Mimicry, Saltational Evolution, and the Crossing of Fitness Valleys

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Mimicry, Saltational Evolution, and the Crossing of Fitness Valleys CHAPTER 16 Mimicry, Saltational Evolution, and the Crossing of Fitness Valleys Olof Leimar, Birgitta S. Tullberg, and James Mallet 16.1 Introduction saltationism. In terms of Adaptive Landscapes, if the mimic-to-be resides on one adaptive peak and The relative contribution of gradual and saltational the model on another, mimicry evolves in a single change to evolution has been debated ever since mutational leap, and the issue of natural selection Darwin (1859) emphasized gradualism in his the- only enters through the constraint that the peak ory of evolution by natural selection. The phe- jumped to should be higher than the starting peak. nomenon of mimicry was an important example This would apply both to Müllerian mimicry, where in this debate. In mimicry evolution, members of the starting point is an aposematic species, and to a population or species become similar in appear- Batesian mimicry, where the starting adaptive peak ance to an aposematic model species and thereby of the palatable mimic-to-be is determined by func- gain increased protection from predation. The num- tions other than aposematism, for instance crypsis ber of steps in the approach to mimicry could be or other protective coloration, like flash coloration few or many and their sizes either large or small. (Cott 1940; Ruxton et al. 2004), or partner choice. In 1915, Punnett published an influential book on In response to claims like those by Punnett (1915), mimicry in butterflies, in which he summed up and as part of his efforts to unify gradualism and his strong opposition to gradualistic accounts of Mendelian genetics, Fisher (1927, 1930) presented mimicry evolution. He dismissed previous sug- a fully gradualistic alternative. He envisaged a gestions by Poulton (e.g. Poulton 1912, 1913) that genetically variable population of mimics-to-be and mimicry could emerge in a sequence of steps, begin- proposed that individuals with trait values deviat- ning with the appearance of a rough likeness of the ing from the population mean in the direction of would-be mimic to its model, followed by further the traits of the model species would be slightly improvement in resemblance. Punnett’s main argu- favored over deviations in the opposite direction, ment was representative of the thinking of the early because of a slightly higher probability of being Mendelians, who often pointed to a lack of interme- mistaken for the model by predators. The outcome diates between existing variants, inferring that the could be a gradual shifting of the mean trait val- variants had originated as mutants in a single step, ues in the direction of improved resemblance. It as opposed to being molded by natural selection appears that Fisher intended his gradualistic sce- through successive replacements of intermediate nario to apply both to Batesian and Müllerian rela- forms. As supporting evidence, Punnett used exam- tions, but it gained more attention in the latter case. ples of female-limited polymorphic mimicry, for In terms of (frequency-dependent) Adaptive Land- instance the one found in the butterfly Papilio poly- scapes of Müllerian mimicry evolution, Fisher’s tes, where the developmental switching between process would be a gradual shifting of two peaks, female morphs was known to be controlled by a until they overlap and, approximately, merge to a small number of Mendelian factors, later shown to single peak. be alleles at an autosomal locus (Clarke and Shep- Fisher’s (1927, 1930) proposition was not gener- pard 1972). Punnett’s position was thus a radical ally accepted. The strongest opposition came from 259 OUP CORRECTED PROOF– FINAL, 3/5/2012, SPi 260 PART V DEVELOPMENT, FORM, AND FUNCTION Goldschmidt (1945a,b), who ended his examina- predators, selection tends to operate on deviations tion of the issue by coming to the conclusion of appearances from the current population mean. that “Punnett’s interpretation of polymorphism by The selective peaks could be constrained, and in mutation (saltation) agrees better with the facts part formed by the aesthetics of predator learning, than Fisher’s neo-Darwinian theory.” Although not to particular regions of phenotypic space, as well as subscribing to the saltationism of Punnett and being influenced by selection towards the current Goldschmidt, even Fisher’s close associates (for mean. If the population mean appearance changes instance E. B. Ford and P. H. Sheppard), who to explore new aesthetic combinations, predator were preoccupied with the problem of Batesian learning need not always act to bring the mean back mimicry evolution, came to deviate in their views to a previous value. This implies that the mean may from Fisher’s original proposition (see Turner 1985 perform a random walk over evolutionary time, for an overview). Instead the so-called two-step exploring parts of the relevant trait space, and