Time Lost and Time Regained: a Short Essay on the Eternity of God Dr

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Time Lost and Time Regained: a Short Essay on the Eternity of God Dr Journal of Religion and Theology Volume 1, Issue 1, 2017, PP 33-37 Time Lost and Time Regained: A Short Essay on the Eternity of God Dr. Charles Taliaferro Professor of Philosophy, Philosophy of Religion, St. Olaf College, USA. *Corresponding Author: Dr. Charles Taliaferro, Professor of Philosophy, Philosophy of Religion, St. Olaf College, USA. ABSTRACT In philosophy of religion and analytical theology there is a substantial debate about God’s relation to time. The traditional, Christian theistic stance, championed by Boethius, Augustine, Aquinas, and others, is that God is timelessly eternal. This is opposed by Nicholas Wolterstorff, Richard Swinburne, and some other major philosophers of religion. Wolterstorff’s objections to the traditional position were examined to bring to light how the critics of the belief that God is eternal fail to appreciate how the traditional stance is pitted against anthropomorphism. It affirmed the unique self-subsistence of God as Creator, and the goodness of temporality. Keywords: Anthropomorphism, eternity, God, Nicholas Wolterstorff, Richard Swinburne, temporality, time. And there are some who have no memorial, metaphysical thesis that there is no past, present, and future for God, but with overriding divine who have perished as though they had not lived; values. they have become as though they had not been born, In this brief essay I use the work of Nicholas Wolterstorff as a foil to bring to light how the and so have their children after them. traditional belief that God is eternal is employed, Sirach 44:9 historically, to underscore three important tenants: God is not to be thought of anthropomorphically; Well! And what if she should die some the life of God is unsurpassably full as the self- afternoon, subsisting Creator; and every moment of time is Afternoon grey and smoky, evening yellow and precious, in part, because of God‟s eternity. rose; TEMPORALITY, A LIFE WORTH LIVING, AND Should die and leave me sitting pen in hand CAUSATION With the smoke coming down above the Consider first the case against the view that God housetops…. is atemporally eternal. Wolterstorff‟s case against T. S. Eliot, Portrait of a Lady those who believe God to be temporal involves In analytical theology and philosophy of an appeal to human experience. religion the debate over God‟s relationship to What‟s characteristic of those of us who live in time is often suffused with highly technical time is that there are experiences we have had arguments involving the concepts of causation, that are over, “irretrievably over and done with.” modality, future free contingents, the theory of We cannot “live them again.” We may remember relativity, the tensed nature of knowledge, them with greater or lesser vividness. But as comparisons of the so-called dynamic and static experiences, they are “forever lost.” (Wolterstorff, theories of time, and so on. It is more rare that 69) philosophers and theologians attend to the root Although Wolterstorff does not explicitly rule values that are in play in the classical literature out the possibility of there being an eternal on God and time that we find in Boethius, person (or, in light of the doctrine of the Trinity, Augustine, Aquinas, and others. Such classical there being three divine persons that are thinkers were not concerned only with the Journal of Religion and Theology V1 ● I1 ● 2017 33 Time Lost and Time Regained: A Short Essay on the Eternity of God atemporally eternal), he focuses his analysis of “Wolterstorff‟s most important, direct challenge what it is to be like us. In our case, experiences to those who embrace God as eternal is that they must, by their very nature, become irretrievably seem to rob God of the capacity to enjoy lost as we live through time even if (perhaps per temporal goods”. impossibile) we never lose consciousness. “Now why would anyone imagine that unchanging “And if there be persons who need no sleep and experience, be it momentary or durational, is a for whom, accordingly, experiences can in more excellent form of life –or if you will, fuller- principle last a long time, it will still be the case, than that which I do experience? Consider how even for enduring experiences, that parts of little of what we actually experience could be them will be over and forever lost. So… gotten into a changeless state. Watching my intrinsic to the experience of a person in time is children grow up would be something I could that, at any moment in that person‟s life, many not experience, listening to a piece of music of her life‟s experiences have this quality of would be something I could not experience, irrevocable overness”. (Ibid., 69) walking through Hagia Sophia so as to see if Wolterstorff develops the following two thought from a variety of different angels would be experiment: if we imagine what it would be like something I could not experience, building a to be a person who did not experience the piece of furniture or designing a house would be overness of time, we wind up with bizarre something I could not experience, and so forth, results. In the first, we seem driven to absurdity; on and on. To me it seems just bizarre to the idea that one‟s experience would have to suppose that such a life would be more occur in a moment: excellent, more full. It seems, on the contrary, “What would be required for my life to be appallingly impoverished”. (Ibid., 73) lacking in any experience that has the quality of How should we assess these considerations irrevocable overnness? It would at