Comment: Evolutionary Criteria for Considering an Emotion “Basic

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Comment: Evolutionary Criteria for Considering an Emotion “Basic EMR0010.1177/1754073914534481Emotion Review Vol. 6 No. 4Buss 534481research-article2014 Comments Emotion Review Vol. 6, No. 4 (October 2014) 313 –331 © The Author(s) 2014 ISSN 1754-0739 DOI: 10.1177/1754073914534481 Comment: Evolutionary Criteria for Considering er.sagepub.com an Emotion “Basic”: Jealousy as an Illustration David M. Buss Department of Psychology, University of Texas, Austin, USA Abstract Jealousy does not appear on Ekman’s list of basic emotions. Indeed, no theorists have proposed that jealousy has a distinc- Modern evolutionary psychology provides a cogent criterion for considering tive and universally recognized signal, facial or otherwise (e.g., an emotion as “basic”: Whether the emotion evolved to solve an adaptive try making a “jealous face” as a thought experiment). Nor does problem tributary to reproduction. Criteria such as distinctive universal jealousy always have a rapid onset or brief duration. Rather signals, presence in other primates, or contribution to survival are than being considered “basic,” jealousy within Ekman’s frame- not relevant, even though some basic emotions have these properties. work may be considered “derived” or a “blend” of different Abundant evidence suggests that sexual jealousy is properly considered emotions such as anger, fear, and sadness (Ekman, personal a basic emotion, even though it lacks a distinct expressive signature, communication, 1991). contributes to adaptive problems of mating rather than survival, and may The second key proponent of basic emotions from a some- or may not be present in other primates. what different evolutionary framework is Robert Plutchik, who proposes eight primary emotions—anger, fear, sadness, disgust, Keywords surprise, anticipation, trust, and joy (Plutchik, 1980). Plutchik’s basic emotions, evolution, jealousy criteria for basic emotions include: (a) present in nonhuman ani- mals, (b) universally present across cultures in humans, and (c) functional in helping organisms solve adaptive problems of sur- The scientific literature on emotions is rife with debates about vival. As with Ekman’s framework, jealousy does not make whether there exist “basic” emotions. Debates also surround the Plutchik’s list of basic or primary emotions. proper criteria for evaluating whether an emotion is basic or not. Although the frameworks of Ekman and Plutchik are both The most prominent proponent of the existence of basic emo- “evolutionary,” viewed from the vantage point of modern evolu- tions is Paul Ekman, who originally hypothesized the existence tionary psychology the central criteria for considering an emo- of six or seven: anger, disgust, fear, happiness, sadness, and sur- tion as “basic” or “primary” require reevaluation. Specifically, prise are the most agreed-upon six, with contempt being a sev- considering an emotion or any other evolved psychological enth candidate (Ekman, 1973, 1999; Ekman & Cordaro, 2011). mechanism as basic requires the answer to one key question: Did Since his original formulation, Ekman has expanded both the the emotion evolve, shaped by selection, because it solved an criteria for considering an emotion as basic as well as the num- adaptive problem—that is, served a specific function—tributary ber of emotions that might meet those criteria. to reproductive success during the time of its evolution better The central original criterion for evaluating an emotion as than rival designs extant in the population at the time? (see also basic, within Ekman’s theoretical framework, is whether the Nesse, 1990; Tooby & Cosmides, 2008; Tracy, 2014). emotion has a distinctive facial expression that can be recog- This criterion for considering an emotion as basic or primary nized universally (see also Darwin [1872], who considered a requires a bit more elaboration in order to contrast it with the range of emotions, some with distinctive facial features). Other theoretical frameworks of Ekman and Plutchik. Unlike both criteria proposed by Ekman for considering emotions as basic Ekman’s and Plutchik’s frameworks, there is no requirement of include distinctive universal signals, presence in other primates, presence in nonhuman animals, primate or otherwise. No one distinctive physiology, rapid onset, brief duration, automatic would deem the adaptation of echolocation not “basic” in bats, appraisal, and