How Not to Think About Evolution
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
Transformations of Lamarckism Vienna Series in Theoretical Biology Gerd B
Transformations of Lamarckism Vienna Series in Theoretical Biology Gerd B. M ü ller, G ü nter P. Wagner, and Werner Callebaut, editors The Evolution of Cognition , edited by Cecilia Heyes and Ludwig Huber, 2000 Origination of Organismal Form: Beyond the Gene in Development and Evolutionary Biology , edited by Gerd B. M ü ller and Stuart A. Newman, 2003 Environment, Development, and Evolution: Toward a Synthesis , edited by Brian K. Hall, Roy D. Pearson, and Gerd B. M ü ller, 2004 Evolution of Communication Systems: A Comparative Approach , edited by D. Kimbrough Oller and Ulrike Griebel, 2004 Modularity: Understanding the Development and Evolution of Natural Complex Systems , edited by Werner Callebaut and Diego Rasskin-Gutman, 2005 Compositional Evolution: The Impact of Sex, Symbiosis, and Modularity on the Gradualist Framework of Evolution , by Richard A. Watson, 2006 Biological Emergences: Evolution by Natural Experiment , by Robert G. B. Reid, 2007 Modeling Biology: Structure, Behaviors, Evolution , edited by Manfred D. Laubichler and Gerd B. M ü ller, 2007 Evolution of Communicative Flexibility: Complexity, Creativity, and Adaptability in Human and Animal Communication , edited by Kimbrough D. Oller and Ulrike Griebel, 2008 Functions in Biological and Artifi cial Worlds: Comparative Philosophical Perspectives , edited by Ulrich Krohs and Peter Kroes, 2009 Cognitive Biology: Evolutionary and Developmental Perspectives on Mind, Brain, and Behavior , edited by Luca Tommasi, Mary A. Peterson, and Lynn Nadel, 2009 Innovation in Cultural Systems: Contributions from Evolutionary Anthropology , edited by Michael J. O ’ Brien and Stephen J. Shennan, 2010 The Major Transitions in Evolution Revisited , edited by Brett Calcott and Kim Sterelny, 2011 Transformations of Lamarckism: From Subtle Fluids to Molecular Biology , edited by Snait B. -
Natural Necessity Natural Selection
NATURAL SELECTION NATURAL NECESSITY See Laws of Nature NATURAL SELECTION In modern evolutionary biology, a set of objects is Adaptationism said to experience a selection process precisely when At the close of his introduction to those objects vary in/itness (see Fitness). For exam On the Origin oj' ple, if zebras that run fast are fitter than zehras that Species, Darwin [1859] 1964, 6 says that natural selection is "the main but not the exclusive" cause run slow (perhaps because faster zebras are better ofevolution. In reaction to misinterpretations ofhis able to avoid lion predation), a selection process is theory, Darwin felt compelled to reemphasize, in the set in motion. If the trait that exhibits variation hook's last edition, that there was more to evolution in fit~ess is heritable-meaning, in our example, that faster parents tend to have faster offspring than natural selection. It remains a matter of con troversy in evolutionary biology how important and slower parents tend to have slower offspring then the selection process is apt to chancre trait natural selection has been in the history of life. frequencies in the population, leading fitte';. traits This is the poinl of biological substance that pres to increase in frequency and less fit traits to decline ently divides adaptationists and anti-adaptationists. The debate over adaptationism also has a separate (Lewontin 1970). This change is the one that selec tion is "apt" to engender, rather than the one that methodological dimension, with critics insisting that adaptive hypotheses be tested more rigorously must occur, because evolutionary theory describes <Gould and Lewontin 1979; Sober 1993). -
Part I April 1952
