Experimental Evolution and Evolvability

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Experimental Evolution and Evolvability Heredity (2008) 100, 464–470 & 2008 Nature Publishing Group All rights reserved 0018-067X/08 $30.00 www.nature.com/hdy SHORT REVIEW Experimental evolution: experimental evolution and evolvability N Colegrave1 and S Collins1,2 1Institute of Evolutionary Biology, School of Biological Sciences, University of Edinburgh, Edinburgh, UK and 2Max Planck Institute for Plant Breeding Research, Cologne, Germany The suggestion that there are characteristics of living organ- architecture. In each case, we summarize what studies of isms that have evolved because they increase the rate of experimental evolution have told us so far and speculate on evolution is controversial and difficult to study. In this review, we where progress might be made in the future. We show that, examine the role that experimental evolution might play in while experimental evolution has helped us to begin to resolving this issue. We focus on three areas in which understand the evolutionary dynamics of traits that affect experimental evolution has been used previously to examine evolvability, many interesting questions remain to be answered. questions of evolvability; the evolution of mutational supply, the Heredity (2008) 100, 464–470; doi:10.1038/sj.hdy.6801095; evolution of genetic exchange and the evolution of genetic published online 23 January 2008 Keywords: experimental evolution; evolvability; mutator; sex; robustness Introduction Many features of organisms have been proposed as evolvability traits, and most can be loosely classified into Natural selection produces organisms that are well one of the three categories. First, there are characters that adapted to their environment and the explanation of how directly increase the input of genetic variation. The complex adaptation may arise has been one of the great elevated mutation rate observed in many species of successes of the neo-Darwinian synthesis. There is little bacteria is one obvious example. Similarly, there is some doubt that the functional significance of traits as diverse as evidence that the existence of hypermutable domains the clutch size of great tits and the infanticide behaviour of within the genomes of pathogenic bacteria and viruses male lions can be explained in terms of their effect on an may allow more rapid adaptive responses in the face of individual’s genetic contribution to the future. But are host immune pressure (Moxon et al., 1994; Earl and there characteristics of organisms that function not to Deem, 2004). Second, there are characters that increase increase their fitness, but instead to increase evolvability? genetic variation by mixing genetic material from That is, are there traits that are selected and maintained different lineages. The widespread existence of eukar- because they increase the ability of a population to respond yotic sex has been explained in this context, but genetic to natural selection? Increasingly, the suggestion that many exchange by various mechanisms is also common place features of organismic design can only be understood in among non-eukaryotes (Redfield, 2001). Third, there are this context is taking hold (Kirschner and Gerhart, 1998; characters that increase evolvability by altering the link Earl and Deem, 2004). However, such claims are con- between genotype and phenotype and so modulating the troversial and clear evidence has been hard to come by way in which a given amount of genetic variation is (Poole et al., 2003; Sniegowski and Murphy, 2006). Indeed, expressed at the phenotype level. This category includes even the term evolvability has been defined and used in a diverse array of organismic features that are less easily different ways, from a technical measure of the amount of characterized than the previous two. The modularity of additive genetic variation within a population to the ability organismic design, the structure of gene networks and of a population to generate novel variation or acquire novel genetic architecture and the robustness of developmental functions (Kirschner and Gerhart, 1998; Wagner, 2005; mechanisms are examples of characters that may Sniegowski and Murphy, 2006). Here, we define evolva- increase evolvability in this way (Wagner and Altenberg, bility as the ability of a population to both generate and use 1996; Kirschner and Gerhart, 1998; Wagner, 2005; genetic variation to respond to natural selection and an Hansen, 2006). evolvability trait as a character that is selected because of In theory, there is nothing to preclude the selection of its effects on evolvability. traits that have no other effect than to increase the evolutionary potential of a population. However, in contrast to genes with direct effects on fitness, which Correspondence: Dr N Colegrave, Institute of Evolutionary Biology, respond directly to selection, evolvability genes are School of Biological Sciences, University of Edinburgh, Ashworth Labs, subject to indirect selection. Take as an example a gene King’s buildings, Edinburgh EH9 3JT, UK. E-mail: [email protected] that increases the genomic mutation rate, but has no