The Blue and Brown Books: Preliminary Studies for the Philosophical Investigations Pdf

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Blue and Brown Books: Preliminary Studies for the Philosophical Investigations Pdf FREE THE BLUE AND BROWN BOOKS: PRELIMINARY STUDIES FOR THE PHILOSOPHICAL INVESTIGATIONS PDF Ludwig Wittgenstein,Peter Docherty | 208 pages | 18 Dec 2002 | John Wiley and Sons Ltd | 9780631146605 | English | Oxford, United Kingdom [PDF] Blue and Brown Books: Preliminary Studies for the Philosophical Investigations - download now See more about this book on Archive. This edition doesn't have a description yet. Can you add one? Previews available in: English. Add another edition? Learn about the virtual Library Leaders Forum happening this month. Preliminary studies for the "Philosophical investigations" Ludwig Wittgenstein. Want to Read. Download for print-disabled. Check nearby libraries WorldCat. Buy this book Better World Books. Share this book Facebook. Last edited by Clean Up Bot. July 27, History. An edition of Preliminary studies for the "Philosophical investigations" This edition published in by Harper in New York. Written in English — pages. Preliminary studies for the 'Philosophical investigations': generally known as the Blue and Brown books. Not in Library. Preliminary studies for the 'Philosophical The Blue and Brown Books: Preliminary Studies for the Philosophical Investigations generally known as the Blue and Brown booksBlackwell. Borrow Listen. Preliminary studies for the "Philosophical investigations". Preliminary studies for the "Philosophical investigations,": generally known as the Blue and Brown books. Preliminary studies for the "Philosophical investigations"Harper. Checked Out. Preliminary studies for the "Philosophical investigations": generally known as the Blue The Blue and Brown Books: Preliminary Studies for the Philosophical Investigations Brown books. Preliminary studies for the Philosophical investigations: generally known as the Blue and Brown booksBlackwell. Preliminary studies for the "Philosophical investigations": generally known as the Blue and brown booksHarper and Row. Preliminary studies for the "Philosophical investigations": generally known as the Blue and brown books. Preliminary studies for the "Philosophical investigations" generally known as the Blue and Brown books. Classifications Library of Congress B W P6 a. Loading Related Books. July 27, Edited by Clean Up Bot. March 27, Edited by ImportBot. February 13, December 13, December 9, Created by WorkBot. Preliminary studies for the "Philosophical investigations" ( edition) | Open Library Sign up for LibraryThing to find out whether you'll like this book. Covers language and philosophy of mind well. The Blue and Brown Books: Preliminary Studies for the Philosophical Investigations to reread P. HadriantheBlind Mar 30, Works with interesting concepts, and demolishes some very silly thinking about philosophy of language that people bring intuitively to the subject. On the other hand, he's a bit more than supportably behaviorist, and with annoying frequency he confuses something he can't find out with something Unknowable By Definition, ignoring that science has indeed taken what were once philosophical problems and turned them into experimentally answerable questions--cog sci, quantum physics and relativity being especially good on that front. That said, it's a great intro to Wittgenstein, and you The Blue and Brown Books: Preliminary Studies for the Philosophical Investigations to remember that there actually were people who thought the way that his seeming strawmen did. The book is essentialy a compliation of notes taken by his students based on his lectures. If you're thinking about purchasing this book, you should definitely be prepared for a weighty read, but not as intense as other works written by, or attributed to, Wittgenstein. Blue and Brown Books. Philosophy of mind. Home Groups Talk More Zeitgeist. I Agree This site uses cookies to deliver our services, improve performance, for analytics, and if not signed in for advertising. Your use of the site and services is subject to these policies and terms. Members Reviews Popularity Average rating Mentions 1, 3 12, 4. The 'Blue Book' is a set of notes dictated to Witgenstein's Cambridge students in the 'Brown Book' was a draft for what eventually became the growth of the first part of Philosophical Investigations. This book reveals the The Blue and Brown Books: Preliminary Studies for the Philosophical