unbidden occurrence (Ekman, 1994). In this brief even if it existed rarely (or never) outside of bat species. Some commentary, I argue that two of these key criteria are problem- adaptations exist in only a single species, such as language in atic from the perspective of modern evolutionary psychology— humans (Pinker & Bloom, 1990). Although many or most emo- distinctive universal signal (facial expression or some other tions may indeed exist in other species or exist in somewhat signal) and presence in other primates. different forms, existence in other species is neither necessary Author note: The author thanks Kelly Asao, Dan Conroy-Beam, Cari Goetz, and Jim Russell for thoughtful comments on an earlier draft. Corresponding author: David M. Buss, Department of Psychology, University of Texas, 1 University Station, A8000, Austin, TX 78712, USA. Email: [email protected] Downloaded from emr.sagepub.com at University of Texas Libraries on September 30, 2015 314 Emotion Review Vol. 6 No. 4 nor sufficient for deeming an emotion as basic according to understood as the specific way in which it contributed to differen- modern evolutionary psychology. tial reproductive success. Whether an evolved emotion comes Second, possessing adaptive functionality is equated with the with a universally recognized signal (some do, some do not) and current understanding of function in modern evolutionary biol- whether it contributes to an adaptive problem of survival (some ogy and psychology (e.g., Buss, 1995; Dawkins, 1982; Tooby & do, some do not) are not proper criteria for considering an emo- Cosmides, 2008; Williams, 1966). Specifically, differential tion basic within the framework of modern evolutionary psychology. reproductive success, not differential survival success, is prop- Basic emotions, of course, are expected to be universal, that erly considered the “engine” of the process of evolution by selec- is, present in most or all humans across cultures. However, uni- tion. Survival is important only inasmuch as it contributes to versality alone can never be used as a sole criterion. There exist reproduction. Moreover, some adaptations evolved that were some universals of humans, such as the use of fire, which may detrimental to survival, but they evolved nonetheless because have attained their universality not because specific adaptations they contributed to relative reproductive success. Examples for them evolved, but rather because they were discovered and include the cumbersome plumage of peacocks, the costly pro- then spread across populations through a process of cultural duction of enormous racks in elk, and elevated levels of testos- transmission. terone and risk-taking in human males—all of which lead to Phenomena that seem like jealousy may exist in other primate shorter lifespans for the males encumbered by them. Because species such as chimpanzees (de Waal, 1982). Nonetheless, these these qualities recurrently led to greater mating success, how- phenomena take unique forms and have distinctive design fea- ever, they evolved despite their costs in the currency of survival. tures in humans due to the particular mating strategies within the This shift is important when it comes to jealousy because human repertoire. Male chimpanzees, for example, show a jeal- sexual jealousy does not necessarily solve a problem of survival. ous-like behavior toward the female and lower ranking males Rather, it has been hypothesized to exist because it contributed to primarily when the female is in estrus. In contrast, men show the solution of adaptive problems of mating. The primary func- sexual jealousy throughout the ovulation cycle of their partner, tions of both male and female sexual jealousy are hypothesized although there is some evidence that it may be especially acute to include deterring infidelity, deterring mate poachers, and when the partner is ovulating (Haselton & Gangestad, 2006). deterring defection from the mateship. These effects historically According to the foregoing analysis, a compelling case can contributed to reproductive success for both men and women by be made that jealousy is indeed a primary or basic emotion. monopolizing a mate’s reproductively relevant resources over There is good evidence that the complex emotion of jealousy the long run. Among men, it additionally increased the probabil- evolved primarily because it solved several key adaptive prob- ity of his genetic paternity in offspring—a key adaptive function lems of mating that were (and possibly