least have to when it comes to the philosophy of God? be totally devoid of change. Would it have to be momentary? Strictly speaking, yes. For if it ETERNAL VALUES were not momentary, then a segment of it would The first point to note is that Wolterstorff‟s be over at a certain time”. (Ibid., 73) reasoning concerns what he takes to be the Although Wolterstorff does not press the issue, I “characteristic of those of us who live in time.” suggest that such a thought experiment would One may grant all his points; for us, thinking amount to a reduction to absurdity. No one can and acting are inconceivable without there being think in an instant. An instant as opposed to an temporal sequence. For us to have and raise event or an interval, has no temporal magnitude; children, build things, explore Hagia Sophia, it is akin to a point in space which may be said listening to music, and so on, requires sequential to have location but not spatial extension. activity in which events transpire and the In a second thought experiment, Wolterstorff present moment is (as it were) in motion and not conjures up the following case in which there is at all static or immutable (not subject to an irrevocable loss of the past, but this fact change). It is understandable that Wolterstorff, seems trivial and uninteresting. as a Christian philosopher, would use human “Suppose my experience is confined to that of life as a reference point for thinking about God seeing an unfaltering patch of vivid green. Yes, in light of the belief that human persons are after ten minutes of this the first ten minutes made in the image of God. But while one might would be over –irrevocably, irretrievably and all rightly think that God, like human beings, loves, of that. But since my experience would continue knows, creates, it is another matter to suppose to be more of exactly the same, surely there that the manner or mode of God‟s love, knowledge, would be no cause for lament in the fact that the and power is, like our own, temporal. The experience of the first ten minutes was forever classical, eternalist tradition does not in any way lost.” (Ibid., 73) claim that temporal changing and sequential So, Wolterstorff‟s reasoning here is that a activity is ipso facto defective. Such temporality changeless being that does not experience is (arguably) essential for there to be a created temporal loss is either an absurdity (thinking, a order of free, interdependent agents who are process that requires temporal passage, in an profoundly responsible for each other‟s welfare. instant) or not at all valuable. Boethius, Augustine, Aquinas, and others 34 Journal of Religion and Theology V1 ● I1 ● 2017 Time Lost and Time Regained: A Short Essay on the Eternity of God simultaneously affirm the goodness of a highlights, but to see them as more precious. contingent creation and recognize what they see Appreciating this may be done in three stages. as the perfection of God, which involves God First, consider Wolterstorff‟s raising children containing “all the plentitude of perfection of all and building things (and so on) under conditions being” --omnem plenitudinem perfcetionis where there is no God, the cosmos is totius esse (Aquinas, Summa Theologiae, I.9.1.) (eventually) annihilated and there is no memory On this view, God‟s greatness cannot be of those acts by anyone or anything. We might augmented or diminished. God is loving, even imagine that at a certain point in time there knowing, and is revealed in time, but this is would be no trace of any kind of there once timelessly willed by a God who is not subject to being purposive, living creatures. In this time. On this point, the classical view may be scenario we may well deem the good lives and appreciated as non-anthropomorphic, not acts to be truly valuable. Those who are modeling the conception of God based on Platonists might go so far as to contend that it human life (and its limitations).
Recommended publications
  • Summary the Purpose of the Dissertation Is to Present The
    Summary The purpose of the dissertation is to present the abductive argument of Richard Swinburne in favor of theism. Richard Swinburne was born on December 26, 1934. He is a British philosopher, a retired professor of the University of Oxford, where he held the position of Nolloth Professor of the Philosophy of the Christian Religion (Oriel College). He has devoted all his philosophical activity to the justification of the Christian faith – he has intended to show that it is rational to believe in God. The main thesis of the dissertation is that Swinburne’s concept of theism does not remain consistent with the assumption that God is perfectly good. This inconsistence comes from the fact that human experience of suffering cannot be reconciled with God’s perfect goodness, especially assuming that God allows or causes the suffering. The structure of the work corresponds to the logical construction of Swinburne’s line of reasoning. The first chapter – Methodology of Philosophy – describes the main philosophical methods Swinburne uses in presenting his arguments. It is divided into two parts: the first one (Theory of Explanation) primarily presents the Swinburne’s construction of the concept of coherence, which is a prerequisite for considering any theory as probable or true. Moreover, this part discusses Swinburne’s dual explanatory theory, according to which two types of explanation are possible: (1) scientific, based on the analysis of unintentional causation, and (2) personal, based on the analysis of intentional causation. At the same time, Swinburne tries to show that it is not possible to explain certain phenomena in the world only by means of scientific explanation.