Investigations and growth of the ideas which found their final expression in Witgenstein's later work. It is indispensable therefore to students of Witgenstein's thought and to all those who wish to study at first-hand the mental processes of a thinker who fundamentally changed the course of modern philosophy. No current Talk conversations about this book. I suppose I should have read this before Philosophical Investigations, but this is still a worthy text on its own, and helps clarify some of the finer points of his intricate and complex ideas. HadriantheBlind Mar 30, Works with interesting concepts, and demolishes some very silly thinking about philosophy of language that people bring intuitively to the subject. Definitely worthwhile if you're preparing to undertake a study of Wittgenstein. Status Wittgenstein, Ludwig — primary author all editions confirmed Anscombe, G. Translator secondary author some editions confirmed Nyman, Heikki Translator secondary author some editions confirmed Rhees, Rush Foreword secondary author some editions confirmed. Belongs to Publisher Series Einaudi Paperbacks O livro castanho by Ludwig Wittgenstein. Philosophical Investigations by Ludwig Wittgenstein. You must log in to edit Common Knowledge data. International Sociological Association: most influential books in Sociology This is closely analogous to saying that we can never know when in Fizeau's experiment the ray of light reaches the mirror. References to this work on external resources. These works, as the sub-title makes clear, are unfinished sketches for Philosophical Investigations, possibly the most important and influential philosophical work of modern times. No library descriptions found. Book description. Haiku summary. Add to Your books. Add to wishlist. Quick Links Amazon. Amazon Kindle 0 editions. Audible 0 editions. CD Audiobook 0 editions. Project Gutenberg 0 editions. Google Books — Loading Local Book Search. Swap 25 want. Rating Average: 4. Is this you? Become a LibraryThing Author. Recently added by. Legacy Libraries. For more help see the Common Knowledge help page. Original publication date. The Blue and Brown Books: Preliminary Studies for the Philosophical Investigations to show. Warning: May contain spoilers. Add to Your books Add to wishlist Quick Links. Blue and Brown Books - Wikipedia The Blue and Brown Books are two sets of notes taken during lectures conducted by Ludwig Wittgenstein from to They were mimeographed as two separated books, and a few copies were circulated in a restricted circle during Wittgenstein's lifetime. Rush Rhees published these together for the first time in as Preliminary Studies for the "Philosophical Investigations". Inchoate versions of many of the ideas that would later be more fully explored in the Philosophical Investigations are found there, so these offer textual evidence for the genesis of what became known as Wittgenstein's later philosophy. The Blue Book was dictated from toand contains certain themes unaddressed in Wittgenstein's later works, including deliberations on thinking as operating with signs. An early conception of what would later become known as language-games is present in the text, which represents the first period of Wittgenstein's thought aftera method of linguistic analysis which would later become ordinary language philosophy. While Wittgenstein in The Blue Book is not dogmatic nor systematic, he does provide arguments that point toward a more self-critical view of language. For example, he does not think that "understanding" and "explaining" are necessarily related. He suggests that when humans are learning a language-game they are actually being trained to understand it. He writes: "If we are taught the meaning of the word 'yellow' by being given some sort of ostensive definition [in this case, ostensive means something like "denoting a way of defining by direct demonstration, e. This drill causes us to associate a yellow image, yellow things, with the word 'yellow. The drill of teaching could in this case be said to have built up a psychical mechanism. This, however, would only be a hypothesis or else a metaphor. We could compare teaching with installing an electric connection between a switch and a bulb. The parallel to the connection going wrong or breaking down would then be what we call forgetting the explanation, or the meaning, of the word It is conceivable, in this sense, that all the processes The Blue and Brown Books: Preliminary Studies for the Philosophical Investigations