HEREDITY VOLUME 6 PART I APRIL 1952 STATISTICALMETHODS IN GENETICS R. A. FISHER Being the Bateson Lecture delivered at the John lnnes Horticultural Institution on Friday, 6th July 1951 * THEtitle chosen for this lecture is "StatisticalMethods in Genetics," but after hearing what I have written you may think that it is not so much an account of the contributions which the study of Statistics has made to the advance of Genetics, as an examination of the nature of genetical Science from the point of view of a statistician,. My reason for taking this point of view is that for many active years of my life I was fully engaged in doing what I could to further the progress of statistical methods, and that though for 25 years or so I have enjoyed the excitements of genetic experimentation, Genetics has only gradually come to be, for me, a whole time study, in place of a very fascinating hobby. Since that experience is in itself exceptional, it may be that the refiexions gathered on the way are worthy of record, and of interest to my genetical colleagues. Genetics and Statistics have in common that they are both characteristic products of the twentieth century. As we should recognise them now, neither of them existed before the year 1900. Of course I do not ignore the fact that earlier workers of many nations, Naudin and Godron, for example, Knight, Gaertner and Kohlreuter broached the practical problems of experimentation in heredity, or that on the theoretical side Galton and Weismann put forward speculations sometimes to an interesting extent near the truth. -
Writings of Charles De Koninck, Volume
D E K O N I N The Writings C K of ልሎ CHARLES C H DE KONINCK A R T L h E e S W D r i E t i n K g O s o N f I N C K ልሎ Edited and Translated by Ralph McInerny The Writings of CHARLES DE KONINCK Charles De Koninck, University of Laval, Quebec. The Writings of CHARLES DE KONINCK volume one Edited and Translated by Ralph McInerny with a biography by Thomas De Koninck andልሎ an introduction by Leslie Armour University of Notre Dame Press Notre Dame, Indiana DeKoninck-000.FM 4/15/08 1:17 PM Page iv Copyright © by University of Notre Dame Notre Dame, Indiana www.undpress.nd.edu All Rights Reserved Manufactured in the United States of America Designed by Wendy McMillen Set in ./. Minion by Four Star Books Printed on # Nature’s Recycle paper by Sheridan Books, Inc. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Koninck, Charles de, d. [Works. English. ] The writings of Charles De Koninck / edited and translated by Ralph McInerny ; with a biography by Thomas De Koninck ; and an introduction by Leslie Armour. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. -: ---- (cloth : alk. paper) -: --- (cloth : alk. paper) . Koninck, Charles de, d. Science—Philosophy. I. McInerny, Ralph M. II. Title. '.—dc This book is printed on recycled paper. Contents Preface vii The Philosophy of Charles De Koninck 1 Leslie Armour Charles De Koninck: A Biographical Sketch 69 Thomas De Koninck ልሎ Works by Charles De Koninck The Philosophy of Sir Arthur Eddington (1934) 99 The Cosmos (1936) 235 The Problem of Indeterminism (1935) 355 Reflections on the Problem of Indeterminism (1937) 401 Are the Experimental Sciences Distinct from the Philosophy of Nature? (1941) 443 Index 457 Preface A few years ago, David Quackenbush, a tutor at Thomas Aquinas College in California, conceived the idea of photocopying the Charles De Koninck ar- chives at the University of Laval. -
Mimicry, Saltational Evolution, and the Crossing of Fitness Valleys
CHAPTER 16 Mimicry, Saltational Evolution, and the Crossing of Fitness Valleys Olof Leimar, Birgitta S. Tullberg, and James Mallet 16.1 Introduction saltationism. In terms of Adaptive Landscapes, if the mimic-to-be resides on one adaptive peak and The relative contribution of gradual and saltational the model on another, mimicry evolves in a single change to evolution has been debated ever since mutational leap, and the issue of natural selection Darwin (1859) emphasized gradualism in his the- only enters through the constraint that the peak ory of evolution by natural selection. The phe- jumped to should be higher than the starting peak. nomenon of mimicry was an important example This would apply both to Müllerian mimicry, where in this debate. In mimicry evolution, members of the starting point is an aposematic species, and to a population or species become similar in appear- Batesian mimicry, where the starting adaptive peak ance to an aposematic model species and thereby of the palatable mimic-to-be is determined by func- gain increased protection from predation. The num- tions other than aposematism, for instance crypsis ber of steps in the approach to mimicry could be or other protective coloration, like flash coloration few or many and their sizes either large or small. (Cott 1940; Ruxton et al. 2004), or partner choice. In 1915, Punnett published an influential book on In response to claims like those by Punnett (1915), mimicry in butterflies, in which he summed up and as part of his efforts to unify gradualism and his strong opposition to gradualistic accounts of Mendelian genetics, Fisher (1927, 1930) presented mimicry evolution. -