still are) tributary to of male sexual jealousy. Jealousy’s irrelevance to survival in no reproduction. Jealousy in mating relationships is largely irrele- way disqualifies it as basic or primary. Of course, successful vant to survival, and in some cases actually is detrimental to mate retention also may contribute to solution to a survival prob- survival. A man whose jealousy upon discovering a mate lem, especially for women who retain mates who partially func- poacher engaged in sexual relations with his wife might cause tion as “body guards.” The key point, though, is that contribution him to launch a physical assault (a crime of passion) puts him- to relative reproductive
Recommended publications
  • Sander-Alphah 203..208
    sander & Scherer Sander-AlphaH Page Proof page 203 28.2.2009 10:08am H happiness The emotion of happiness is a subjective, for optimism. Recent research has found that an individ- valenced reaction to a positive experience or event (Ort- ual’s experiences of happiness can be significantly bol- ony et al. 1988). Happiness can be conceptualized as an stered by the regular, committed practice of activities umbrella term that encompasses a variety of positive such as counting blessings, expressing optimism, and per- feelings, ranging from the low-intensity states of *con- forming acts of kindness (Lyubomirsky et al. 2005b). In tentment, *enjoyment, serenity, and *amusement to the sum, frequent happiness is a highly valued goal that is high-intensity states of elation, *joy, and euphoria. partially a function of *temperament, but can also be These positive states are typically experienced when a attained through effortful intentional activity. person is making progress towards the realization of SONJA LYUBOMIRSKY AND JAIME L. KURTZ *goals (Carver and Scheier 1998), and, notably, signal that the environment is benign and safe for both relax- hatred Hatred, the noun, and to hate, the verb, do not ation and exploration (Schwarz and Clore 1983). As such, completely coincide in their semantic ranges. Hatred researchers had originally conceptualized a happy emo- carries with it more intensity and greater seriousness tion as producing a form of ‘free activation’ that is than many of our most common uses of the verb. conducive to creativity and divergent thought (Frijda Hatred is unlikely to apply aptly to one’s feelings about 1986, Isen et al.
    [Show full text]
  • The Brain Basis of Emotion: a Meta-Analytic Review
    BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (2012) 35, 121–202 doi:10.1017/S0140525X11000446 The brain basis of emotion: A meta-analytic review Kristen A. Lindquist Department of Neurology, Harvard Medical School/Massachusetts General Hospital/Martinos Center for Biomedical Imaging, Charlestown, MA 02129, and Department of Psychology, Harvard University, Cambridge, MA 02138 [email protected] http://www.nmr.mgh.harvard.edu/lindqukr/ Tor D. Wager Department of Psychology and Neuroscience, University of Colorado, Boulder, CO 80309 [email protected] http://www.psych.colorado.edu/tor/ Hedy Kober Department of Psychiatry, Yale University School of Medicine, New Haven, CT 06519 [email protected] http://medicine.yale.edu/psychiatry/people/hedy_kober.profile Eliza Bliss-Moreau California National Primate Research Center, University of California, Davis, CA 95616, and Department of Psychiatry and Behavioral Sciences, University of California, Davis, CA 95616 [email protected] http://www.elizablissmoreau.com/EBM/home.html Lisa Feldman Barrett Department of Psychology, Northeastern University, Boston, MA 02115, and Departments of Radiology and Psychiatry, Harvard Medical School/ Massachusetts General Hospital/Martinos Center for Biomedical Imaging, Charlestown, MA 02129 [email protected] http://www.affective-science.org/ Abstract: Researchers have wondered how the brain creates emotions since the early days of psychological science. With a surge of studies in affective neuroscience in recent decades, scientists are poised to answer this question. In this target article, we present a meta-analytic summary of the neuroimaging literature on human emotion. We compare the locationist approach (i.e., the hypothesis that discrete emotion categories consistently and specifically correspond to distinct brain regions) with the psychological constructionist approach (i.e., the hypothesis that discrete emotion categories are constructed of more general brain networks not specific to those categories) to better understand the brain basis of emotion.