understanding, obeying, etc. Having said that, Wittgenstein is not one to believe that even understanding a language-game can be reduced to one process; like the plethora of language-games available to human beings, there are also plethora of "understandings. Moreover, Wittgenstein doesn't think that humans use language mechanically, as if following a calculus. He writes in The Blue Book"[I]n general we don't use language according to strict rules--it hasn't been taught us by means of strict The Blue and Brown Books: Preliminary Studies for the Philosophical Investigations, either. Isn't it possible that the listener would associate "pencil" with "wood"? Maybe the listener would associate the word "pencil" with "round" instead
Recommended publications
  • David Suchoff Family Resemblances: Ludwig Wittgenstein As a Jewish Philosopher the Admonition to Silence with Which Wittgenstein
    David Suchoff Family Resemblances: Ludwig Wittgenstein as a Jewish Philosopher The admonition to silence with which Wittgenstein ended the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (1922) also marks the starting point for the emer- gence of his Jewish philosophical voice. Karl Kraus provides an instructive contrast: as a writer well known to Wittgenstein, Kraus’s outspoken and aggressive ridicule of “jüdeln” or “mauscheln” –the actual or alleged pronunciation of German with a Jewish or Yiddish accent – defined a “self-fashioning” of Jewish identity – from German and Hebrew in this case – that modeled false alternatives in philosophic terms.1 Kraus pre- sented Wittgenstein with an either-or choice between German and Jewish identity, while engaging in a witty but also unwitting illumination of the interplay between apparently exclusive alternatives that were linguistically influenced by the other’s voice. As Kraus became a touchstone for Ger- man Jewish writers from Franz Kafka to Walter Benjamin and Gershom Scholem, he also shed light on the situation that allowed Wittgenstein to develop his own non-essentialist notion of identity, as the term “family resemblance” emerged from his revaluation of the discourse around Judaism. This transition from The False Prison, as David Pears calls Wittgenstein’s move from the Tractatus to the Philosophical Investiga- tions, was also a transformation of the opposition between German and Jewish “identities,” and a recovery of the multiple differences from which such apparently stable entities continually draw in their interconnected forms of life.2 “I’ll teach you differences,” the line from King Lear that Wittgenstein mentioned to M. O’C. Drury as “not bad” as a “motto” for the Philo- sophical Investigations, in this way represents Wittgenstein’s assertion of a German Jewish philosophic position.
    [Show full text]
  • 'Solved by Sacrifice' : Austin Farrer, Fideism, and The
    ‘SOLVED BY SACRIFICE’ : AUSTIN FARRER, FIDEISM, AND THE EVIDENCE OF FAITH Robert Carroll MacSwain A Thesis Submitted for the Degree of PhD at the University of St. Andrews 2010 Full metadata for this item is available in the St Andrews Digital Research Repository at: https://research-repository.st-andrews.ac.uk/ Please use this identifier to cite or link to this item: http://hdl.handle.net/10023/920 This item is protected by original copyright ‘SOLVED BY SACRIFICE’: Austin Farrer, Fideism, and the Evidence of Faith Robert Carroll MacSwain A thesis submitted to the School of Divinity of the University of St Andrews in candidacy for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy The saints confute the logicians, but they do not confute them by logic but by sanctity. They do not prove the real connection between the religious symbols and the everyday realities by logical demonstration, but by life. Solvitur ambulando, said someone about Zeno’s paradox, which proves the impossibility of physical motion. It is solved by walking. Solvitur immolando, says the saint, about the paradox of the logicians. It is solved by sacrifice. —Austin Farrer v ABSTRACT 1. A perennial (if controversial) concern in both theology and philosophy of religion is whether religious belief is ‘reasonable’. Austin Farrer (1904-1968) is widely thought to affirm a positive answer to this concern. Chapter One surveys three interpretations of Farrer on ‘the believer’s reasons’ and thus sets the stage for our investigation into the development of his religious epistemology. 2. The disputed question of whether Farrer became ‘a sort of fideist’ is complicated by the many definitions of fideism.