pos- process, where a large mutation first achieves sibly different peaks of an Adaptive Landscape, approximate similarity to the model, after which in a shifting balance process (Wright 1977; Mal- smaller changes can improve the likeness, became let and Singer 1987; Coyne et al. 1997; Mallet and accepted as describing Batesian mimicry evolution. Joron 1999; Mallet 2010; see also Chapters 2 and The idea is often credited to Nicholson (1927), 4–6). This would correspond to a random walk to a although Poulton (1912) had already suggested it. new adaptive peak. The phenomenon will be more Over time, the two-step process became accepted pronounced in small local populations, and/or in also in the context of Müllerian mimicry (Turner populations with limited predation pressure, where 1984; Sheppard et al. 1985). In terms of Adap- selection towards the current mean will be weak- tive Landscapes, the process entails a mutational ened. The process could be responsible both for leap from the adaptive peak of the mimic-to-be, mimicry evolution and for the rapid diversification protected as it is by predator learning of that of novel aposematic signals that occurs in many phenotype, to somewhere on the slope of the aposematic groups (Mallet and Joron 1999; Mallet higher, more protective peak of the model, thus 2010). crossing a fitness valley, followed by a series of In the following, we extend this brief review of modifications climbing the higher peak. Because the history of ideas, outlining some recent work mimicry often involves several traits, which at on mimicry evolution. The concept of an Adap- least initially can be genetically independent, this tive Landscape will be central in the presenta- first mutational leap is clearly a less demanding tion, in particular the question of how a transi- assumption than a saltation as argued for by Pun- tion from one adaptive peak to another can come nett and Goldschmidt. Even so, the assumption about. The landscapes we consider depict fitness needs to be backed up by arguments or observa- as a function of the phenotypic traits of individ- tions making it likely that predators in fact would uals, rather than as a function of genotype or avoid attacking the first, quite imperfect, mutant allele frequencies (see Chapters 1–3, 5, 7, 18 and 19 mimic. for expositions and discussions on different types A different kind of ingredient in explanations of of Adaptive Landscapes). It should be kept in mimicry evolution is that, possibly only in a partic- mind that, for aposematism and mimicry, Adaptive ular region or period of time, evolutionary forces Landscapes are strongly density- and frequency- other than mimicry may modify the appearances dependent, in the sense that their shapes depend of mimics-to-be, fortuitously bringing about suffi- on the traits and population sizes that are present cient resemblance to a model to start off mimicry in a prey community (this is also true for many evolution. Examples could be selection in relation other types of Adaptive Landscapes; see Chap- to mate choice or thermoregulation (Mallet and ter 7). The reason for the frequency dependence Singer 1987). Random genetic drift in small pop- is that predator behavior is influenced by learn- ulations is another general category of this kind. ing and generalization about the properties of the In aposematism, with learnt attack avoidance by community. OUP CORRECTED PROOF– FINAL, 3/5/2012, SPi MIMICRY, SALTATIONAL EVOLUTION, AND THE CROSSING OF FITNESS VALLEYS 261 16.2 Transitions between adaptive the most commonly used and empirically substan- peaks tiated in animal psychology (Ghirlanda and Enquist 2003). Similarly, the assumptions about predator Predators learn about prey, for instance to avoid learning follow broadly accepted ideas of associa- attacking those with particular appearances if they tive learning (Rescorla and Wagner 1972). have been found to be distasteful or otherwise Restricting attention to a single trait, a two- unprofitable in previous attacks. Generalization is step process of Müllerian mimicry evolution is another crucial aspect of predator psychology: if a illustrated in Fig. 16.1b. Because large-effect muta- predator encounters prey with a different appear- tions are known to occur, at least for certain ance than previous prey, the reaction to the new traits, for instance for the hue or intensity of pig- prey may be a generalized version of the learnt mentation (Socha and Nemec 1996), and because reaction to similar-looking prey. From assumptions large-effect alleles have been found in Müllerian about learning and generalization by predators in a mimicry systems (Joron et al. 206b; Baxter et al. predator–prey community, an Adaptive Landscape 2009), it follows that a two-step process involving of prey survival as a function of phenotype can be a single-locus mutation could well produce shifts defined. Fig. 16.1 shows a generalization function between adaptive peaks in one-dimensional trait and an Adaptive Landscape for a one-dimensional spaces. trait space.
