Circuit Complexity, Proof Complexity and Polynomial Identity Testing (Extended Abstract)

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Circuit Complexity, Proof Complexity and Polynomial Identity Testing (Extended Abstract) Circuit Complexity, Proof Complexity and Polynomial Identity Testing (Extended abstract) Joshua A. Grochow Toniann Pitassi Santa Fe Institute Depts. of Computer Science and Mathematics Santa Fe, NM, USA University of Toronto Email: [email protected] Toronto, Canada Email: [email protected] Abstract—We introduce a new and natural algebraic proof prior to our work, essentially all implications went the op- system, which has tight connections to (algebraic) circuit posite direction: a circuit complexity lower bound implying complexity. In particular, we show that any super-polynomial a proof complexity lower bound. We use this result to begin lower bound on any Boolean tautology in our proof system implies that the permanent does not have polynomial-size to explain why several long-open lower bound questions algebraic circuits (VNP 6= VP). in proof complexity—lower bounds on Extended Frege, 0 As a corollary, super-polynomial lower bounds on the on AC [p]-Frege, and on number-of-lines in Polynomial number of lines in Polynomial Calculus proofs (as opposed Calculus-style proofs—have been so apparently difficult. to the usual measure of number of monomials) imply the Permanent versus Determinant Conjecture. A. Background and Motivation Note that, prior to our work, there was no proof system for which lower bounds on an arbitrary tautology implied any Algebraic Circuit Complexity.: The most natural way to computational lower bound. compute a polynomial function f(x1; : : : ; xn) is with a se- Our proof system helps clarify the relationships between quence of instructions g1; : : : ; gm = f—called an algebraic previous algebraic proof systems, and begins to shed light circuit or a straight-line program—starting from the inputs on why proof complexity lower bounds for various proof x ; : : : ; x , and where each instruction g is of the form g ◦ systems have been so much harder than lower bounds on the 1 n i j corresponding circuit classes. In doing so, we highlight the im- gk for some j; k < i, where ◦ is either a linear combination portance of polynomial identity testing (PIT) for understanding or multiplication. The goal of algebraic complexity is to un- proof complexity. derstand the optimal asymptotic complexity of computing a 1 Keywords-AC0[p]-Frege; algebraic circuit complexity; Grob- given polynomial family (fn(x1; : : : ; xpoly(n))n=1, typically ner bases; lower bounds; polynomial identity testing; proof in terms of size and depth of algebraic circuits. In addition complexity; syzygies to the intrinsic interest in these questions, since Valiant’s All proofs are present in the freely available draft of the work [2] algebraic complexity has become more and more full version [1]. important for Boolean computational complexity. Valiant argued that understanding algebraic complexity could give new intuitions that may lead to better understanding of other I. INTRODUCTION models of computation; several direct connections have been NP versus coNP is the very natural question of whether, found between algebraic and Boolean complexity [3], [4], for every graph that doesn’t have a Hamiltonian path, there is [5]; and the Geometric Complexity Theory Program (see, a short proof of this fact. One of the arguments for the utility e. g., the overview [6] and references therein) suggests how of proof complexity is that by proving lower bounds against algebraic techniques might be used to resolve major Boolean stronger and stronger proof systems, we “make progress” complexity conjectures. towards proving NP 6= coNP. However, until now this Two central functions in this area are the determinant argument has been more the expression of a philosophy or and permanent polynomials, which are fundamental both be- hope, as there is no known proof system for which lower cause of their prominent role in many areas of mathematics bounds imply computational complexity lower bounds of and because they are complete for various natural complex- any kind, let alone NP 6= coNP. ity classes. In particular, the permanent of f0; 1g-matrices We remedy this situation by introducing a very natural is #P-complete, and the permanent of arbitrary matrices algebraic proof system, which has tight connections to is VNP-complete. Valiant’s Permanent versus Determinant (algebraic) circuit complexity. We show that any super- Conjecture [2] states that the permanent of an n × n matrix, polynomial lower bound on any Boolean tautology in our as a polynomial in n2 variables, cannot be written as the proof system implies that the permanent does not have determinant of any polynomially larger matrix all of whose polynomial-size algebraic circuits (VNP 6= VP). Note that, entries are variables or constants. Unlike in Boolean circuit complexity, (slightly) non-trivial Definition 1 (Ideal Proof System). An IPS certificate