    [Show full text]
  • Wittgenstein's Invitation to Philosophy
    Nordic Wittgenstein Review 4 (No 2) 2015 Beth Savickey b.savickey @ uwinnipeg.ca “Let us imagine...”: Wittgenstein’s Invitation to Philosophy Abstract Wendy Lee-Lampshire writes that Wittgenstein’s conception of language has something valuable to offer feminist attempts to construct epistemologies firmly rooted in the social, psychological and physical situations of language users (1999: 409). However, she also argues that his own use of language exemplifies a form of life whose constitutive relationships are enmeshed in forms of power and authority. For example, she interprets the language game of the builders as one of slavery, and questions how we read and respond to it. She asks: “Who are ‘we’ as Wittgenstein’s reader(s)?” This is an important question, and how we answer offers insight not only into our own philosophical practices, but also into Wittgenstein’s use of language games. With the words “Let us imagine...”, Wittgenstein invites readers to participate in creative, collaborative, and improvisational language games that alter not only the texts themselves, but our relationship with others. 1. Introduction In the opening of the Investigations, Wittgenstein introduces the language game of the builders (in response to Augustine’s description of the learning of human language): Let us imagine a language for which the description given by Augustine is right. The language is meant to serve for communication between a builder A and an assistant B. A is building with building stones: there are blocks, pillars, slabs, and beams. B has to pass the 99 Beth Savickey CC-BY stones, and that in the order in which A needs them.
    [Show full text]
  • Wittgenstein, Anxiety, and Performance Behavior
    Incapacity Incapacity Wittgenstein, Anxiety, and Performance Behavior Spencer Golub northwestern university press evanston, illinois Northwestern University Press www.nupress.northwestern.edu Copyright © 2014 by Spencer Golub. Published 2014 by Northwestern University Press. All rights reserved. Printed in the United States of America 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Golub, Spencer, author. Incapacity : Wittgenstein, anxiety, and performance behavior / Spencer Golub. pages cm Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 978-0-8101-2992-4 (cloth : alk. paper) 1. Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 1889–1951. 2. Language and languages—Philosophy. 3. Performance—Philosophy. 4. Literature, Modern—20th century—History and criticism. 5. Literature—Philosophy. I. Title. B3376.W564G655 2014 121.68—dc23 2014011601 Except where otherwise noted, this book is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License. To view a copy of this license, visit http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/. In all cases attribution should include the following information: Golub, Spencer. Incapacity: Wittgenstein, Anxiety, and Performance Behavior. Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 2014. For permissions beyond the scope of this license, visit http://www.nupress .northwestern.edu/. An electronic version of this book is freely available, thanks to the support of libraries working with Knowledge Unlatched. KU is a collaborative initiative designed to make high-quality books open access for the public good. More information about the initiative and links to the open-access version can be found at www.knowledgeunlatched.org. For my mother We go towards the thing we mean. —Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, §455 .
    [Show full text]
  • Middle Wittgenstein" : from Logical Atomism to Practical Holism*
    er7, 812Are DAVID STERN THE "MIDDLE WITTGENSTEIN" : FROM LOGICAL ATOMISM TO PRACTICAL HOLISM* 1 . THE "MIDDLE WITTGENSTEIN" Wittgenstein arranged the Tractatus in its final form during the summer of 1918 ; Part I of the Philosophical Investigations was put into the form in which we now have it during the mid 1940s . The Tractatus was published in 1922; the Philosophical Investigations in 1953, two years after Wittgenstein's death . Because the two books were widely studied and interpreted at a time when the rest of his writing was unavailable, it became common practice to speak of the author of the first book as "Early Wittgenstein", and the author of the second as the "Late Wittgenstein" . As it gradually became clear that his writing during the intervening years was not only voluminous, but also could not simply be understood as a rejection of one view and the adoption of another, it was natural to speak of the author of this further body of writing, or at least those parts of it which could not be regarded as "Early", or "Late", as "Middle Wittgenstein" . While it is certainly convenient to use this talk of an early, middle and late Wittgenstein as conversational shorthand for lengthier and more cautious ways of discussing the development of his philosophy, it also has its dangers. One of the main assumptions which commonly accompanies this periodisation is the belief that we'can neatly divide the development of Wittgenstein's thought into several sharply demarcated phases. While there is some truth to this, it is only a half-truth, and for this reason it is particularly dangerous .