Recommended publications
  • Transformations of Lamarckism Vienna Series in Theoretical Biology Gerd B
    Transformations of Lamarckism Vienna Series in Theoretical Biology Gerd B. M ü ller, G ü nter P. Wagner, and Werner Callebaut, editors The Evolution of Cognition , edited by Cecilia Heyes and Ludwig Huber, 2000 Origination of Organismal Form: Beyond the Gene in Development and Evolutionary Biology , edited by Gerd B. M ü ller and Stuart A. Newman, 2003 Environment, Development, and Evolution: Toward a Synthesis , edited by Brian K. Hall, Roy D. Pearson, and Gerd B. M ü ller, 2004 Evolution of Communication Systems: A Comparative Approach , edited by D. Kimbrough Oller and Ulrike Griebel, 2004 Modularity: Understanding the Development and Evolution of Natural Complex Systems , edited by Werner Callebaut and Diego Rasskin-Gutman, 2005 Compositional Evolution: The Impact of Sex, Symbiosis, and Modularity on the Gradualist Framework of Evolution , by Richard A. Watson, 2006 Biological Emergences: Evolution by Natural Experiment , by Robert G. B. Reid, 2007 Modeling Biology: Structure, Behaviors, Evolution , edited by Manfred D. Laubichler and Gerd B. M ü ller, 2007 Evolution of Communicative Flexibility: Complexity, Creativity, and Adaptability in Human and Animal Communication , edited by Kimbrough D. Oller and Ulrike Griebel, 2008 Functions in Biological and Artifi cial Worlds: Comparative Philosophical Perspectives , edited by Ulrich Krohs and Peter Kroes, 2009 Cognitive Biology: Evolutionary and Developmental Perspectives on Mind, Brain, and Behavior , edited by Luca Tommasi, Mary A. Peterson, and Lynn Nadel, 2009 Innovation in Cultural Systems: Contributions from Evolutionary Anthropology , edited by Michael J. O ’ Brien and Stephen J. Shennan, 2010 The Major Transitions in Evolution Revisited , edited by Brett Calcott and Kim Sterelny, 2011 Transformations of Lamarckism: From Subtle Fluids to Molecular Biology , edited by Snait B.
    [Show full text]
  • Natural Necessity Natural Selection
    NATURAL SELECTION NATURAL NECESSITY See Laws of Nature NATURAL SELECTION In modern evolutionary biology, a set of objects is Adaptationism said to experience a selection process precisely when At the close of his introduction to those objects vary in/itness (see Fitness). For exam­ On the Origin oj' ple, if zebras that run fast are fitter than zehras that Species, Darwin [1859] 1964, 6 says that natural selection is "the main but not the exclusive" cause run slow (perhaps because faster zebras are better ofevolution. In reaction to misinterpretations ofhis able to avoid lion predation), a selection process is theory, Darwin felt compelled to reemphasize, in the set in motion. If the trait that exhibits variation hook's last edition, that there was more to evolution in fit~ess is heritable-meaning, in our example, that faster parents tend to have faster offspring than natural selection. It remains a matter of con­ troversy in evolutionary biology how important and slower parents tend to have slower offspring­ then the selection process is apt to chancre trait natural selection has been in the history of life. frequencies in the population, leading fitte';. traits This is the poinl of biological substance that pres­ to increase in frequency and less fit traits to decline ently divides adaptationists and anti-adaptationists. The debate over adaptationism also has a separate (Lewontin 1970). This change is the one that selec­ tion is "apt" to engender, rather than the one that methodological dimension, with critics insisting that adaptive hypotheses be tested more rigorously must occur, because evolutionary theory describes <Gould and Lewontin 1979; Sober 1993).
    [Show full text]
  • The Origin of Historical Kinds in Biology and Culture Günter P. Wagne
    Preprints (www.preprints.org) | NOT PEER-REVIEWED | Posted: 24 April 2019 doi:10.20944/preprints201904.0266.v1 Extending the Explanatory Scope of Evolutionary Theory: The Origin of Historical Kinds in Biology and Culture Günter P. Wagner and Gary Tomlinson Yale University Abstract Since its inception, evolutionary theory has experienced a number of extensions. The most important of these took the forms of the Modern Evolutionary Synthesis (MES), embracing genetics and population biology in the early 20th century, and the Extended Evolutionary Synthesis (EES) of the last thirty years, embracing, among other factors, non-genetic forms of inheritance. While we appreciate the motivation for this recent extension, we argue that it does not go far enough, since it restricts itself to widening explanations of adaptation by adding mechanisms of inheritance and variation. A more thoroughgoing extension is needed, one that widens the explanatory scope of evolutionary theory. In addition to adaptation and its various mechanisms, evolutionary theory must recognize as a distinct intellectual challenge the origin of what we call “historical kinds.” Under historical kinds we include any process that acquires a quasi-independent and traceable lineage-history in biological and cultural evolution. We develop the notion of a historical kind in a series of paradigmatic exemplars, from genes and homologues to rituals and music, and we propose a preliminary characterization. Keywords: historical individuals, extended evolutionary synthesis, evolutionary innovation, culture 1. Introduction For the last several decades, a set of concerns has exerted increasing pressure on the modern evolutionary synthesis (MES) of the mid-twentieth century, with the goal of widening the explanatory powers of evolutionary theory.