    [Show full text]
  • The-Embodiment-Of-Emotion-Aghu.Pdf
    1 CN Chapter 10 CT The Embodiment of Emotion Lisa Feldman Barrett and Kristen A. Lindquist Boston College To appear in G.R. Semin and E.R. Smith (Eds.), Embodied grounding: social, cognitive, affective and neuroscientific approaches. New York: Cambridge University Press. 2 In current psychological discourse, it is fashionable to talk about emotions as “embodied” phenomena. At first glance, this idea is not novel. Historically, almost all psychological theories of emotion have proposed that emotional reactions are constituted by the body in some fashion. Some suggest that changes in the body cause changes in the mind; others suggest the opposite, or that the body and mind interact to produce an emotional response. Amid theoretical differences, these theories use the common metaphor that the body and mind are separate and independent forces that can act upon one another in an emotional episode. Current embodiment theories of the mind challenge this assumption by suggesting that the body helps to constitute the mind in shaping an emotional response. This view has novel implications for understanding the structure and content of the conceptual system for emotion, as well as for defining what emotions are and how they are caused. In the present chapter, we explore a more modern embodiment view of emotion. First, we discuss how the Cartesian “machine metaphor” underlies much theorizing about emotion, as we situate an embodied view of emotion in its historical context. Our historical review is not intended to be comprehensive but rather to illustrate how emotion theories to date have conceptualized the role of the body and mind in emotion.
    [Show full text]
  • Unconscious Emotion
    (9)") (t-,r^r) 1,,R .9-L^*. 1\ L'x)J-"1 t UnconsciousEmotio7n9 7 AJed--qJ"-lq-t'L tf L*'nh"-' |3 C-7,e"'< Emotions are meansd esignedt o regulateb ehaviori n relation to agendass et 0U''<-u'> f r-aa ^fr> Yt-lL " D<A'-J by biological evolution.T hus, emotion pervadedt he critical ecologicalp roblems L that our distanta ncestorsh ad to solve if their genesw ere to be representeidn the UnconsciousE motion: nextg enerationT. hesep roblemsin cludedf indinga nd consumingfo od andd rink, finding shelterss, eekingp rotectiona nd supportf rom conspecificsa, ssertingo neself Evoul tionaryP erspectives, socially, satisfyingc uriosity,g etringa ccesst o and engagingw ith sexualp artners, caring for offspring,a nd avoiding and escapingli fe-threateninge vents.T hesea re PsychophysiologicDaal ta,a nd all activitiess tructuredb y emotions( seeT ooby & Cosmides,1 990).I n a biological perspectivet,h erefore,e motionsc an be understooda s clever meanss hapedb y evo- NeuropsychologicMale chanisms lution to make us want to do what our ancestorhsa d to do successfulltyo pass geneso n to comingg eneration(se .g.,O hman,1 993a,1 996). ConceptuaIlm plications A R N E O H M A N , A N D E R SF L Y K T , A N D D A N I E L I - U N D Q V I S T The evolutionary-functionapl erspectiveo n the psychologyo f emotion shifts the emphasisf rom the unique phenomenologyo f human feeling to action tendencies and responsep attemst hat we sharew ith fellow inhabitantso f the animalk ingdom, Rathert han conceptualizinge motiona s a centralf eelings tatem ore or lessi mper- fectly
    [Show full text]
  • Current Directions in Psychological Science
    Current Directions in Psychological Science http://cdp.sagepub.com/ What Are Emotion Expressions For? Azim F. Shariff and Jessica L. Tracy Current Directions in Psychological Science 2011 20: 395 DOI: 10.1177/0963721411424739 The online version of this article can be found at: http://cdp.sagepub.com/content/20/6/395 Published by: http://www.sagepublications.com On behalf of: Association for Psychological Science Additional services and information for Current Directions in Psychological Science can be found at: Email Alerts: http://cdp.sagepub.com/cgi/alerts Subscriptions: http://cdp.sagepub.com/subscriptions Reprints: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.nav Permissions: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.nav >> Version of Record - Dec 5, 2011 What is This? Downloaded from cdp.sagepub.com by Jessica Tracy on December 8, 2011 Current Directions in Psychological Science What Are Emotion Expressions For? 20(6) 395 –399 © The Author(s) 2011 Reprints and permission: sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.nav DOI: 10.1177/0963721411424739 Azim F. Shariff1 and Jessica L. Tracy2 http://cdps.sagepub.com 1University of Oregon and 2University of British Columbia Abstract Although research on the nonverbal expression of emotion has played a prominent role throughout psychology during the past two decades—including an instrumental role in the development of contemporary evolutionary psychology—little research has focused on the evolutionary origins and functions of the emotional expressions themselves. However, recent findings from psychophysical, comparative, social, and cross-cultural psychology are converging to produce a compelling functionalist account, suggesting that emotional expressions serve critical adaptive purposes. Most of these studies have narrowly focused on single emotions—an approach that has been very useful for providing new insights about specific expressions but not for developing a broader understanding of why humans universally display and recognize distinct emotions.