Received 16 May 2007; revised 12 October 2007; accepted 28 October other effect. Such a gene can potentially increase in 2007; published online 23 January 2008 frequency if it can ‘hitchhike’ with novel beneficial Experimental evolution and evolvability N Colegrave and S Collins 465 mutations that it creates (Sniegowski et al., 2000). Such down, and is unlikely to be a significant force in sexual indirect selection will be weak in comparison to direct organisms. selection, but even weak evolutionary forces can have Naturally occurring mutator strains are found in many considerable importance over the long timescales of bacteria, including Escherichia coli. Loss-of-function mu- evolutionary history. tations in DNA repair systems means that these strains However, while evolvability traits are possible in have a mutation rate 10- to100-fold higher than wild-type theory, demonstrating that a particular trait has been strains. This has allowed the evolutionary dynamics of shaped by such selection pressures is far from straight- mutator genotypes to be examined in the lab. Early forward. First, it is necessary to show that the trait really experiments showed that chemostats inoculated with does increase the rate of adaptation. For example, mixtures of mutator and wild-type E. coli would increasing the supply of beneficial mutations could frequently become dominated by the mutator genotype potentially increase the rate of adaptation, but may have (Cox and Gibson, 1974; Chao and Cox, 1983). The little actual effect if adaptation is not limited by appearance and subsequent spread to fixation of mutator mutational supply. Second, it is also necessary to show alleles within 3 of the 12 long-term selection lines of the that selection favours the trait because it increases Lenski’s group (Sniegowski et al., 1997) showed that such evolvability rather than increased evolvability being an genes can also spread when they arise naturally. Together unselected by-product of selection for some other these results provide direct evidence that genes for function (Sniegowski and Murphy, 2006). This distinction elevated mutation rate can spread through populations, between the adaptive value of a trait and its unselected and that they do so at a rate too high to be explained by consequences is critical if we are to fully understand the genetic drift. However, is increased evolvability the forces that have moulded a trait (Williams, 1996). selective force driving the increase in frequency of these Experimental evolution offers the potential to examine mutators or is their spread due to some other direct directly the evolutionary dynamics of putative evolva- selective benefit? bility traits. Such experiments allow researchers to Further experiments cast doubt on a necessary link observe directly whether a trait does indeed increase between elevated mutation rate and increased evolva- the rate of adaptation of a population, and if so, under bility. When the rate of adaptation of mutator and wild- what circumstances. In addition, it is possible to observe type E. coli was compared directly, elevated mutation whether such traits increase in frequency in situations rate had minimal effect on the rate of adaptation except where the rate of adaptation is limiting (and perhaps in poorly adapted populations with small effective equally importantly, that they do not increase in population sizes (de Visser et al., 1999). The rate of frequency when it is not). In this review, we will examine adaptation of larger populations was limited, not by the some of the ways in which the techniques of experi- rate of mutational supply, but by the efficiency of mental evolution may improve our understanding of selection, and so elevated mutation rates had little effect evolvability. We will not attempt a complete overview of (Gerrish and Lenski, 1998; de Visser et al., 1999). Thus, the field. Instead, we begin by focusing on two areas, the increased mutational supply does not guarantee an evolution of elevated mutation rates in bacteria and the increase in evolvability. evolution of eukaryotic sex. These are areas in which our However, clear evidence that mutator genes can understanding of the evolutionary processes is reason- spread because they increase evolvability came from ably well-developed, and experimental evolution studies detailed examination of the three mutator lines from have been central in aiding that development. We will Lenski’s experiments. In two of the three lines, the then examine the much more controversial question of spread of the mutator genotype was accompanied by an whether aspects of genetic architecture have evolved to increase in the rate of adaptation relative to populations increase evolvability (Wagner, 2005; Hansen, 2006). This that did not substitute mutator alleles (Shaver et al., is an area that has received a great deal of attention 2002). In addition, there was no evidence that the recently, but in which our understanding is much less increase in mutation rate seen was favoured by direct well-developed. We will highlight how experimental selection (Shaver et al., 2002). However, the observed evolution might help to develop this understanding.