    [Show full text]
  • Richard Swinburne's Arguments for Substance Dualism
    Richard Swinburne’s arguments for substance dualism. MA by Research in Theology and Religion David Horner September 2018 Richard Swinburne’s arguments for substance dualism. Submitted by David Horner to the University of Exeter as a dissertation for the degree of MA by Research in Theology and Religion in September 2018 This dissertation is available for Library use on the understanding that it is copyright material and that no quotation from the dissertation may be published without proper acknowledgement. I certify that all material in this dissertation which is not my own work has been identified and that no material has previously been submitted and approved for the award of a degree by this or any other University. 1 Acknowledgements. I would like to thank my supervisors, Dr Jonathan Hill and Dr Joel Krueger for their support and encouragement in the writing of this dissertation and for their patience in trying to keep me on the straight and narrow. I want to acknowledge the many conversations, on this and other topics, I have had with my friend and philosopher, Dr Chris Boyne, who sadly died in June of this year. I thank all my other chums at The Bull, Ditchling, for listening to my metaphysical ramblings. And finally, I thank my wife, Linda, for once more putting up with this kind of thing. 2 Abstract This dissertation is a contribution to debates in the philosophy of mind and of personal identity. It presents a critical account of arguments for substance dualism to be found in Richard Swinburne’s Mind, Brain, and Free Will (2013).
    [Show full text]
  • Literature Review
    New Insights and Directions for Religious Epistemology http://www.newinsights.ox.ac.uk Literature Review Analytic epistemology experienced a monumental resurgence in the latter part of the twentieth century. A short paper by Edmund Gettier launched a frenzied era of original research into the nature of some of our central epistemic concepts, e.g., knowledge, justification, rationality, belief, defeat, and evidence. The excitement of Gettier’s challenge to the view that knowledge is justified true belief drew interest from a wide range of very talented philosophers. Formidable figures such as Fred Dretske, John Pollack, Robert Nozick, Roderick Chisholm, Alvin Goldman, Marshall Swain, David Armstrong, Alvin Plantinga, William Alston, Richard Swinburne, and Gilbert Harman, to name just a few, published widely on the foregoing epistemic concepts. This outpouring of original research meant that new theoretical tools and insights became available for application in philosophy of religion. Religious epistemology, taking advantage of this resurgence in mainstream epistemology, experienced a new era of original research. William Alston, Nicholas Wolterstorff, Alvin Plantinga, and Richard Swinburne all played a particularly central role in this resurgence. Alston, in his popular book Perceiving God, argued that religious beliefs held by way of religious experience are just as justified as our regular or quotidian perceptual beliefs. In his masterpiece Warranted Christian Belief, Plantinga, inspired by (i) the notion of a basic belief in the epistemic theory of foundationalism, (ii) his proper functioning account of warrant, and (iii) John Calvin’s theology, defended the position that Christian beliefs are warranted if true. The broad outlines of his position came to be labeled “Reformed Epistemology.” Wolterstorff, in his Reason within the Bounds of Religion, provided an elegant and sophisticated account of the role religious belief play in an agent’s overall epistemic “web” of beliefs.