    [Show full text]
  • A Framework for Digital Emotions Meghan Rosatelli Virginia Commonwealth University
    Virginia Commonwealth University VCU Scholars Compass Theses and Dissertations Graduate School 2011 A Framework for Digital Emotions Meghan Rosatelli Virginia Commonwealth University Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarscompass.vcu.edu/etd Part of the Interdisciplinary Arts and Media Commons © The Author Downloaded from http://scholarscompass.vcu.edu/etd/239 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at VCU Scholars Compass. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of VCU Scholars Compass. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Copyright © 2011 by Meghan Rosatelli All rights reserved A Framework for Digital Emotions A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy at Virginia Commonwealth University by Meghan Elizabeth Rosatelli Bachelor of Arts, University of Colorado at Boulder, 2004 Master of Arts, Virginia Commonwealth University, 2007 Director: Dr. Richard Fine Professor, Department of English Virginia Commonwealth University Richmond, Virginia August 2011 TABLE OF CONTENTS LIST OF FIGURES……………………………………………………………..……………..…iii LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS…………………………………………………………………….iv ABSTRACT……………………………………………………………………………………….v INTRODUCTION…………………………………………………………………………...……1 PART 1. A FRAMEWORK FOR DIGITAL EMOTIONS……….…………………….……….22 Chapter 1. Emotions are Fickle Things………………………………………………………..…23 Chapter 2. Emotions Put the “New” in “New Media”……………………………………….…..61
    [Show full text]
  • Evolution of Emotion Semantics
    To appear in Cognition. This preprint may contain errors not present in the published version. Evolution of emotion semantics Aotao Xua,∗, Jennifer E. Stellarb, Yang Xua,c aDepartment of Computer Science, University of Toronto bDepartment of Psychology, University of Toronto cCognitive Science Program, University of Toronto Abstract Humans possess the unique ability to communicate emotions through language. Although concepts like anger or awe are abstract, there is a shared consensus about what these English emotion words mean. This consensus may give the impression that their meaning is static, but we propose this is not the case. We cannot travel back to earlier periods to study emotion concepts directly, but we can examine text corpora, which have partially preserved the mean- ing of emotion words. Using natural language processing of historical text, we found evidence for semantic change in emotion words over the past century and that varying rates of change were predicted in part by an emotion concept's prototypicality|how representative it is of the broader category of \emotion". Prototypicality negatively correlated with historical rates of emotion semantic change obtained from text-based word embeddings, beyond more established variables including usage frequency in English and a second comparison lan- guage, French. This effect for prototypicality did not consistently extend to the semantic category of birds, suggesting its relevance for predicting seman- tic change may be category-dependent. Our results suggest emotion semantics arXiv:2108.02887v1 [cs.CL] 5 Aug 2021 are evolving over time, with prototypical emotion words remaining semantically stable, while other emotion words evolve more freely. Keywords: emotion; semantic change; semantic stability; prototype theory; word embedding ∗Corresponding author Email address: [email protected] (Aotao Xu) Preprint submitted to Cognition August 9, 2021 1 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Is Emotion a Natural Kind?*
    Is Emotion a Natural Kind?* Paul E. Griffiths, Department of History and Philosophy of Science, University of Pittsburgh, Pittsburgh, PA 15232, USA [email protected] 7280wds plus references 1. Introduction In What Emotions Really Are: The problem of psychological categories (Griffiths, 1997) I argued that it is unlikely that all the psychological states and processes that fall under the vernacular category of emotion are sufficiently similar to one another to allow a unified scientific psychology of the emotions. The psychological, neuroscientific and biological theories that best explain any particular subset of human emotions will not adequately explain all human emotions. In a slogan, emotions are not a natural kind (pp. 14-17; 241-247)i. I argued that the same is probably true of many specific emotion categories, such as anger and love (p. 17). On some occasions when a person is properly said to be angry, certain psychological, neuroscientific and biological theories will adequately explain what is happening to that person. On other occasions of anger, however, different theories will be needed. I described my position as eliminitivism about emotion, because it implies that the term ‘emotion’ and some specific emotion terms like ‘anger’ are examples of what philosophers of language have called ‘partial reference’ (p. 242). The term ‘jade’ is the classic example of partial reference. The term ‘jade’ is used as if it referred to a particular kind of mineral, in the same manner as ‘malachite’ or ‘diamond’. In reality, however, the term covers two different stones, jadeite or nephrite. The term ‘jade’ partially refers to each of these two minerals.