that a lower bounds for the size of algebraic circuits are known system of F-polynomial equations F1(~x) = F2(~x) = ··· = [7], [8]. However, their techniques only give lower bounds Fm(~x) = 0 is unsatisfiable over F is a polynomial C(~x;~y) up to Ω(n log n). Moreover, their methods do not give in the variables x1; : : : ; xn and y1; : : : ; ym such that lower bounds for polynomials of constant degree. Recent 1) C(x1; : : : ; xn;~0) = 0, and exciting work [9], [10], [11] has shown that polynomial- 2) C(x1; : : : ; xn;F1(~x);:::;Fm(~x)) = 1. size algebraic circuits computing functions of polynomial The first condition is equivalent to C being in the ideal degree can in fact be computed by subexponential-size depth generated by y ; : : : ; y , and the two conditions together 4 algebraic circuits. Thus, strong enough lower bounds for 1 m therefore imply that 1 is in the ideal generated by the F , depth 4 algebraic circuits for the permanent would already i and hence that F (~x) = ··· = F (~x) = 0 is unsatisfiable. prove VP 6= VNP. 1 m An IPS proof of the unsatisfiability of the polynomials Proof Complexity.: Despite considerable progress ob- Fi is an F-algebraic circuit on inputs x1; : : : ; xn; y1; : : : ; ym taining super-polynomial lower bounds for many weak proof computing some IPS certificate of unsatisfiability. systems (resolution, cutting planes, bounded-depth Frege systems), there has been essentially no progress in the last For any class C of polynomial families, we may speak 25 years for stronger proof systems such as Extended Frege of C-IPS proofs of a family of systems of equations (Fn) systems or Frege systems. More surprisingly, no nontrivial where Fn is Fn;1(~x) = ··· = Fn;poly(n)(~x) = 0. When we lower bounds are known for the seemingly weak AC0[p]- refer to IPS without further qualification, we mean VP-IPS, Frege system. In contrast, the analogous result in circuit i. e., the family of IPS proofs should be computed by circuits complexity was resolved by Smolensky over 25 years ago of polynomial size and polynomial degree. [12]. The Ideal Proof System is easily shown to be sound; To date, there has been no satisfactory explanation for its completeness (without size bounds) follows from the this state of affairs. In proof complexity, there are no Nullstellensatz. known formal barriers such as relativization [13], Razborov– We typically consider IPS as a propositional proof system Rudich natural proofs [14], or algebrization [15] that exist in by translating a CNF tautology ' into a system of equations Boolean function complexity. Moreover, there has not even in the following standard way. We translate a clause κ of been progress by way of conditional lower bounds. That is, ' into a single algebraic equation F (~x) using x 7! 1 − x, trivially NP 6= coNP implies superpolynomial lower bounds x_y 7! xy.A f0; 1g-assignment thus satisfies κ if and only for AC0[p]-Frege, but we know of no weaker complexity if it satisfies the equation F = 0. We add to this system 2 assumption that implies such lower bounds. The only formal of equations the equations xi − xi = 0, which forces any implication in this direction shows that certain circuit lower solutions over F to be f0; 1g-valued. bounds imply lower bounds for proof systems that admit Like previously defined algebraic systems [18], [19], [20], feasible interpolation, but unfortunately even very weak [21], proofs in our system can be checked in randomized proof systems such as Frege and AC0-Frege don’t have this polynomial time. The key difference between our system and property, under standard complexity-theoretic assumptions previously studied ones is that those systems are axiomatic [16], [17]. In the converse direction, there are essentially no in the sense that they require that every sub-computation implications at all. For example, we do not know if AC0[p]- (derived polynomial) be in the ideal generated by the original Frege lower bounds—nor even Frege nor Extended Frege polynomial equations Fi, and thus be a sound consequence lower bounds—imply any nontrivial circuit lower bounds. of the equations F1 = ··· = Fm = 0. In contrast our system has no such requirement; an IPS B. Our Results proof can compute potentially unsound sub-computations In this paper, we define a simple and natural proof system (whose vanishing does not follow from F1 = ··· = Fm = that we call the Ideal Proof System (IPS) based on Hilbert’s 0), as long as the final polynomial is in the ideal generated Nullstellensatz. Our system is similar in spirit to related by the equations. This key difference allows IPS proofs to algebraic proof systems that have been studied previously, be ordinary algebraic circuits, and thus nearly all results in but is different in a crucial way that we explain below. algebraic circuit complexity apply directly to the Ideal Proof Given a set of polynomials F1;:::;Fm in n variables System. To quote the tagline of a common US food chain, x1; : : : ; xn over a field F without a common zero over the IPS is a “No rules, just right” proof system.