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae of Alvin Plantinga
    CURRICULUM VITAE OF ALVIN PLANTINGA A. Education Calvin College A.B. 1954 University of Michigan M.A. 1955 Yale University Ph.D. 1958 B. Academic Honors and Awards Fellowships Fellow, Center for Advanced Study in the Behavioral Sciences, 1968-69 Guggenheim Fellow, June 1 - December 31, 1971, April 4 - August 31, 1972 Fellow, American Academy of Arts & Sciences, 1975 - Fellow, Calvin Center for Christian Scholarship, 1979-1980 Visiting Fellow, Balliol College, Oxford 1975-76 National Endowment for the Humanities Fellowships, 1975-76, 1987, 1995-6 Fellowship, American Council of Learned Societies, 1980-81 Fellow, Frisian Academy, 1999 Gifford Lecturer, 1987, 2005 Honorary Degrees Glasgow University, l982 Calvin College (Distinguished Alumni Award), 1986 North Park College, 1994 Free University of Amsterdam, 1995 Brigham Young University, 1996 University of the West in Timisoara (Timisoara, Romania), 1998 Valparaiso University, 1999 2 Offices Vice-President, American Philosophical Association, Central Division, 1980-81 President, American Philosophical Association, Central Division, 1981-82 President, Society of Christian Philosophers, l983-86 Summer Institutes and Seminars Staff Member, Council for Philosophical Studies Summer Institute in Metaphysics, 1968 Staff member and director, Council for Philosophical Studies Summer Institute in Philosophy of Religion, 1973 Director, National Endowment for the Humanities Summer Seminar, 1974, 1975, 1978 Staff member and co-director (with William P. Alston) NEH Summer Institute in Philosophy of Religion (Bellingham, Washington) 1986 Instructor, Pew Younger Scholars Seminar, 1995, 1999 Co-director summer seminar on nature in belief, Calvin College, July, 2004 Other E. Harris Harbison Award for Distinguished Teaching (Danforth Foundation), 1968 Member, Council for Philosophical Studies, 1968-74 William Evans Visiting Fellow University of Otago (New Zealand) 1991 Mentor, Collegium, Fairfield University 1993 The James A.
    [Show full text]
  • The Existence of God
    The Existence of God Richard Swinburne Why believe that there is a God at all? My answer is that to suppose that there is a God explains why there is a physical universe at all; why there are the scientific laws there are; why animals and then human beings have evolved; why humans have the opportunity to mould their characters and those of their fellow humans for good or ill and to change the environment in which we live; why we have the well-authenticated account of Christ‟s life, death and resurrection; why throughout the centuries millions of people (other than ourselves) have had the apparent experience of being in touch with an guided by God, and so much else. In fact, the hypothesis of the existence of God makes sense of the whole of our experience, and it does so better than any other explanation that can be put forward, and that is the grounds for believing it to be true.In this lecture I shall try to show you how it makes sense of the first three of these phenomena.That phenomena evident to all, and in particular the universe and its order, provide good grounds for believing that God exists has been a general Christian, Jewish, and Islamic conviction.The production of arguments to show this is called „natural theology‟, and it might be useful to start with a few remarks about the place of natural theology in Christian tradition . The prophet Jeremiah wrote of the “covenant of night and day”,1 indicating that the regularity by which day succeeded night showed that the god in charge of the Universe was powerful and reliable, viz, that that god was God.
    [Show full text]
  • Handbook of the 1St World Congress on Logic and Religion
    2 Handbook of the 1st World Congress on Logic and Religion 3 HANDBOOK OF THE 1ST WORLD CONGRESS ON LOGIC AND RELIGION João Pessoa, Abril 1-5. 2015, Brazil EDITED BY RICARDO SOUSA SILVESTRE JEAN-YVES BÉZIAU 4 Handbook of the 1st World Congress on Logic and Religion 5 CONTENTS 1. The 1st World Congress on Logic and Religion 6 1.1. Aim of the 1st World Congress on Logic and Religion 6 1.2. Call for Papers 1 1.3. Organizers 9 1.3.1. Organizing Committee 9 1.3.2. Scientific Committee 9 1.4. Realization 11 1.5. Sponsors 11 2. Abstracts 12 2.1 Keynote Talks 12 2.2 Contributed Talks 31 3. Index of names 183 3.1. Keynote Speakers 183 3.2. Contributed Speakers 183 6 Handbook of the 1st World Congress on Logic and Religion 1. THE 1ST WORLD CONGRESS ON LOGIC AND RELIGION 1.1. Aim of the 1st World Congress on Logic and Religion Although logic, symbol of rationality, may appear as opposed to religion, both have a long history of cooperation. Philosophical theology, ranging from Anselm to Gödel, has provided many famous proofs for the existence of God. On the other side, many atheologians, such as Hume, for example, have developed powerful arguments meant to disproof God’s existence. These arguments have been scrutinized and developed in many interesting ways by twentieth century analytic philosophy of religion. Moreover, in the Bible the logos is assimilated to God, which has been reflected in western philosophy in different ways by philosophers such as Leibniz and Hegel.