    [Show full text]
  • The Problem of Privacy in the Evolution of Emotion and Emotional
    The Problem of Privacy and the Evolution of Emotion and Emotional Behavior T. V. Joe Layng, Ph.D. I will begin by retelling a story I that first heard from Israel Goldiamond. I have always wanted a bear skin. You can imagine how happy I was when I finally had the opportunity to hunt for one. For hours I tracked a bear through the woods and finally, there it was, my dream was about to come true. I carefully raised my rifle taking aim at the bear. At the same time, the bear saw me. It raised up on two legs, and growled a very menacing growl. I didn’t care, I was elated. My dream, my quest was to be realized. My heart pounded with excitement as I took aim, and then in a culminating act, pulled the trigger. Click. Click was all I heard. No gunshot. I tried again. Click. The rifle had apparently jammed. Fear quickly spread through my body. The bear was raised as before and my rifle was still aimed at the bear. But something had changed. Instead of a nice new bear rug in the living room, the bear was about to get a nice new human skin for its den. That is, the consequences had changed, or, more precisely, there had been a change in consequential contingencies. Same stimulus, same behavior, massively different consequence. The swift change from elation to fear tracked the swift change in contingencies. I began to run. Was I running because I was afraid? Was I afraid because I was running? No.
    [Show full text]
  • The Brain Basis of Emotion: a Meta-Analytic Review
    BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (2012) 35, 121–202 doi:10.1017/S0140525X11000446 The brain basis of emotion: A meta-analytic review Kristen A. Lindquist Department of Neurology, Harvard Medical School/Massachusetts General Hospital/Martinos Center for Biomedical Imaging, Charlestown, MA 02129, and Department of Psychology, Harvard University, Cambridge, MA 02138 [email protected] http://www.nmr.mgh.harvard.edu/lindqukr/ Tor D. Wager Department of Psychology and Neuroscience, University of Colorado, Boulder, CO 80309 [email protected] http://www.psych.colorado.edu/tor/ Hedy Kober Department of Psychiatry, Yale University School of Medicine, New Haven, CT 06519 [email protected] http://medicine.yale.edu/psychiatry/people/hedy_kober.profile Eliza Bliss-Moreau California National Primate Research Center, University of California, Davis, CA 95616, and Department of Psychiatry and Behavioral Sciences, University of California, Davis, CA 95616 [email protected] http://www.elizablissmoreau.com/EBM/home.html Lisa Feldman Barrett Department of Psychology, Northeastern University, Boston, MA 02115, and Departments of Radiology and Psychiatry, Harvard Medical School/ Massachusetts General Hospital/Martinos Center for Biomedical Imaging, Charlestown, MA 02129 [email protected] http://www.affective-science.org/ Abstract: Researchers have wondered how the brain creates emotions since the early days of psychological science. With a surge of studies in affective neuroscience in recent decades, scientists are poised to answer this question. In this target article, we present a meta-analytic summary of the neuroimaging literature on human emotion. We compare the locationist approach (i.e., the hypothesis that discrete emotion categories consistently and specifically correspond to distinct brain regions) with the psychological constructionist approach (i.e., the hypothesis that discrete emotion categories are constructed of more general brain networks not specific to those categories) to better understand the brain basis of emotion.