Recommended publications
  • Circuit Complexity, Proof Complexity and Polynomial Identity Testing
    Electronic Colloquium on Computational Complexity, Report No. 52 (2014) Circuit Complexity, Proof Complexity and Polynomial Identity Testing Joshua A. Grochow and Toniann Pitassi April 12, 2014 Abstract We introduce a new and very natural algebraic proof system, which has tight connections to (algebraic) circuit complexity. In particular, we show that any super-polynomial lower bound on any Boolean tautology in our proof system implies that the permanent does not have polynomial- size algebraic circuits (VNP 6= VP). As a corollary to the proof, we also show that super- polynomial lower bounds on the number of lines in Polynomial Calculus proofs (as opposed to the usual measure of number of monomials) imply the Permanent versus Determinant Conjecture. Note that, prior to our work, there was no proof system for which lower bounds on an arbitrary tautology implied any computational lower bound. Our proof system helps clarify the relationships between previous algebraic proof systems, and begins to shed light on why proof complexity lower bounds for various proof systems have been so much harder than lower bounds on the corresponding circuit classes. In doing so, we highlight the importance of polynomial identity testing (PIT) for understanding proof complex- ity. More specifically, we introduce certain propositional axioms satisfied by any Boolean circuit computing PIT. (The existence of efficient proofs for our PIT axioms appears to be somewhere in between the major conjecture that PIT2 P and the known result that PIT2 P=poly.) We use these PIT axioms to shed light on AC0[p]-Frege lower bounds, which have been open for nearly 30 years, with no satisfactory explanation as to their apparent difficulty.
    [Show full text]
  • Reflection Principles, Propositional Proof Systems, and Theories
    Reflection principles, propositional proof systems, and theories In memory of Gaisi Takeuti Pavel Pudl´ak ∗ July 30, 2020 Abstract The reflection principle is the statement that if a sentence is provable then it is true. Reflection principles have been studied for first-order theories, but they also play an important role in propositional proof complexity. In this paper we will revisit some results about the reflection principles for propositional proofs systems using a finer scale of reflection principles. We will use the result that proving lower bounds on Resolution proofs is hard in Resolution. This appeared first in the recent article of Atserias and M¨uller [2] as a key lemma and was generalized and simplified in some spin- off papers [11, 13, 12]. We will also survey some results about arithmetical theories and proof systems associated with them. We will show a connection between a conjecture about proof complexity of finite consistency statements and a statement about proof systems associated with a theory. 1 Introduction arXiv:2007.14835v1 [math.LO] 29 Jul 2020 This paper is essentially a survey of some well-known results in proof complexity supple- mented with some observations. In most cases we will also sketch or give an idea of the proofs. Our aim is to focus on some interesting results rather than giving a complete ac- count of known results. We presuppose knowledge of basic concepts and theorems in proof complexity. An excellent source is Kraj´ıˇcek’s last book [19], where you can find the necessary definitions and read more about the results mentioned here.