The Origin of Historical Kinds in Biology and Culture Günter P. Wagne
Preprints (www.preprints.org) | NOT PEER-REVIEWED | Posted: 24 April 2019 doi:10.20944/preprints201904.0266.v1 Extending the Explanatory Scope of Evolutionary Theory: The Origin of Historical Kinds in Biology and Culture Günter P. Wagner and Gary Tomlinson Yale University Abstract Since its inception, evolutionary theory has experienced a number of extensions. The most important of these took the forms of the Modern Evolutionary Synthesis (MES), embracing genetics and population biology in the early 20th century, and the Extended Evolutionary Synthesis (EES) of the last thirty years, embracing, among other factors, non-genetic forms of inheritance. While we appreciate the motivation for this recent extension, we argue that it does not go far enough, since it restricts itself to widening explanations of adaptation by adding mechanisms of inheritance and variation. A more thoroughgoing extension is needed, one that widens the explanatory scope of evolutionary theory. In addition to adaptation and its various mechanisms, evolutionary theory must recognize as a distinct intellectual challenge the origin of what we call “historical kinds.” Under historical kinds we include any process that acquires a quasi-independent and traceable lineage-history in biological and cultural evolution. We develop the notion of a historical kind in a series of paradigmatic exemplars, from genes and homologues to rituals and music, and we propose a preliminary characterization. Keywords: historical individuals, extended evolutionary synthesis, evolutionary innovation, culture 1. Introduction For the last several decades, a set of concerns has exerted increasing pressure on the modern evolutionary synthesis (MES) of the mid-twentieth century, with the goal of widening the explanatory powers of evolutionary theory. -
Soft Inheritance: Challenging the Modern Synthesis
Genetics and Molecular Biology, 31, 2, 389-395 (2008) Copyright © 2008, Sociedade Brasileira de Genética. Printed in Brazil www.sbg.org.br Review Article Soft inheritance: Challenging the Modern Synthesis Eva Jablonka1 and Marion J. Lamb2 1The Cohn Institute for the History and Philosophy of Science and Ideas, Tel-Aviv University, Tel-Aviv, Israel. 211 Fernwood, Clarence Road, London, United Kingdom. Abstract This paper presents some of the recent challenges to the Modern Synthesis of evolutionary theory, which has domi- nated evolutionary thinking for the last sixty years. The focus of the paper is the challenge of soft inheritance - the idea that variations that arise during development can be inherited. There is ample evidence showing that phenotypic variations that are independent of variations in DNA sequence, and targeted DNA changes that are guided by epigenetic control systems, are important sources of hereditary variation, and hence can contribute to evolutionary changes. Furthermore, under certain conditions, the mechanisms underlying epigenetic inheritance can also lead to saltational changes that reorganize the epigenome. These discoveries are clearly incompatible with the tenets of the Modern Synthesis, which denied any significant role for Lamarckian and saltational processes. In view of the data that support soft inheritance, as well as other challenges to the Modern Synthesis, it is concluded that that synthesis no longer offers a satisfactory theoretical framework for evolutionary biology. Key words: epigenetic inheritance, hereditary variation, Lamarckism, macroevolution, microevolution. Received: March 18, 2008; Accepted: March 19, 2008. Introduction 1. Heredity occurs through the transmission of germ- There are winds of change in evolutionary biology, line genes. -
Examples of Orthogenetic Series in Plants and Animals : Studies In