Recommended publications
  • Transformations of Lamarckism Vienna Series in Theoretical Biology Gerd B
    Transformations of Lamarckism Vienna Series in Theoretical Biology Gerd B. M ü ller, G ü nter P. Wagner, and Werner Callebaut, editors The Evolution of Cognition , edited by Cecilia Heyes and Ludwig Huber, 2000 Origination of Organismal Form: Beyond the Gene in Development and Evolutionary Biology , edited by Gerd B. M ü ller and Stuart A. Newman, 2003 Environment, Development, and Evolution: Toward a Synthesis , edited by Brian K. Hall, Roy D. Pearson, and Gerd B. M ü ller, 2004 Evolution of Communication Systems: A Comparative Approach , edited by D. Kimbrough Oller and Ulrike Griebel, 2004 Modularity: Understanding the Development and Evolution of Natural Complex Systems , edited by Werner Callebaut and Diego Rasskin-Gutman, 2005 Compositional Evolution: The Impact of Sex, Symbiosis, and Modularity on the Gradualist Framework of Evolution , by Richard A. Watson, 2006 Biological Emergences: Evolution by Natural Experiment , by Robert G. B. Reid, 2007 Modeling Biology: Structure, Behaviors, Evolution , edited by Manfred D. Laubichler and Gerd B. M ü ller, 2007 Evolution of Communicative Flexibility: Complexity, Creativity, and Adaptability in Human and Animal Communication , edited by Kimbrough D. Oller and Ulrike Griebel, 2008 Functions in Biological and Artifi cial Worlds: Comparative Philosophical Perspectives , edited by Ulrich Krohs and Peter Kroes, 2009 Cognitive Biology: Evolutionary and Developmental Perspectives on Mind, Brain, and Behavior , edited by Luca Tommasi, Mary A. Peterson, and Lynn Nadel, 2009 Innovation in Cultural Systems: Contributions from Evolutionary Anthropology , edited by Michael J. O ’ Brien and Stephen J. Shennan, 2010 The Major Transitions in Evolution Revisited , edited by Brett Calcott and Kim Sterelny, 2011 Transformations of Lamarckism: From Subtle Fluids to Molecular Biology , edited by Snait B.
    [Show full text]
  • Evolving Neural Networks That Are Both Modular and Regular: Hyperneat Plus the Connection Cost Technique Joost Huizinga, Jean-Baptiste Mouret, Jeff Clune
    Evolving Neural Networks That Are Both Modular and Regular: HyperNeat Plus the Connection Cost Technique Joost Huizinga, Jean-Baptiste Mouret, Jeff Clune To cite this version: Joost Huizinga, Jean-Baptiste Mouret, Jeff Clune. Evolving Neural Networks That Are Both Modular and Regular: HyperNeat Plus the Connection Cost Technique. GECCO ’14: Proceedings of the 2014 Annual Conference on Genetic and Evolutionary Computation, ACM, 2014, Vancouver, Canada. pp.697-704. hal-01300699 HAL Id: hal-01300699 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-01300699 Submitted on 11 Apr 2016 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. To appear in: Proceedings of the Genetic and Evolutionary Computation Conference. 2014 Evolving Neural Networks That Are Both Modular and Regular: HyperNeat Plus the Connection Cost Technique Joost Huizinga Jean-Baptiste Mouret Jeff Clune Evolving AI Lab ISIR, Université Pierre et Evolving AI Lab Department of Computer Marie Curie-Paris 6 Department of Computer Science CNRS UMR 7222 Science University of Wyoming Paris, France University of Wyoming [email protected] [email protected] [email protected] ABSTRACT 1. INTRODUCTION One of humanity’s grand scientific challenges is to create ar- An open and ambitious question in the field of evolution- tificially intelligent robots that rival natural animals in intel- ary robotics is how to produce robots that possess the intel- ligence and agility.