    [Show full text]
  • Richard Swinburne, PROVIDENCE and the PROBLEM of EVIL
    Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers Volume 18 Issue 3 Article 12 7-1-2001 Richard Swinburne, PROVIDENCE AND THE PROBLEM OF EVIL Philip L. Quinn Follow this and additional works at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy Recommended Citation Quinn, Philip L. (2001) "Richard Swinburne, PROVIDENCE AND THE PROBLEM OF EVIL," Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers: Vol. 18 : Iss. 3 , Article 12. DOI: 10.5840/faithphil200118324 Available at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy/vol18/iss3/12 This Book Review is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers by an authorized editor of ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. 394 Faith and Philosophy But then, alas, there is Hell. Adams firmly relies on the hope that God can somehow bring it about that everyone shall enjoy bliss with him. She is an unrepentant believer in the salvation of all human beings and the Lmreal­ ity of Hell. And one might well wish to take one's hat off to her on that score. For the scenario she envisages is agreeable. How nice to think that all of us shall end with the joy of the beatific vision. But Adams gives us no serious reason to think that all of us shall do that. And she goes against New Testament and other Christian writings in supposing that everyone shall attain a state of contentment which leaves them reconciled to what has happened to them in this life and to what they have done in it.
    [Show full text]
  • Reidianism in Contemporary English-Speaking Religious Epistemology
    REIDIANISM IN CONTEMPORARY ENGLISH-SPEAKING RELIGIOUS EPISTEMOLOGY PETER BYRNE King’s College London Abstract. This paper explores the main contours of recent work in English- speaking philosophy of religion on the justification of religious belief. It sets out the main characteristics of the religious epistemologies of such writers as Alston, Plantinga, and Swinburne. It poses and seeks to answer the question of how far any or all of these epistemologies are indebted or similar to the epistemology of the Scottish Enlightenment thinker Thomas Reid. It concludes that while there are some links to Reid in recent writing, contemporary approaches depart from Reid’s views on the specific topic of the justification of religious belief. INTRODUCTION My aim in this paper is to present a survey of the contemporary debate as to ‘positive epistemic status’ and religious belief highlighting (as much as I can) the use of Reid and Scottish philosophy in contemporary philosophy of religion. There is a great deal that can be done by way of fulfilling this aim, since Reid is referred to frequently by important protagonists in contemporary English-speaking religious epistemology – though only Reid: I have come across no mention in this literature to other Scottish philosophers (except of course for David Hume). The most important figures in debates about the rationality and justification of religious belief in the last 20 years have been William Alston, Alvin Plantinga and Richard Swinburne. Nicholas Wolterstorff also deserves a mention here, but though he is not in any sense a follower of Plantinga, his work tends (unfairly) to be regarded as a supplement EUROPEAN JOURNAL FOR PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION 3/2 (AUTUMN 2011), PP.
    [Show full text]
  • Why God Allows Evil Richard Swinburne
    p. 105 Why God Allows Evil Richard Swinburne Richard Swinburne is the Nolloth Professor of Philosophy of the Christian Religion at the Univeristy of Oxford. He has done important work in metaphysics, epistemology and the philosophy of religion. From Richard Swinburne Is There a God? pp. 95-113 (Oxford Univeristy Press, 1996) 106 PART 1 • Reason and Religious Belief This world is a clearly providential world in this her own life and that of close relatives and friends sense-that we humans can have a great influence (which can so easily seem the only important on our own destiny, and on the destiny of our thing in the world), and ask very generally what world and its other inhabitants; and it is very good things would a generous and everlasting good for us that it is like that. And yet animals God give to human beings in the course of a and humans suffer (through natural processes of short earthly life. Of course thrills of pleasure disease and accident), and they cause each other and periods of contentment are good things, to suffer (we hurt and n1aim each other and and-other things being equal-God would cer­ cause each other to starve). The world, that is, tainly seek to provide plenty of those. But a gen­ contains much evil. An omnipotent God could erous God will seek to give deeper good things have prevented this evil, and surely a perfectly than these. He \vill seek to give us great respon­ good and o.mnipotent God would have done so.
