A. Treatise on Sociology B. Religion of Humanity C.
    [Show full text]
  • ISBN TITLE AUTHOR PUBLISHER/MMEDIUM AREA SHELF LOCATION QUANT 9780761453482 Born for Adventure Kathleen Karr Two Lions Hardcover
    ISBN TITLE AUTHOR PUBLISHER/MMEDIUM AREA SHELF LOCATION QUANT 9780761453482 Born for Adventure Kathleen Karr Two Lions Hardcover Ackerman Children's Literature: Africa 1 9780374371784 Time's Memory Julius Lester Farrar Straus GHardcover Ackerman Children's Literature: Africa 1 At the Crossroads Rachel Isadora Greenwillow Hardcover Ackerman Children's Literature: Africa 1 9780517885444 Tar Beach Faith Ringgold Dragonfly BooPaperback Ackerman Children's Literature: Africa 1 Never Forgotten Patricia McKissack Schwartz and Hardcover Ackerman Children's Literature: Africa 1 9781563978227 Madoulina (Story from West Africa) Joe Bognomo Boyds Mills PrPaperback Ackerman Children's Literature: Africa 1 9780374312893 Circle Unbroken Margot Theis Raven Farrar, Straus Hardcover Ackerman Children's Literature: Africa 1 9780688102562 African Beginnings Kathleen Benson; James Haskins Amistad Hardcover Ackerman Children's Literature: Africa 1 9780688151782 Storytellers, The Ted Lewin Harpercollins Hardcover Ackerman Children's Literature: Africa 1 9780027814903 Abiyoyo Pete Seeger Simon and SchHardcover Ackerman Children's Literature: Africa 1 9780671882686 Fire on the Mountain Earl B. Lewis Simon & SchuHardcover Ackerman Children's Literature: Africa 1 9780690013344 Honey, I Love and Other Love Poems Eloise Greenfield HarperCollins Hardcover Ackerman Children's Literature: Africa 1 9780545270137 One Hen: How One Small Load Made a Big Difference Katie Smith Milway Scholastic Paperback Ackerman Children's Literature: Africa 2 Man of the People: A Novel
    [Show full text]
  • Practical Scientific Knowledge Education Based on Herbert Spencer’S “What Knowledge Is of Most Worth?”
    OPEN ACCESS EURASIA Journal of Mathematics Science and Technology Education ISSN: 1305-8223 (online) 1305-8215 (print) 2017 13(7):4291-4299 DOI: 10.12973/eurasia.2017.00836a Practical Scientific Knowledge Education based on Herbert Spencer’s “What Knowledge is of Most Worth?” Yun-Na Liu Tianjin University of Technology, CHINA Kang Li Motorola, CHINA Arlis McLean Motorola, USA Received 12 December 2017 ▪ Revised 11 May 2017 ▪ Accepted 25 May 2017 ABSTRACT For industrial structure upgrading and modern service industry developing, China will need a large number of high-quality talents to contribute to new industrialization. China's higher education is important for cultivating high-quality, multi-skilled and well-trained talents. “What Knowledge is of most Worth?” that raised by Herbert Spencer is one of the most typical questions for education. After investigation, this study researches 2 questions based on China’s huge demand of well-trained, high-skilled, and application-oriented talents under current economic development: 1) “What Knowledge is of most Worth?” Practical Scientific Knowledge. 2) The guidance on the education practice. The essay demonstrates the challenges and provides constructive suggestions including reform education curriculum, strengthen faculty and enhance university-enterprise cooperation which is multi-win for undergraduates, universities and enterprises. Based on the university-enterprise cooperation practice with company M, the experiences are summarized and the research results can be popularized. This thesis will analyze Herbert Spencer’s “What Knowledge is of Most Worth?”, and provide the helpful advices on practical scientific knowledge education based on Herbert Spencer’s “What Knowledge is of Most Worth?” Keywords: practical scientific knowledge education, Herbert Spencer, worth INTRODUCTION In today’s competition, human resources are the most important resource for achieving the goals.