    [Show full text]
  • Contents Part 1. a Tour of Propositional Proof Complexity. 418 1. Is There A
    The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic Volume 13, Number 4, Dec. 2007 THE COMPLEXITY OF PROPOSITIONAL PROOFS NATHAN SEGERLIND Abstract. Propositional proof complexity is the study of the sizes of propositional proofs, and more generally, the resources necessary to certify propositional tautologies. Questions about proof sizes have connections with computational complexity, theories of arithmetic, and satisfiability algorithms. This is article includes a broad survey of the field, and a technical exposition of some recently developed techniques for proving lower bounds on proof sizes. Contents Part 1. A tour of propositional proof complexity. 418 1. Is there a way to prove every tautology with a short proof? 418 2. Satisfiability algorithms and theories of arithmetic 420 3. A menagerie of Frege-like proof systems 427 4. Reverse mathematics of propositional principles 434 5. Feasible interpolation 437 6. Further connections with satisfiability algorithms 438 7. Beyond the Frege systems 441 Part 2. Some lower bounds on refutation sizes. 444 8. The size-width trade-off for resolution 445 9. The small restriction switching lemma 450 10. Expansion clean-up and random 3-CNFs 459 11. Resolution pseudowidth and very weak pigeonhole principles 467 Part 3. Open problems, further reading, acknowledgments. 471 Appendix. Notation. 472 References. 473 Received June 27, 2007. This survey article is based upon the author’s Sacks Prize winning PhD dissertation, however, the emphasis here is on context. The vast majority of results discussed are not the author’s, and several results from the author’s dissertation are omitted. c 2007, Association for Symbolic Logic 1079-8986/07/1304-0001/$7.50 417 418 NATHAN SEGERLIND Part 1.
    [Show full text]
  • A Short History of Computational Complexity
    The Computational Complexity Column by Lance FORTNOW NEC Laboratories America 4 Independence Way, Princeton, NJ 08540, USA [email protected] http://www.neci.nj.nec.com/homepages/fortnow/beatcs Every third year the Conference on Computational Complexity is held in Europe and this summer the University of Aarhus (Denmark) will host the meeting July 7-10. More details at the conference web page http://www.computationalcomplexity.org This month we present a historical view of computational complexity written by Steve Homer and myself. This is a preliminary version of a chapter to be included in an upcoming North-Holland Handbook of the History of Mathematical Logic edited by Dirk van Dalen, John Dawson and Aki Kanamori. A Short History of Computational Complexity Lance Fortnow1 Steve Homer2 NEC Research Institute Computer Science Department 4 Independence Way Boston University Princeton, NJ 08540 111 Cummington Street Boston, MA 02215 1 Introduction It all started with a machine. In 1936, Turing developed his theoretical com- putational model. He based his model on how he perceived mathematicians think. As digital computers were developed in the 40's and 50's, the Turing machine proved itself as the right theoretical model for computation. Quickly though we discovered that the basic Turing machine model fails to account for the amount of time or memory needed by a computer, a critical issue today but even more so in those early days of computing. The key idea to measure time and space as a function of the length of the input came in the early 1960's by Hartmanis and Stearns.
    [Show full text]
  • Proof Complexity in Algebraic Systems and Bounded Depth Frege Systems with Modular Counting
    PROOF COMPLEXITY IN ALGEBRAIC SYSTEMS AND BOUNDED DEPTH FREGE SYSTEMS WITH MODULAR COUNTING S. Buss, R. Impagliazzo, J. Kraj¶³cek,· P. Pudlak,¶ A. A. Razborov and J. Sgall Abstract. We prove a lower bound of the form N ­(1) on the degree of polynomials in a Nullstellensatz refutation of the Countq polynomials over Zm, where q is a prime not dividing m. In addition, we give an explicit construction of a degree N ­(1) design for the Countq principle over Zm. As a corollary, using Beame et al. (1994) we obtain ­(1) a lower bound of the form 2N for the number of formulas in a constant-depth N Frege proof of the modular counting principle Countq from instances of the counting M principle Countm . We discuss the polynomial calculus proof system and give a method of converting tree-like polynomial calculus derivations into low degree Nullstellensatz derivations. Further we show that a lower bound for proofs in a bounded depth Frege system in the language with the modular counting connective MODp follows from a lower bound on the degree of Nullstellensatz proofs with a constant number of levels of extension axioms, where the extension axioms comprise a formalization of the approximation method of Razborov (1987), Smolensky (1987) (in fact, these two proof systems are basically equivalent). Introduction A propositional proof system is intuitively a system for establishing the validity of propo- sitional tautologies in some ¯xed complete language. The formal de¯nition of propositional proof system is that it is a polynomial time function f which maps strings over an alphabet § onto the set of propositional tautologies (Cook & Reckhow 1979).