    [Show full text]
  • High Heritability of Telomere Length, but Low Evolvability, and No Significant
    bioRxiv preprint doi: https://doi.org/10.1101/2020.12.16.423128; this version posted December 16, 2020. The copyright holder for this preprint (which was not certified by peer review) is the author/funder. All rights reserved. No reuse allowed without permission. 1 High heritability of telomere length, but low evolvability, and no significant 2 heritability of telomere shortening in wild jackdaws 3 4 Christina Bauch1*, Jelle J. Boonekamp1,2, Peter Korsten3, Ellis Mulder1, Simon Verhulst1 5 6 Affiliations: 7 1 Groningen Institute for Evolutionary Life Sciences, University of Groningen, Nijenborgh 7, 8 9747AG Groningen, The Netherlands 9 2 present address: Institute of Biodiversity Animal Health & Comparative Medicine, College 10 of Medical, Veterinary and Life Sciences, University of Glasgow, Glasgow G12 8QQ, United 11 Kingdom 12 3 Department of Animal Behaviour, Bielefeld University, Morgenbreede 45, 33615 Bielefeld, 13 Germany 14 15 16 * Correspondence to: 17 [email protected] 18 19 Running head: High heritability of telomere length bioRxiv preprint doi: https://doi.org/10.1101/2020.12.16.423128; this version posted December 16, 2020. The copyright holder for this preprint (which was not certified by peer review) is the author/funder. All rights reserved. No reuse allowed without permission. 20 Abstract 21 Telomere length (TL) and shortening rate predict survival in many organisms. Evolutionary 22 dynamics of TL in response to survival selection depend on the presence of genetic variation 23 that selection can act upon. However, the amount of standing genetic variation is poorly known 24 for both TL and TL shortening rate, and has not been studied for both traits in combination in 25 a wild vertebrate.
    [Show full text]
  • 12 Evolvability of Real Functions
    i i i i Evolvability of Real Functions PAUL VALIANT , Brown University We formulate a notion of evolvability for functions with domain and range that are real-valued vectors, a compelling way of expressing many natural biological processes. We show that linear and fixed-degree polynomial functions are evolvable in the following dually-robust sense: There is a single evolution algorithm that, for all convex loss functions, converges for all distributions. It is possible that such dually-robust results can be achieved by simpler and more-natural evolution algorithms. Towards this end, we introduce a simple and natural algorithm that we call wide-scale random noise and prove a corresponding result for the L2 metric. We conjecture that the algorithm works for a more general class of metrics. 12 Categories and Subject Descriptors: F.1.1 [Computation by Abstract Devices]: Models of Computa- tion—Self-modifying machines; G.1.6 [Numerical Analysis]: Optimization—Convex programming; I.2.6 [Artificial Intelligence]: Learning—Concept learning;J.3[Computer Applications]: Life and Medical Sciences—Biology and genetics General Terms: Algorithms, Theory Additional Key Words and Phrases: Evolvability, optimization ACM Reference Format: Valiant, P. 2014. Evolvability of real functions. ACM Trans. Comput. Theory 6, 3, Article 12 (July 2014), 19 pages. DOI:http://dx.doi.org/10.1145/2633598 1. INTRODUCTION Since Darwin first assembled the empirical facts that pointed to evolution as the source of the hugely diverse and yet finely honed mechanisms of life, there has been the mys- tery of how the biochemical mechanisms of evolution (indeed, how any mechanism) can apparently consistently succeed at finding innovative solutions to the unexpected problems of life.