    [Show full text]
  • How Capitalism Lost Its Soul Marie-Laure Salles-Djelic
    How Capitalism Lost its Soul Marie-Laure Salles-Djelic To cite this version: Marie-Laure Salles-Djelic. How Capitalism Lost its Soul: From Protestant Ethics to Robber Barons. D. Daianu; Radu Vranceanu. Ethical Boundaries of Capitalism, Ashgate Publishing, pp.43 - 64, 2005, 9780754643951. hal-01892001 HAL Id: hal-01892001 https://hal-sciencespo.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-01892001 Submitted on 10 Oct 2018 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. How Capitalism Lost its Soul From Protestant Ethics to Robber Barons Marie-Laure Djelic, ESSEC, France Published in Daianu, D. and Vranceanu, R. (eds), Ethical Boundaries of Capitalism, Ashgate 2005 1. Introduction A serious discussion of capitalism and its development cannot avoid the confrontation, at one moment or another, with ethical issues. Historically, there have been quite a number of different positions in the debate – giving us a sense that the confrontation is, indeed, a complex one. When it comes to the connection between ethics and capitalism, we can differentiate between at least four different ideal typical perspectives. First, we find what we call the missionary perspective. „Missionaries‟ are in general associated with the liberal tradition.
    [Show full text]
  • Left-Libertarianism: a Review Essay
    BARBARA H. FRIED Left-Libertarianism: A Review Essay I. INTRODUCTION Peter Vallentyne and Hillel Steiner's two-volume collection of historical and contemporary works on left-libertarianism formally marks the emergence over the past two decades of a theory of distributive justice that seeks to harness the premises of the libertarian right to the political agenda of the egalitarian left. Its proponents and sympathetic fellow travelers include (in addition to Vallentyne and Steiner) Philippe Van Parijs, Allan Gibbard, Michael Otsuka, Baruch Brody, and James Grunebaum, among others. Vallentyne and Steiner draw together a wealth of interesting material, intelligently situated in the excellent introductory essays and sum- maries provided by the editors. The first volume, The Origins of Left- Libertarianism, contains writings from a number of historical figures whom Vallentyne and Steiner correctly identify as intellectual forebears. In this group are John Locke, early agrarian radicals Thomas Paine and William Ogilvie, liberal socialists of the mid-nineteenth century includ- ing Hippolyte Colins, Leon Walras and Francois Huet, and left-liberal radical land reformers including J. S. Mill, (the early) Herbert Spencer, and, most famously, Henry George. The volume brings to the fore a long This article considers The Origins of Left-Libertarianism: An Anthology of Historical Writings and Left-Libertarianism and its Critics: The Contemporary Debate both edited by Peter Vallentyne and Hillel Steiner (New York: Palgrave, 2000), hereinafter V&S or V&SII. Earlier versions were presented at faculty workshops at Boston University, University of Michigan, Stanford University and New York University law schools. I am grateful to par- ticipants in those workshops, as well as to Elizabeth Anderson, Joseph Bankman, Hugh Baxter, Thomas Grey, Don Herzog, Mark Kelman, Gary Lawson, Debra Satz, Bill Simon and the Editors of Philosophy & Public Affairs for their very helpful comments.
    [Show full text]
  • Durkheim's Refutation of Spencerian Methodological Individualism: a Critical Evaluation
    East Tennessee State University Digital Commons @ East Tennessee State University Electronic Theses and Dissertations Student Works 5-2009 Durkheim's Refutation of Spencerian Methodological Individualism: A Critical Evaluation. Matthew rB yan Smith East Tennessee State University Follow this and additional works at: https://dc.etsu.edu/etd Part of the Theory, Knowledge and Science Commons Recommended Citation Smith, Matthew Bryan, "Durkheim's Refutation of Spencerian Methodological Individualism: A Critical Evaluation." (2009). Electronic Theses and Dissertations. Paper 1891. https://dc.etsu.edu/etd/1891 This Thesis - Open Access is brought to you for free and open access by the Student Works at Digital Commons @ East Tennessee State University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ East Tennessee State University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Durkheim’s Refutation of Spencerian Methodological Individualism: A Critical Evaluation ____________________ A thesis presented to the faculty of the Department of Sociology and Anthropology East Tennessee State University In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree Master of Arts in Sociology ___________________ by Matthew Bryan Smith May 2009 ___________________ Dr. Paul Kamolnick, Chair Dr. Scott Beck Dr. Michael Allen Keywords: Durkheim, Spencer, individualism, social facts, collective consciousness, division of labor, group mind, morality, contract. ABSTRACT Durkheim’s Refutation of Spencerian Methodological Individualism: A Critical Evaluation by Matthew Bryan Smith The famed French classical social theorist Emile Durkheim’s academic reputation is based largely on his critical rejection of the British utilitarian tradition and specifically the writings of the classical British sociologist Herbert Spencer.