    [Show full text]
  • Soft Inheritance: Challenging the Modern Synthesis
    Genetics and Molecular Biology, 31, 2, 389-395 (2008) Copyright © 2008, Sociedade Brasileira de Genética. Printed in Brazil www.sbg.org.br Review Article Soft inheritance: Challenging the Modern Synthesis Eva Jablonka1 and Marion J. Lamb2 1The Cohn Institute for the History and Philosophy of Science and Ideas, Tel-Aviv University, Tel-Aviv, Israel. 211 Fernwood, Clarence Road, London, United Kingdom. Abstract This paper presents some of the recent challenges to the Modern Synthesis of evolutionary theory, which has domi- nated evolutionary thinking for the last sixty years. The focus of the paper is the challenge of soft inheritance - the idea that variations that arise during development can be inherited. There is ample evidence showing that phenotypic variations that are independent of variations in DNA sequence, and targeted DNA changes that are guided by epigenetic control systems, are important sources of hereditary variation, and hence can contribute to evolutionary changes. Furthermore, under certain conditions, the mechanisms underlying epigenetic inheritance can also lead to saltational changes that reorganize the epigenome. These discoveries are clearly incompatible with the tenets of the Modern Synthesis, which denied any significant role for Lamarckian and saltational processes. In view of the data that support soft inheritance, as well as other challenges to the Modern Synthesis, it is concluded that that synthesis no longer offers a satisfactory theoretical framework for evolutionary biology. Key words: epigenetic inheritance, hereditary variation, Lamarckism, macroevolution, microevolution. Received: March 18, 2008; Accepted: March 19, 2008. Introduction 1. Heredity occurs through the transmission of germ- There are winds of change in evolutionary biology, line genes.
    [Show full text]
  • The Physics of Wind-Blown Sand and Dust
    The physics of wind-blown sand and dust Jasper F. Kok1, Eric J. R. Parteli2,3, Timothy I. Michaels4, and Diana Bou Karam5 1Department of Earth and Atmospheric Sciences, Cornell University, Ithaca, NY, USA 2Departamento de Física, Universidade Federal do Ceará, Fortaleza, Ceará, Brazil 3Institute for Multiscale Simulation, Universität Erlangen-Nürnberg, Erlangen, Germany 4Southwest Research Institute, Boulder, CO USA 5LATMOS, IPSL, Université Pierre et Marie Curie, CNRS, Paris, France Email: [email protected] Abstract. The transport of sand and dust by wind is a potent erosional force, creates sand dunes and ripples, and loads the atmosphere with suspended dust aerosols. This article presents an extensive review of the physics of wind-blown sand and dust on Earth and Mars. Specifically, we review the physics of aeolian saltation, the formation and development of sand dunes and ripples, the physics of dust aerosol emission, the weather phenomena that trigger dust storms, and the lifting of dust by dust devils and other small- scale vortices. We also discuss the physics of wind-blown sand and dune formation on Venus and Titan. PACS: 47.55.Kf, 92.60.Mt, 92.40.Gc, 45.70.Qj, 45.70.Mg, 45.70.-n, 96.30.Gc, 96.30.Ea, 96.30.nd Journal Reference: Kok J F, Parteli E J R, Michaels T I and Bou Karam D 2012 The physics of wind- blown sand and dust Rep. Prog. Phys. 75 106901. 1 Table of Contents 1. Introduction .......................................................................................................................................................... 4 1.1 Modes of wind-blown particle transport ...................................................................................................... 4 1.2 Importance of wind-blown sand and dust to the Earth and planetary sciences ...........................................