    [Show full text]
  • On Monotone Circuits with Local Oracles and Clique Lower Bounds
    On monotone circuits with local oracles and clique lower bounds Jan Kraj´ıˇcek Igor C. Oliveira Faculty of Mathematics and Physics Charles University in Prague December 17, 2019 Abstract We investigate monotone circuits with local oracles [K., 2016], i.e., circuits containing additional inputs yi = yi(~x) that can perform unstructured computations on the input string ~x. Let µ [0, 1] be the locality of the circuit, a parameter that bounds the combined ∈ m strength of the oracle functions yi(~x), and Un,k, Vn,k 0, 1 be the set of k-cliques and the set of complete (k 1)-partite graphs, respectively⊆ (similarly { } to [Razborov, 1985]). Our results can be informally− stated as follows. (i) For an appropriate extension of depth-2 monotone circuits with local oracles, we show that the size of the smallest circuits separating Un,3 (triangles) and Vn,3 (complete bipartite graphs) undergoes two phase transitions according to µ. (ii) For 5 k(n) n1/4, arbitrary depth, and µ 1/50, we prove that the monotone ≤ ≤ ≤ Θ(√k) circuit size complexity of separating the sets Un,k and Vn,k is n , under a certain restrictive assumption on the local oracle gates. The second result, which concerns monotone circuits with restricted oracles, extends and provides a matching upper bound for the exponential lower bounds on the monotone circuit size complexity of k-clique obtained by Alon and Boppana (1987). 1 Introduction and motivation arXiv:1704.06241v3 [cs.CC] 16 Dec 2019 We establish initial lower bounds on the power of monotone circuits with local oracles (mono- tone CLOs), an extension of monotone circuits introduced in [Kra16] motivated by problems in proof complexity.
    [Show full text]
  • Propositional Proof Complexity Past Present and Future
    Prop ositional Pro of Complexity Past Present and Future Paul Beame and Toniann Pitassi Abstract Pro of complexity the study of the lengths of pro ofs in prop ositional logic is an area of study that is fundamentally connected b oth to ma jor op en questions of computational complexity theory and to practical prop erties of automated theorem provers In the last decade there have b een a number of signicant advances in pro of complexity lower b ounds Moreover new connections b etween pro of complexity and circuit complexity have b een uncovered and the interplay b etween these two areas has b ecome quite rich In addition attempts to extend existing lower b ounds to ever stronger systems of pro of have spurred the introduction of new and interesting pro of systems adding b oth to the practical asp ects of pro of complexity as well as to a rich theory This note attempts to survey these developments and to lay out some of the op en problems in the area Introduction One of the most basic questions of logic is the following Given a uni versally true statement tautology what is the length of the shortest pro of of the statement in some standard axiomatic pro of system The prop osi tional logic version of this question is particularly imp ortant in computer science for b oth theorem proving and complexity theory Imp ortant related algorithmic questions are Is there an ecient algorithm that will pro duce a pro of of any tautology Is there an ecient algorithm to pro duce the shortest pro of of any tautology Such questions of theorem proving and
    [Show full text]
  • Proof Complexity I: Introduction to Propositional Proof Complexity