    [Show full text]
  • Herbert Spencer
    5 Herbert Spencer Draft Proof - Do not copy, post, or distribute Copyright ©2017 by SAGE Publications, Inc. This work may not be reproduced or distributed in any form or by any means without express written permission of the publisher. Chapter 5 Herbert Spencer 131 Chapter Outline Spencer and Comte General Theoretical Principles Sociology The Evolution of Society Ethics and Politics Criticisms and Contemporary Applications n the theoretical ideas of Herbert Spencer (1820–1903) we see a considerable advance over those of Auguste Comte. Not only was Spencer’s work important in Ithe development of sociological theory, but many of his theoretical ideas stand up well from the vantage point of contemporary sociological theory. In spite of this, Jonathan Turner (1985b; see also Francis, 2007, 2011), who has agreed with many of Spencer’s ideas, pointed out that modern sociological theorists have been disinclined to take Spencer seriously, relegating him, like Comte, to the “dustbin” of history. (Actually, in superheated terms, Turner argued that contemporary social theorists have been inclined to “spit on the grave of Spencer” [1985b:71].) This negativity is, to a large extent, traceable to Spencer’s highly conservative libertarian (not liberal) politics and to his belief in a sociological version of survival of the fittest. Although we do not fully share Turner’s enthusiasm for Spencer, there is much of merit in Spencer’s work. We demonstrate that a number of Spencer’s theoretical ideas con- tinue to be important and relevant to sociological theory. However, there are also serious problems with Spencer’s theory that lead to the conclusion that although it represents an advance over Comtian theory, it is not quite up to the standard of the other major early theorists—Marx, Durkheim, Weber, and Simmel—to be discussed in the ensuing four chapters.
    [Show full text]
  • Rethinking Classical Liberalism in “Progressive” Times: the Divergent
    Rethinking Classical Liberalism in “Progressive” Times: The Divergent Sociologies of Spencer and Sumner Robert Adcock [email protected] Department of Political Science The George Washington University Paper presented at panel on “Rethinking Teleology and Liberalism,” Annual Meeting of the American Political Science Association, Toronto. September 4, 2009. 1 Nineteenth-century liberal political thought was intimately interwoven with theories of transformative social change. Liberal institutions and ideals were championed as the optimal political order for “modern” or “advanced” societies.1 This mode of argument was premised on beliefs about the character of such societies and how they arise. When early nineteenth-century liberals such as Benjamin Constant articulated these beliefs they drew on the theory of the rise of “commercial society” associated with the Scottish Enlightenment.2 But that theory predated, and thus did not speak directly to, democratization and industrialization, the two dominant socially transformative trends of the new century. When Tocqueville updated liberalism by addressing these trends in the 1830s he interpreted them as potential threats to the political order classical liberals advocated: a representative government limited to securing peace, property, and the rule of law, and thereby, a society in which the motor of progress is free competition and association. The dark edge of Tocqueville’s analysis was, however, mitigated by mid-century as liberals such as John Stuart Mill intellectually tamed industrialization and suffrage expansion by interpreting them as extensions of paths of economic and political progress charted in the rise of commerce. Classical liberalism’s limited government ideal was thereby rearticulated as being just as relevant and forward-looking a political theory as it had been early in the century.
    [Show full text]