    [Show full text]
  • Wittgenstein and Forms of Life* J
    Phil. Soc. Sci. 10 (1980) 241-258 EDlTORS i, J. O. Wisdom John O'Neill 1. C. Jarvie, Monuging Editor Wittgenstein and Forms of Life* J. N. Hattiangadi NICHOLAS F. GIER, Philosophy, University of Idaho !EDKTORIAL BOARD I David Bakan (Psychology. York). L. A. Boland (Economics. Simon \ Fraser), Frank Cunningham (Philosophy. Toronto), Kurt Danziger Ludwig Wittgenstein's concept of 'forms of life' (Lebensformen), though (Psychology. York). W. H. Dray (Philosophy. Ottawa). Robert H. ! mentioned only seven times in all of his published writings,t is, accord­ Haynes (Biology, York). Melvyn Hill (Social Science, York), Harold ing to leading Wittgenstein scholars, the most significant concept in the Kaplan (Political Science, York). J. J. Leach (Philosophy. Western), later philosophy. 1 Wittgenstein maintains that many traditional T. H. Leith (Natural Science. York), Gordon Lowther (Anthropology. I York), J. W. Mohr (Law, Osgoode), Christopher Nichols (Sociology, f * Received 2.1.79 YorkL P. H. Nowell-Smith (Philosophy. York), L. R. Rubinoff t ABBREVIATIONS: I BB = The Blue and Brown Books, ed. by R. Rhees (Harper Torchbooks, 1969). (Philosophy, Trent). H. T. Wilson (Administrative Studies, York), Neil LC = Lectures and Covnersations, ed. C. Barrett (University of California, 1966). Wood (Political Science, York), J. W. Yolton (Philosophy. Rutgers). NB = Notebooks 1914-1916, trans. G. E. M. Anscombe (HarperTorchbooks, 1961). j OC = On Certainty, trans·. Anscombe and von Wright (Harper Torchbooks, 1969). PHILOSOPHY OF THE SOCIAL SCIENCES is an international quar­ OCo = On Colour, trans. McAlister & Schiittle (Blackwell, 1977). terly which publishes articles, discussions. symposia, literature sur­ ~ PG = Philosophical Grammar, trans. Anthony Kenny (Blackwell, 1974). PI = Philosophical Investigations, trans.
    [Show full text]
  • Wittgenstein, Lewis Carroll and the Philosophical Puzzlement of Language
    33 Wittgenstein, Lewis Carroll And The philosophical Puzzlement of Language AmyL. Kind Amherst College Alice felt dreadfully puzzled. The Hatter's remark seemed to her no sort of meaning in it, and yet it was certainly English. "I don't quite understand you," she said, as politely as she could. (l&, 61) When Lewis Carroll sends Alice down the rabbit hole in his fairy-tale masterpiece, Alice's Adventures in Wonderland, he plunges her into a world of puzzlement. The characters speak English, and it is grammatically correct (even elegant) English, but Alice is nonetheless continually baffled by their use of language. In his PhilosQphical Inv!(;!tigations, Ludwig Wittgenstein discusses this type of puzzlement, describing philosophy as "a battle against the bewitchment of intelligence by means of language" CEl #109). In fact, Wittgenstein spends a large part of the Investigations attempting to show how philosophy must deal with the problems inherent in our use of language. But while Wittgenstein is concerned with finding an escape from the puzzlement, Carroll submerges himself furlher in the morass. In his fairy-tale masterpieces, Carroll uses and misuses language to achieve humor and charm; his heroine, in both Wonderland and ThrQugh !.he Looking Glass, continually meets with the very sources of philosophical puzzlement which Wittgenstein fears. The methods differ, but both Wittgenstein and Carroll admonish their readers to pay attention to language, pointing out the fallacy in assuming that we can understand a sentence simply because it
    [Show full text]
  • 7. Roland Barthes, a Lover's Discourse, Fragments (I 977; Harmondsworth: Pen• Guin, 1990}