THE OHIO JOURNAL OF SCIENCE VOL. XXXVII SEPTEMBER, 1937 No. 5 EXAMPLES OF ORTHOGENETIC SERIES IN PLANTS AND ANIMALS STUDIES IN DETERMINATE EVOLUTION X* JOHN H. SCHAFFNER Orthogenetic series are so prominent in both the plant and animal kingdoms that their consideration becomes of major significance in any careful study of the evolution of organisms. A few types of plant series are here presented together with several animal series in order to illustrate the nature and significance of orthogenesis. In studying living organisms one cannot tell directly, from the orthogenetic series itself, what is the real relationship of the members of a series to one another nor in what sequence they evolved; but this is after all of secondary importance. The fundamental problem is the fact that the evolutionary process brings out such a series and that these series usually have no relation either to utilitarian advan- tage or to any ecological conditions either physical or biological. The evolution of each series is commonly independent of other movements in the same group of organisms and may even proceed in a different direction or in a sequence exactly the opposite. In the past the most definite orthogenetic series were recognized in the fossil records and in these, of course, the direction of any given movement or sequence was definitely indicated by the succession of the rock strata in which the fossils were found. In attempting to explain orthogenetic series in the past it was usually assumed that the series was the result of natural selection or was produced by ecological sequences, either in time or space by a direct effect of the environment. -
The Third Base
Appendix The Third Base Donald Forsdyke If I thought that by learning more and more I should ever arrive at the knowledge of absolute truth, I would leave off studying. But I believe I am pretty safe. Samuel Butler, Notebooks Darwin’s mentor, the geologist Charles Lyell, and Darwin himself, both con- sidered the relationship between the evolution of biological species and the evolution of languages [1]. But neither took the subject to the deep informa- tional level of Butler and Hering. In the twentieth century the emergence of a new science – Evolutionary Bioinformatics (EB) – was heralded by two dis- coveries. First, that DNA – a linear polymer of four base units – was the chromosomal component conveying hereditary information. Second, that much of this information was “a phenomenon of arrangement” – determined by the sequence of the four bases. We conclude with a brief sketch of the new work as it relates to William Bateson’s evolutionary ideas. However, imbued with true Batesonian caution (“I will believe when I must”), it is relegated to an Appendix to indicate its provisional nature. Modern languages have similarities that indicate branching evolution from common ancestral languages [2]. We recognize early variations within a language as dialects or accents. When accents are incompatible, communi- cation is impaired. As accents get more disparate, mutual comprehension de- creases and at some point, when comprehension is largely lost, we declare that there are two languages where there was initially one. The origin of lan- guage begins with differences in accent. If we understand how differences in accent arise, then we may come to understand something fundamental about the origin of language (and hence of a text written in that language). -
Tempo and Mode in the Macroevolutionary Reconstruction of Darwinism STEPHEN JAY GOULD Museum of Comparative Zoology, Harvard University, Cambridge, MA 02138
Proc. Nadl. Acad. Sci. USA Vol. 91, pp. 6764-6771, July 1994 Colloquium Paper This paper was presented at a coloquium ented "Tempo and Mode in Evolution" organized by Walter M. Fitch and Francisco J. Ayala, held January 27-29, 1994, by the National Academy of Sciences, in Irvine, CA. Tempo and mode in the macroevolutionary reconstruction of Darwinism STEPHEN JAY GOULD Museum of Comparative Zoology, Harvard University, Cambridge, MA 02138 ABSTRACT Among the several central nings of Dar- But conceptual complexity is not reducible to a formula or winism, his version ofLyellian uniformitranism-the extrap- epigram (as we taxonomists of life's diversity should know olationist commitment to viewing causes ofsmall-scale, observ- better than most). Too much ink has been wasted in vain able change in modern populations as the complete source, by attempts to define the essence ofDarwin's ideas, or Darwin- smooth extension through geological time, of all magnitudes ism itself. Mayr (1) has correctly emphasized that many and sequences in evolution-has most contributed to the causal different, if related, Darwinisms