    Proof Complexity I: Introduction to propositional proof complexity Sam Buss Caleidoscope Research School Institute Henri Poincar´e, Paris June 17-18, 2019 Sam Buss Proof Complexity I This talk discusses: Proof systems: Frege proofs, extended Frege proofs, abstract proof systems, resolution, cutting planes, nullstellensatz, the polynomial calculus. The extension rule: Frege versus extended resolution (equivalent to extended Frege). Resolution versus extended resolution Interpolation and lower bounds: Resolution. Cutting planes. Automatizability and conditional lower bounds. Sam Buss Proof Complexity I Propositional logic, satisfiability, tautologies Propositional formulas: Variables: Range over True/False. Literal: Variables and negated variables. Formulas: Formed from variables/literals, and propositional connectives, such as ∧, ∨, →, ¬. CNF, DNF - Conjunctive/Disjunctive Normal Form Formulas. Satisfiability and Validity: A formula ϕ is a tautology iff every truth assignment makes ϕ true. A formula ϕ is satisfiable iff some truth assignment makes ϕ true. ϕ is unsatisfiable iff ¬ϕ is a tautology. It is NP-hard to determine satisfiability/validity of ϕ. One way to establish unsatisfiability is to give a proof of ¬ϕ. Sam Buss Proof Complexity I The Frege proof system F is a “textbook-style” propositional proof system with Modus Ponens as its only rule of inference. Variables: x, y, z,... range over True/False. Connectives: ¬, ∧, ∨, →. Modus Ponens: ϕ ϕ → ψ . ψ Axiom Schemes: ϕ → ψ → ϕ (ϕ → ψ) → (ϕ → ψ → χ) → (ϕ → χ) ϕ → ψ → ϕ ∧ ψ ϕ ∧ ψ → ϕ ϕ ∧ ψ → ψ and 5 more axiom schemes. Defn: The size of a Frege proof is the number of symbols in the proof. F m ϕ means ϕ has an F proof of size m.
    [Show full text]
  • A Reduction of Proof Complexity to Computational Complexity for $ AC^ 0 [P] $ Frege Systems
    A reduction of proof complexity to computational complexity for AC0[p] Frege systems Jan Kraj´ıˇcek Faculty of Mathematics and Physics Charles University in Prague Abstract We give a general reduction of lengths-of-proofs lower bounds for con- stant depth Frege systems in DeMorgan language augmented by a connec- tive counting modulo a prime p (the so called AC0[p] Frege systems) to computational complexity lower bounds for search tasks involving search trees branching upon values of maps on the vector space of low degree polynomials over Fp. In 1988 Ajtai [2] proved that the unsatisfiable set (¬PHPn) of propositional formulas _ pij and ¬pi1j ∨ ¬pi2j and ¬pij1 ∨ ¬pij2 j∈[n] for all i ∈ [n +1] = {1,...,n +1} , all i1 6= i2 ∈ [n + 1], j ∈ [n], and all i ∈ [n + 1], j1 6= j2 ∈ [n] respectively, expressing the failure of the pigeonhole principle (PHP), has for no d ≥ 1 a polynomial size refutation in a Frege proof system operating only with DeMorgan formulas of depth at most d. Subse- quently Kraj´ıˇcek [18] established an exponential lower bound for these so called AC0 Frege proof systems (for different formulas) and Kraj´ıˇcek, Pudl´ak and Woods [23] and Pitassi, Beame and Impagliazzo [26] improved independently (and announced jointly in [7]) Ajtai’s bound for PHP to exponential. All these papers employ some adaptation of the random restriction method arXiv:1311.2501v4 [math.LO] 22 Aug 2014 that has been so successfully applied earlier in circuit complexity (cf. [1, 14, 31, 15]). Razborov [28] invented already in 1987 an elegant method, simplified and generalized by Smolensky [30], to prove lower bounds even for AC0[p] circuits, p a prime.