    Notes Introduction Notes 1. Ron Silliman, "Language, Poetry, Realism," In the American Tree (Orono, ME: National Poetry Foundation, 1984), xix. 2. Silliman, "Language, Poetry, Realism," xvii. 3. Silliman, "Language, Poetry, Realism," xvi. 4. David Antin, "Modernism and Postmodernism: Approaching the Present in American Poetry," Boundary 2 1 (Fall1972}: 98-133. 5. See Plato, Symposium 184e-206a, trans. Benjamin Jowett, The Dialogues of Plato, 2nd ed., vol. 2 (Oxford: Clarendon, 1875), from which Zukofsky has lifted phrases and quotations to compose the bulk of the poem. For notes 5 and 6, I am grateful to Ian Tompkins of the University of Wales, Aberyst­ wyth, for his aid with finding these sources and his translation of the Greek. 6. For example, see Plato, Timaeus, trans. and ed. Rev. R G. Bury, Loeb Classical library (1929; London: Heinemann, 1966), 23b, 75e, 89d, or Plato, Laws, trans. and ed. Rev. R G. Bury, Loeb Classical library (London: Heinemann, 1952}, 716d, 870b, where the brightest and the best as a form of good is fre­ quently a phrase used by Athenians as a way of distinguishing themselves. 7. Roland Barthes, A Lover's Discourse, Fragments (I 977; Harmondsworth: Pen­ guin, 1990}. 8. Suzanne Clark has explored this sentimental discourse in relation to women's poetic modernism in Sentimental Modernism (Bloomington: University of Indiana Press, 1991}, in which she points out the way in which a "mascu­ line" modernism sought to repress the sentimental as a feminized discourse. She points to Ann Douglas' book, The Feminization ofAmerican Culture, as one example of the case against the sentimental in favor of a tough, Puritan critical reason.
    [Show full text]
  • How Did Hertz Influence Wittgenstein' S Philosophical Development?
    HOW DID HERTZ INFLUENCE WITTGENSTEIN' S PHILOSOPHICAL DEVELOPMENT? Allan JANIK Brenner Archivellnnsbruck University I don't believe that I have ever invented a way of thinking. I have always taken one over from someone else. I have simply straightaway seized upon it with enthusiasm for my work of clarification ... Boltzmann, Hertz, Schopenhauer, Frege, Russell, Kraus, Loos, Weininger, Spengler, Sraffa have in­ fluenced me. Wittgenstein, Cu/ture and Va/ue. 1ge It was an awful thought to go and sit there among logical positivists ... Wittgenstein to Rush Rhees, 13.VII.38 From the very beginning the seemingly unscientific, virtually anti­ scientific, "everyday", character of Wittgenstein's mature concep­ tion of philosophy struck many of his contemporaries as either absurdly trivial or perversely false. Thus Bertrand Russell could accuse Wittgenstein of becoming lazy no longer possessing the intellectual rigor that real philosophizing demands, and of making a doctrine out of his laziness I , whereas Ernest Gellner railed against "the authoritarian, capricious, messianic and elusive characteristics ofWittenstein's practice" and its odious influence upon a generation of philosophers transformed into sophists.2 The ideas that, description should replace explanation, it is not 1. Bertrand RusselI, My Philosophical Development (London: Allen & Un­ win, 1959), 261f. 2. Emest Gellner, Words and Things (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1959),264-5. 20 possible to advance theses in philosophy, that c1arity is a matter of understanding language, rather than rigorous logical analysis, and, that philosophy leaves everything as it is, implied for many philo­ sophers and others as well that the later Wittgenstein had rejected the critical values of the Enlightenment associated with his early logical positivism for an irrationalist obscurantism.