exist, both in the thought of hegemony of microevolutlon and the assumption that paleon- the eponym himself, and in the subsequent history of evo- tology can document the contingent history of life but cannot lutionary biology-ranging from natural selection, to genea- act as a domain of novel evolutionary theory. G. G. Simpson logical connection of all living beings, to gradualism of tried to combat this view of paleontology as theoretically inert change. in his classic work, Tempo and Mode in Evolution (1944), with It would therefore be fatuous to claim that any one legit- a brilliant argument that the two subjects of his tide fall into a imate "essence" can be more basic or important than an- unue paleontological domain and that modes (processes and other. -
From Logos to Bios: Hellenic Philosophy and Evolutionary Biology
From Logos to Bios: Hellenic Philosophy and Evolutionary Biology by Wynand Albertus de Beer submitted in accordance with the requirements for the degree of D Litt et Phil in the subject Religious Studies at the University of South Africa Supervisor: Prof Danie Goosen February 2015 Dedicated with grateful acknowledgements to my supervisor, Professor Danie Goosen, for his wise and patient guidance and encouragement throughout my doctoral research, and to the examiners of my thesis for their helpful comments and suggestions. From Logos to Bios: Hellenic Philosophy and Evolutionary Biology by W.A. de Beer Degree: D Litt et Phil Subject: Religious Studies Supervisor: Prof Danie Goosen Summary: This thesis deals with the relation of Hellenic philosophy to evolutionary biology. The first part entails an explication of Hellenic cosmology and metaphysics in its traditional understanding, as the Western component of classical Indo-European philosophy. It includes an overview of the relevant contributions by the Presocratics, Plato, Aristotle, and the Neoplatonists, focussing on the structure and origin of both the intelligible and sensible worlds. Salient aspects thereof are the movement from the transcendent Principle into the realm of Manifestation by means of the interaction between Essence and Substance; the role of the Logos, being the equivalent of Plato’s Demiurge and Aristotle’s Prime Mover, in the cosmogonic process; the interaction between Intellect and Necessity in the formation of the cosmos; the various kinds of causality contributing to the establishment of physical reality; and the priority of being over becoming, which in the case of living organisms entails the primacy of soul over body. -
Statement About Pnas Paper “The New Mutation Theory of Phenotypic Evolution”
July 30, 2007 (revised) Brief Historical Perspectives of the Paper “THE NEW MUTATION THEORY OF PHENOTYPIC EVOLUTION” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, 104:12235-12242, Published July 17, 2007 online. Masatoshi Nei The following is the author’s account of the history of development of the mutation theory of phenotypic evolution and related matters. Darwinism (1) Charles Darwin proposed that evolution occurs by natural selection in the presence of fluctuating variation. (2) At his time, the mechanism of generation of new variation was not known, and he assumed that new variation is generated by climatic changes, inheritance of acquired characters, spontaneous variations, etc. However, he believed that new variation occurs in random direction and evolutionary change is caused by natural selection. (3) He assumed that enormous phenotypic diversity among different phyla and classes is the result of accumulation of gradual evolution by natural selection. Saltationism Several biologists such as Thomas Huxley, William Bateson, and Hugo de Vries argued that the extent of variation between species is much greater than that within 1 species and therefore saltational or macromutational change is necessary to form new species rather than gradual evolution as proposed by Darwin. In this view a new species can be produced by a single macromutation, and therefore natural selection is unimportant. This view was strengthened when de Vries discovered several new forms of evening primroses which were very different from the parental species (Oenothera lamarckiana) and appeared to be new species. This discovery suggested that new species can arise by a single step of macromutation. However, it was later shown that O.