    [Show full text]
  • The University of Chicago Epistasis, Contingency, And
    THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO EPISTASIS, CONTINGENCY, AND EVOLVABILITY IN THE SEQUENCE SPACE OF ANCIENT PROTEINS A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF THE DIVISION OF THE BIOLOGICAL SCIENCES AND THE PRITZKER SCHOOL OF MEDICINE IN CANDIDACY FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY GRADUATE PROGRAM IN BIOCHEMISTRY AND MOLECULAR BIOPHYSICS BY TYLER NELSON STARR CHICAGO, ILLINOIS AUGUST 2018 Table of Contents List of Figures .................................................................................................................... iv List of Tables ..................................................................................................................... vi Acknowledgements ........................................................................................................... vii Abstract .............................................................................................................................. ix Chapter 1 Introduction ......................................................................................................1 1.1 Sequence space and protein evolution .............................................................1 1.2 Deep mutational scanning ................................................................................2 1.3 Epistasis ...........................................................................................................3 1.4 Chance and determinism ..................................................................................4 1.5 Evolvability ......................................................................................................6
    [Show full text]
  • Experimental Evolution
    Heredity (2008) 100, 441–442 & 2008 Nature Publishing Group All rights reserved 0018-067X/08 $30.00 www.nature.com/hdy EDITORIAL Experimental evolution Heredity (2008) 100, 441–442; doi:10.1038/hdy.2008.19 and their interactions, it should be possible to predict which genes will be altered, how they will be altered and in what order, in any defined environment. Our under- Microcosms are used in ecology and evolution to shrink standing of cell biology is as yet wholly inadequate for space and time to manageable scales. They have never the task, but the smaller genomes of viruses might be been extensively used in ecology, because many ecolo- more accessible. Bull and Molineux describe the most gists doubt that any important features of large complex ambitious attempts to date in pursuit of this grail, using systems, such as lakes, can be profitably investigated in phage T7 of E. coli. Given the detailed knowledge of T7 small chambers or vials (Carpenter, 1996). Consequently, genetics, it should be possible to introduce a specific ecology lacks any generally accepted model system genetic lesion and then predict what compensatory to facilitate the cumulative growth of understanding of mutations will be fixed so as to restore the lost function. how communities work. Evolutionary biologists have In many cases, these mutations were correctly identified been less skeptical, and at least three major schools and for very simple genomes, at least, a nearly complete have adopted microcosm methods. Perhaps the best understanding of adaptation seems to be within grasp. known is the extensive exploration of the effects of artificial selection in Drosophila (and to a lesser extent in At the same time, both Ferenci and Bull and Molineux other organisms, such as mice).
    [Show full text]
  • Reconciling Explanations for the Evolution of Evolvability
    Reconciling Explanations for the Evolution of Evolvability Bryan Wilder and Kenneth O. Stanley To Appear In: Adaptive Behavior journal. London: SAGE, 2015. Abstract Evolution's ability to find innovative phenotypes is an important ingredient in the emergence of complexity in nature. A key factor in this capability is evolvability, or the propensity towards phenotypic variation. Numerous explanations for the origins of evolvability have been proposed, often differing in the role that they attribute to adaptive processes. To provide a new perspective on these explanations, experiments in this paper simulate evolution in gene regulatory networks, revealing that the type of evolvability in question significantly impacts the dynamics that follow. In particular, while adaptive processes result in evolvable individuals, processes that are either neutral or that explicitly encourage divergence result in evolvable populations. Furthermore, evolvability at the population level proves the most critical factor in the production of evolutionary innovations, suggesting that nonadaptive mechanisms are the most promising avenue for investigating and understanding evolvability. These results reconcile a large body of work across biology and inform attempts to reproduce evolvability in artificial settings. Keywords: Evolvability, evolutionary computation, gene regulatory networks Introduction Something about the structure of biological systems allows evolution to find new innovations. An important question is whether such evolvability (defined roughly as the propensity to introduce novel 1 phenotypic variation) is itself a product of selection. In essence, is evolvability evolvable (Pigliucci, 2008)? Much prior work has attempted to encourage evolvability in artificial systems in the hope of reproducing the open-ended dynamics of biological evolution (Reisinger & Miikkulainen, 2006; Grefenstette, 1999; Bedau et al., 2000; Channon, 2006; Spector, Klein, & Feinstein, 2007; Standish, 2003).