    [Show full text]
  • Can Religious Experience Provide Justification for the Belief in God? the Debate in Contemporary Analytic Philosophy Kai-Man Kwan* Hong Kong Baptist University
    Philosophy Compass 1/6 (2006): 640–661, 10.1111/j.1747-9991.2006.00037.x Can Religious Experience Provide Justification for the Belief in God? The Debate in Contemporary Analytic Philosophy Kai-man Kwan* Hong Kong Baptist University Abstract In recent analytic philosophy of religion, one hotly debated topic is the veridicality of religious experience. In this paper, I briefly trace how the argument from religious experience comes into prominence in the twentieth century. This is due to the able defense of this argument by Richard Swinburne,William Alston, and Jerome Gellman among others. I explain the argument’s intuitive force and why the stock objections to religious experience are not entirely convincing. I expound Swinburne’s approach and his application of the Principle of Credulity to religious experience. Then I critically examine four major objections to Swinburne. I conclude that the argument from religious experiences is not likely to be conclusive but it should not be dismissed either. The Experiential Roots of Religion Religion is characterized by the passion that it can arouse. Why is religion capable of such enormous effects on human life? Apart from the fact that religion is about the ultimate concern of human beings, we also need to bear in mind that religion often has an experiential basis. God is not just a hypothesis for the religiously devoted. He is a Living Reality who permeates all their lives. Those people who experience God will echo with Job: “I have heard of thee by the hearing of the ear, but now mine eye seeth thee” (Holy Bible, Job 42.5).
    [Show full text]
  • I. Richard Swinburne's Theism
    UNIVERSITY OF NAVARRA ECCLESIASTICAL FACULTY OF PHILOSOPHY Alex Mbonimpa The Providence of God according to Richard Swinburne: A Critical Study under the Guidance of St. Thomas Aquinas. Thesis for a Doctorate supervised by Prof. Dr. Rev. Enrique Moros Pamplona 2016 TABLE OF CONTENTS TABLE OF CONTENTS ....................................................... 5 INTRODUCTION ................................................................ 11 Method.............................................................................. 15 Biographical Note............................................................. 19 Acknowledgements .......................................................... 24 I. RICHARD SWINBURNE’S THEISM ............................ 27 1. Justification and Knowledge ............................................ 29 1.1 Subjective Justification ............................................. 30 1.2 Objective Justification .............................................. 32 1.3 The Quest for an Ultimate Explanation .................... 35 a) How Explanation Works ........................................ 37 b) The Truth of an Explanation .................................. 41 c) Candidates for an Ultimate Explanation ................ 46 1.4 The Justification of Theism ...................................... 47 a) The Simplicity of Theism....................................... 47 b) The Limit of Scientific Explanation ....................... 50 2. The Attributes of God....................................................... 53 2.1 What Swinburne
    [Show full text]
  • The Atheist Trap, Or the Argument from Design and Scientific Falsification
    University of Rhode Island DigitalCommons@URI Open Access Master's Theses 1993 The Atheist Trap, or the Argument from Design and Scientific Falsification Joseph R. Mixie University of Rhode Island Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.uri.edu/theses Recommended Citation Mixie, Joseph R., "The Atheist Trap, or the Argument from Design and Scientific alsificationF " (1993). Open Access Master's Theses. Paper 1761. https://digitalcommons.uri.edu/theses/1761 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by DigitalCommons@URI. It has been accepted for inclusion in Open Access Master's Theses by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@URI. For more information, please contact [email protected]. BTI02 M589 1993 THE A THEIST TRAP, OR THE ARGUMENT FROM DESIGN AND SCIENTIFIC FALSIFICATION ISM BY JOSEPH R. MIXIE A THESIS SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF ARTS IN PHILOSOPHY 2 I<;'�,,,,�,. -;; UNIVERSITY OF RHODE ISLAND ... 1993 THESIS ABSTRACT The argument from design is one of the most widely debated arguments for the existence of God. There has been much written in support of and in criticism of the argument's basic structure and conclusion. I shall attempt to clarify these positions, and to argue that the thei?ti c account provides a more rationally justified explanation of human life on earth than the atheistic account. Many philosophers think that any proof for the existence of God is mere "metaphysical speculation." Many times these philosophers use the criteria of scientific empiricism as the standard for an "acceptable" scientific theory, regardless of the subject matter.
    [Show full text]