    [Show full text]
  • Emotion and the Affective Sciences
    The Oxford Companion - TO- Emotion and the Affective Sciences EDITED BY DAVID SANDER AND KLAUS R. SCHERER OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS eustress continues to evolve, we may learn we have new powers entails a cognitive judgement as to desirability, value, or or limitations we did not previously know of, which is significance; an affective reaction or disposition along sure to give rise to new ethical issues. the dimensions of reward/aversion, pleasure/pain, and LOUIS C. CHARLAND goodness/badness; and a behavioural component along the dimension of approach/ avoidance (see APPROACH/ eustress The concept of eustress was introduced by WITHDRAWAL). Evaluative processes are multiple, extend­ Selye (1964) to refer to the ensemble of positive adaptive ing from genetically endowed approach/avoidance re­ reactions of the organism to beneficial stressors, as op­ actions to positive and negative stimuli, respectively. posed to *distress, which he viewed as a specific syn­ Examples include positive approach I ingestion responses drome that was triggered by unspecific harmful stimuli to palatable flavours and the negative avoidance I with­ or activities (general adaptation syndrome). For Selye, drawal reactions to pain stimuli. Other evaluative eustress represents the pleasant *stress of fulfilment, judgements may be acquired and based on mid-level without the harmful consequences of damaging distress. · associative processes and higher-level cognitive pro­ This concept includes properties of the stressor (benefi­ cesses. Examples include the positive rewarding effects cial stressor), the effort (positive valence), and the effects of money (which may have no intrinsic value, in and of (without damaging outcomes). Stressors are seen as itself ) or fear, anxiety, or avoidance reactions to things beneficial when they do not exceed the capacity for like snakes or the sound of a dentist's drill.
    [Show full text]
  • Of Emotion Tancies and Be Externalized As Social Sensu Strictu Is Restricted
    7~~~ ___________________________________ BOOKREVIEVVS __________________ N_A_TU__ R_E_V_O_L_.3_2_3~ __ O_CT __ OB_E_R_l_~_6 vides a new feeling system that coincides whose evolutionary origin and brain struc­ Great expectancies with the evolution of mammals; and (3) ture are quite different from those of these feelings can in turn modify expec­ mammals, to whom, apparently, emotion of emotion tancies and be externalized as social sensu strictu is restricted. Eric A. Sa/zen signals of emotional states. Students might find Parts I-III of this Livesey thus effectively matches his book valuable in appreciating the theore­ earlier definition of emotion, no doubt tical propositions of Part IV. The special­ Learning and Emotion: A Biological to his satisfaction and pleasure. His thesis ist reader, however, might have preferred Synthesis. Volume 1, Evolutionary Pro­ implies that the evolution of emotion de­ the relevant facts to have been referenced cesses. By Peter J. Livesey. Lawrence pended on the evolution of learned expec­ and integrated into the presentation of the Erlbaum:i986. Pp.312. $32.50, £22. tancies. He also proposes that the function theory. In Vol. 2 of the work (which, I'm of emotion is to feed back and influence told, will not be published until 1988 or EMOTION has been variously seen as expectancies and so act as a "teaching so), Livesey proposes to identify the providing emergency support responses, mechanism". If emotion guides learning neural systems for directing attention to energizing and response amplification, as Livesey implies, one wonders what relevant stimuli and for organizing appro­ motivation through incentive and re­ guided Oscar Wilde when, in The Picture priate behaviour on subsequent encoun­ inforcement, and adaptive instinctive of Dorian Gray, he wrote: "The advan­ ters, with special reference to the role of responses, or as being non-functional tage of the emotions is that they lead us the limbic system in the mediation of this response disorganization.
    [Show full text]