    [Show full text]
  • Evolutionary Developmental Biology 573
    EVOC20 29/08/2003 11:15 AM Page 572 Evolutionary 20 Developmental Biology volutionary developmental biology, now often known Eas “evo-devo,” is the study of the relation between evolution and development. The relation between evolution and development has been the subject of research for many years, and the chapter begins by looking at some classic ideas. However, the subject has been transformed in recent years as the genes that control development have begun to be identified. This chapter looks at how changes in these developmental genes, such as changes in their spatial or temporal expression in the embryo, are associated with changes in adult morphology. The origin of a set of genes controlling development may have opened up new and more flexible ways in which evolution could occur: life may have become more “evolvable.” EVOC20 29/08/2003 11:15 AM Page 573 CHAPTER 20 / Evolutionary Developmental Biology 573 20.1 Changes in development, and the genes controlling development, underlie morphological evolution Morphological structures, such as heads, legs, and tails, are produced in each individual organism by development. The organism begins life as a single cell. The organism grows by cell division, and the various cell types (bone cells, skin cells, and so on) are produced by differentiation within dividing cell lines. When one species evolves into Morphological evolution is driven another, with a changed morphological form, the developmental process must have by developmental evolution changed too. If the descendant species has longer legs, it is because the developmental process that produces legs has been accelerated, or extended over time.
    [Show full text]
  • Cell Biology, Molecular Embryology, Lamarckian and Darwinian Selection As Evolvability
    Evolvability of multicellular systems 7 Cell biology, molecular embryology, Lamarckian and Darwinian selection as evolvability H. Hoenigsberg Instituto de Genética Evolutiva y Biologia Molecular, Universidad Manuela Beltrán, Bogotá, DC, Colombia Corresponding author: H. Hoenigsberg E-mail: [email protected] Genet. Mol. Res. 2 (1): 7-28 (2003) Received July 31, 2002 Published February 6, 2003 ABSTRACT. The evolvability of vertebrate systems involves various mechanisms that eventually generate cooperative and nonlethal functional variation on which Darwinian selection can operate. It is a truism that to get vertebrate animals to develop a coherent machine they first had to inherit the right multicellular ontogeny. The ontogeny of a metazoan involves cell lineages that progressively deny their own capacity for increase and for totipotency in benefit of the collective interest of the individual. To achieve such cell altruism Darwinian dynamics rescinded its original unicellular mandate to reproduce. The distinction between heritability at the level of the cell lineage and at the level of the individual is crucial. However, its implications have seldom been explored in depth. While all out reproduction is the Darwinian measure of success among unicellular organisms, a high replication rate of cell lineages within the organism may be deleterious to the individual as a functional unit. If a harmoniously functioning unit is to evolve, mechanisms must have evolved whereby variants that increase their own replication rate by failing to accept their own somatic duties are controlled. For questions involving organelle origins, see Godelle and Reboud, 1995 and Hoekstra, 1990. In other words, modifiers of conflict that control cell lineages with conflicting genes and new mutant replication rates that deviate from their somatic duties had to evolve.
    [Show full text]
  • Just How Lamarckian Is CRISPR-Cas Immunity: the Continuum of Evolvability Mechanisms Eugene V
    Koonin and Wolf Biology Direct (2016) 11:9 DOI 10.1186/s13062-016-0111-z OPINION Open Access Just how Lamarckian is CRISPR-Cas immunity: the continuum of evolvability mechanisms Eugene V. Koonin* and Yuri I. Wolf Abstract The CRISPR-Cas system of prokaryotic adaptive immunity displays features of a mechanism for directional, Lamarckian evolution. Indeed, this system modifies a specific locus in a bacterial or archaeal genome by inserting a piece of foreign DNA into a CRISPR array which results in acquired, heritable resistance to the cognate selfish element. A key element of the Lamarckian scheme is the specificity and directionality of the mutational process whereby an environmental cue causes only mutations that provide specific adaptations to the original challenge. In the case of adaptive immunity, the specificity of mutations is equivalent to self-nonself discrimination. Recent studies on the CRISPR mechanism have shown that the levels of discrimination can substantially differ such that in some CRISPR-Cas variants incorporation of DNA is random whereas discrimination occurs by selection of cells that carry cognate inserts. In other systems, a higher level of specificity appears to be achieved via specialized mechanisms. These findings emphasize the continuity between random and directed mutations and the critical importance of evolved mechanisms that govern the mutational process. Reviewers: This article has been reviewed by Yitzhak Pilpel, Martijn Huynen, and Bojan Zagrovic. Keywords: CRISPR-Cas, Self-nonself discrimination, Lamarckian evolution, Darwinian evolution, DNA repair Background For several decades in the 20th century, IAC has fallen out Inheritance of Acquired adaptive Characters (IAC) has of fashion in mainstream biology, and worse, has been been a subject of thorny, circuitous debates among bi- central to several pseudo-scientific fads the foremost of ologists over the last two centuries [1].