    [Show full text]
  • Wittgenstein's Method in §§109-133 of the Philosophical Investigations. A
    Wittgenstein's Method in §§109-133 of the Philosophical Investigations. A thesis presented to the faculty of the College of Arts and Sciences of Ohio University In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree Master of Arts David T. Schwan June 2009 © 2009 David T. Schwan. All Rights Reserved. 2 This thesis titled Wittgenstein's Method in §§109-133 of the Philosophical Investigations. by DAVID T. SCHWAN has been approved for the Department of Philosophy and the College of Arts and Sciences by Arthur Zucker Associate Professor of Philosophy Benjamin M. Ogles Dean, College of Arts and Sciences 3 Abstract SCHWAN, DAVID T., M.A., June 2009, Philosophy Wittgenstein's Method in §§109-133 of the Philosophical Investigations (61 pp.) Director of Thesis: Arthur Zucker Wittgenstein directly addresses the nature of philosophy (and philosophical problems) both in the Investigations and in much of his writing and conversation outside that text. I will argue for an interpretation of Wittgenstein’s philosophical method in the Philosophical Investigations based on 1) his conversations and lectures during his years at Cambridge, 2) his views expressed in the Blue Book and 3) his views expressed in the Big Typescript. My goal is to ‘take Wittgenstein at his word’ and examine his comments on philosophy in many different contexts. Given the cohesive nature of Wittgenstein’s views on philosophy in the 1930’s, I will argue that §§109-133 in the Philosophical Investigations represents the coherent method that Wittgenstein employed throughout his ‘later’ years. Approved: _____________________________________________________________ Arthur Zucker Associate Professor of Philosophy 4 Acknowledgments I want to thank Dr.
    [Show full text]
  • Nineteen Fifty-Eight: Information Technology and the Reconceptualisation
    Downloaded from Nineteen Fifty-Eight: Information Technology and the Reconceptualisation of Creativity http://camqtly.oxfordjournals.org/ Christopher Mole NINETEEN FIFTY-EIGHT WAS AN EXTRAORDINARY YEAR for innovations in the arts and in the sciences. This essay examines the ways in which those innovations were driven by developments in the formal theory of infor- at University Of British Columbia Library on December 2, 2011 mation. The developments in information theory facilitated the rapid growth of computational technologies. They also provided new foun- dations, and new explanatory ideals, for linguistics, for psychology, and for the human sciences more generally. They thereby put pressure on estab- lished conceptions of human creativity and culture. In the natural sciences and in mathematics there were logical results (from the philosophy of science and from metamathematics) that enabled this pressure to be used in generating a positive new conception of the way in which mathematical and scientific enterprises require an essentially cultural form of human creativity. The literary arts had no analogous results with which to operate. The pressure on established conceptions of human creativity was therefore felt by authors and critics in the form of an urgent anxiety which, as the concluding sections of this essay show, can be seen manifest- ing itself in the novels, plays, and critical disputes of the period. The links between formal theories of information and the conception of creativity are at their closest in the science of linguistics. It is there that the innovations of 1958 begin. I Noam Chomsky’s 1959 review of B. F. Skinner’s 1957 book Verbal Behavior would not have dealt such a devastating blow to Skinner’s behaviourist doi:10.1093/camqtly/bfr030 # The Author, 2011.
    [Show full text]
  • Ejournals @ Oklahoma State University Library
    CONTESTING WITTGENSTEIN”S REMARKS ON ARCHITECTURE JOCHEN SCHUFF As the general concern of this journal issue is the relevance of Wittgenstein’s thinking for the philosophy of architecture, I will take the task quite literally. Accordingly, the aim of my paper is to explore whether there is evidence for systematic ideas about architecture in Wittgenstein. Reading Culture and Value, it may well seem as if architecture All things ranked among the subjects Wittgenstein did think “considered, about—at least from time to time. I will provide there is not some context concerning the status of these remarks—as well as that of some others not much to included in Culture and Value—in Wittgenstein’s be found in work. All things considered, there is not much to be Wittgenstein’s found in Wittgenstein’s writing concerning the writing arts or aesthetics in general. There are, to be sure, concerning some editions of student’s notes of lectures on the subject of aesthetics [1], and numerous opinions the arts or reported in correspondences and biographies, aesthetics in but only a few remarks devoted to art both in the single book Wittgenstein published in his general. lifetime, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, and among the 20,000 pages of text he left in his Nachlass. Most ” of these remarks contain reflections about music, especially musical meaning and understanding. In relation, there is even less Wittgenstein specifically wrote on the subject of architecture. The fact may be striking, since Wittgenstein, while having temporarily abandoned philosophy, famously took part in designing and building the city mansion for his sister Margarethe Stonborough-Wittgenstein in Kundmanngasse, Vienna, between 1926 and 1928.
    [Show full text]