    [Show full text]
  • Bounded Arithmetic and Propositional Proof Complexity
    Bounded Arithmetic and Propositional Proof Complexity Samuel R. Buss¤ Departments of Mathematics and Computer Science University of California, San Deigo La Jolla, CA 92093-0112 Abstract This is a survey of basic facts about bounded arithmetic and about the relationships between bounded arithmetic and propositional proof i i complexity. We introduce the theories S2 and T2 of bounded arithmetic and characterize their proof theoretic strength and their provably total functions in terms of the polynomial time hierarchy. We discuss other axiomatizations of bounded arithmetic, such as minimization axioms. It is shown that the bounded arithmetic hierarchy collapses if and only if bounded arithmetic proves that the polynomial hierarchy collapses. We discuss Frege and extended Frege proof length, and the two translations from bounded arithmetic proofs into propositional proofs. We present some theorems on bounding the lengths of propositional interpolants in terms of cut-free proof length and in terms of the lengths of resolution refutations. We then de¯ne the Razborov- Rudich notion of natural proofs of P =6 NP and discuss Razborov's theorem that certain fragments of bounded arithmetic cannot prove superpolynomial lower bounds on circuit size, assuming a strong cryptographic conjecture. Finally, a complete presentation of a proof of the theorem of Razborov is given. 1 Review of Computational Complexity 1.1 Feasibility This article will be concerned with various \feasible" forms of computability and of provability. For something to be feasibly computable, it must be computable in practice in the real world, not merely e®ectively computable in the sense of being recursively computable. ¤Supported in part by NSF grants DMS-9503247 and DMS-9205181.
    [Show full text]
  • Generalizing Boolean Satisfiability II
    Journal of Artificial Intelligence Research 22 (2004) 481-534 Submitted 08/04; published 12/04 Generalizing Boolean Satisfiability II: Theory Heidi E. Dixon [email protected] On Time Systems, Inc. 1850 Millrace, Suite 1 Eugene, OR 97403 USA Matthew L. Ginsberg [email protected] On Time Systems, Inc. 1850 Millrace, Suite 1 Eugene, OR 97403 USA Eugene M. Luks [email protected] Computer and Information Science University of Oregon Eugene, OR 97403 USA Andrew J. Parkes [email protected] CIRL 1269 University of Oregon Eugene, OR 97403 USA Abstract This is the second of three planned papers describing zap, a satisfiability engine that substantially generalizes existing tools while retaining the performance characteristics of modern high performance solvers. The fundamental idea underlying zap is that many problems passed to such engines contain rich internal structure that is obscured by the Boolean representation used; our goal is to define a representation in which this structure is apparent and can easily be exploited to improve computational performance. This paper presents the theoretical basis for the ideas underlying zap, arguing that existing ideas in this area exploit a single, recurring structure in that multiple database axioms can be obtained by operating on a single axiom using a subgroup of the group of permutations on the literals in the problem. We argue that the group structure precisely captures the general structure at which earlier approaches hinted, and give numerous examples of its use. We go on to extend the Davis-Putnam-Logemann-Loveland inference procedure to this broader setting, and show that earlier computational improvements are either subsumed or left intact by the new method.
    [Show full text]
  • Proof Complexity Lower Bounds from Algebraic Circuit Complexity∗
    Proof Complexity Lower Bounds from Algebraic Circuit Complexity∗ Michael A. Forbes1, Amir Shpilka2, Iddo Tzameret3, and Avi Wigderson4 1 Department of Computer Science, Princeton University, Princeton, USA [email protected] 2 Department of Computer Science, Tel Aviv University, Tel Aviv, Israel [email protected] 3 Department of Computer Science, Royal Holloway, University of London, Egham, UK [email protected] 4 School of Mathematics, Institute for Advanced Study, Princeton, USA [email protected] Abstract We give upper and lower bounds on the power of subsystems of the Ideal Proof System (IPS), the algebraic proof system recently proposed by Grochow and Pitassi [26], where the circuits comprising the proof come from various restricted algebraic circuit classes. This mimics an established research direction in the boolean setting for subsystems of Extended Frege proofs whose lines are circuits from restricted boolean circuit classes. Essentially all of the subsystems considered in this paper can simulate the well-studied Nullstellensatz proof system, and prior to this work there were no known lower bounds when measuring proof size by the algebraic complexity of the polynomials (except with respect to degree, or to sparsity). Our main contributions are two general methods of converting certain algebraic lower bounds into proof complexity ones. Both require stronger arithmetic lower bounds than common, which should hold not for a specific polynomial but for a whole family defined by it. These may be likened to some of the methods by which Boolean circuit lower bounds are turned into related proof-complexity ones, especially the “feasible interpolation” technique.
    [Show full text]