    [Show full text]
  • Long-Term Experimental Evolution in Escherichia Coli. V. Effects of Recombination with Immigrant Genotypes on the Rate of Bacterial Evolution
    © Birkhliuser Verlag, Basel, 1997 J. evol. bioi. 10 (1997) 743-769 1010-061X/97/050743-27 $ 1.50 + 0.20/0 I Journal of Evolutionary Biology Long-term experimental evolution in Escherichia coli. V. Effects of recombination with immigrant genotypes on the rate of bacterial evolution 1 2 3 V. Souza, P. E. Turner • and R. E. LenskF·* 1Centro de Ecologia, Universidad Nacional Aut6noma de Mexico, Coyoacim, Ciudad de Mexico, 04510, Mexico 2 Center for Microbial Ecology, Michigan State University, East Lansing MI 48824, USA 3 Current address: Department of Zoology, University of Maryland, College Park MD 20742, USA Key words: Complex selection; conjugation; Escherichia coli; experimental evolu­ tion; hitchhiking; migration; plasmids; recombination. Abstract This study builds upon an earlier experiment that examined the dynamics of mean fitness in evolving populations of Escherichia coli in which mutations were the sole source of genetic variation. During thousands of generations in a constant environment, the rate of improvement in mean fitness of these asexual populations slowed considerably from an initially rapid pace. In this study, we sought to determine whether sexual recombination with novel genotypes would reaccelerate the rate of adaption in these populations. To that end, treatment populations were propagated for an additional 1000 generations in the same environment as their ancestors, but they were periodically allowed to mate with an immigrant pool of genetically distinct Hfr (high frequency recombination) donors. These donors could transfer genes to the resident populations by conjugation, but the donors them­ selves could not grow in the experimental environment. Control populations were propagated under identical conditions, but in the absence of sexual recombination with the donors.
    [Show full text]
  • Robustness, Evolvability, and the Logic of Genetic Regulation
    Robustness, Evolvability, and the Joshua L. Payne*,** Logic of Genetic Regulation University of Zurich Jason H. Moore† Dartmouth College ‡ Andreas Wagner University of Zurich The Santa Fe Institute Abstract In gene regulatory circuits, the expression of individual genes is commonly modulated by a set of regulating gene products, which bind to a geneʼs cis-regulatory region. This region encodes an input-output function, referred to as signal-integration logic, that maps a specific combination of regulatory signals (inputs) to a particular expression state (output) of a gene. The space of all possible signal- Keywords integration functions is vast and the mapping from input to output Evolutionary innovation, random Boolean is many-to-one: For the same set of inputs, many functions (genotypes) circuit, genetic regulation, genotype yield the same expression output (phenotype). Here, we exhaustively networks, genotype-phenotype map enumerate the set of signal-integration functions that yield identical gene expression patterns within a computational model of gene regulatory circuits. Our goal is to characterize the relationship between robustness and evolvability in the signal-integration space of regulatory circuits, and to understand how these properties vary between the genotypic and phenotypic scales. Among other results, we find that the distributions of genotypic robustness are skewed, so that the majority of signal- integration functions are robust to perturbation. We show that the connected set of genotypes that make up a given phenotype are constrained to specific regions of the space of all possible signal- integration functions, but that as the distance between genotypes increases, so does their capacity for unique innovations.
    [Show full text]