    [Show full text]
  • The Case for Saltational Events in Human Evolution
    The Case for Saltational Events in Human Evolution IAN TATTERSALL Summary. Evolutionary saltation is a rather ill-defined Victorian concept that may contrast in various ways with gradual (linear) evolution. In comparing evolutionary modes it is thus more pro- ductive to bear in mind the difference between ‘transformational’ and ‘taxic’ mindsets, each of which sharply influences the way in which the evolutionary record is interpreted. It is also important to recognise the fact that, even under traditional notions of natural selection, we cannot think of the evolutionary process as one of fine-tuning the myriad systems that make up each individual and each taxon. Both individuals and species thrive or fail reproduc- tively as the sums of their parts, not as the bearers of multiple fea- tures that can somehow be tracked independently of each other over vast spans of time. In this review I look at the human morpho- logical and behavioural records in an attempt to discern pattern in human evolution, and particularly in the emergence of our own species, Homo sapiens, as narrowly defined. Homo sapiens is a vari- able species, although not notably more so than Homo nean- derthalensis, which can itself be understood only in the context of its membership in a diverse clade of endemic European species. The record clearly indicates that both modern human morphology and modern human cognitive processes appeared rather suddenly, even saltationally, although not at the same time. INTRODUCTION I HAVE BEEN ASKED TO SPEAK at this Symposium about saltation and the evidence for it in the human evolutionary record.
    [Show full text]
  • Generating and Filtering Major Phenotypic Novelties: Neogoldschmidtian Saltation Revisited
    Chapter 7 Generating and filtering major phenotypic novelties: neoGoldschmidtian saltation revisited Richard N\. Bateman and William A. D/M/che/e ABSTRACT Further developing a controversial neoGoldschmidtian paradigm that we first pub- lished in 1994, we here narrowly define saltational evolution as a genetic modifica- tion that is expressed as a profound phenotypic change across a single generation and results in a potentially independent evolutionary lineage termed a prospecies (the 'hopeful monster' of Richard Goldschmidt). Of several saltational and parasaltational mechanisms previously discussed by us, the most directly relevant to evolutionary-developmental genetics is dichotomous saltation, which is driven by mutation within a single ancestral Uneage. It can result not only in instantaneous speciation but also in the simultaneous origin of a profound phenotypic novelty more likely to be treated as a new supraspecific taxon. Saltational events form unusually long branches on morphological phylogenies, which follow a punctuated equilibrium pattern, but at the time of origin they typically form zero length branches on the contrastingly gradualistic molecular phylogenies. Our chosen case- studies of heterotopy (including homeosis) and heterochrony in fossil seed-ferns and extant orchids indicate that vast numbers of prospecies are continuously generated by mutation of key developmental genes that control morphogenesis. First principles suggest that, although higher plant mutants are more likely to become established than higher animals, the fitness of even plant prospecies is in at least most cases too low to survive competition-mediated selection. The establishment of prospecies is most Hkely under temporary release from selection in environments of low biotic competition for resources, followed by honing to competitive fitness by gradual rein- troduction to neoDarwinian selection.
    [Show full text]
  • On Species Concepts, Phylogenetics and the Science of Natural History— Three Current Issues Facing Taxonomy
    Megataxa 001 (1): 067–072 ISSN 2703-3082 (print edition) https://www.mapress.com/j/mt/ MEGATAXA Copyright © 2020 Magnolia Press Correspondence ISSN 2703-3090 (online edition) https://doi.org/10.11646/megataxa.1.1.14 On species concepts, phylogenetics and the science of natural history— three current issues facing taxonomy MAARTEN J. M. CHRISTENHUSZ Curtin University, Perth, Australia / Plant Gateway, UK [email protected]; https://orcid.org/0000-0003-1398-8743 Taxonomy faces some major challenges in the 21st particular important traits, both leaving “gaps”, genetic or Century (Godfray 2002). The threat to biodiversity comes morphological/ecological. largely from human overpopulation, but the impact of The concept of genus and species originated from climate change is unprecedented (Pievani 2014) and the logic of Greek philosopher Aristotle, but these ideas increasingly a risk factor for many species. This makes were introduced to biology through works of Bauhin it even more critical to rapidly catalogue our biodiversity (1596), Ray (1686) and contemporaries. However, it to better protect it (Mace 2004). If you do not know what was not before these were widely applied by Linnaeus is there, it is impossible to know what we are losing, let (1736), forming the basis of the binomial nomenclatural alone protect something for which we have no name and system, that species became the biological working entity cannot identify. Understanding diversity and the dynamics (Svenson 1953). A plethora of species concepts have been of evolution and speciation is important to discover the proposed in the past (Wheeler & Meier 2000; De Queiroz adaptability of species in a changing world dominated by 1998; 2007), but none defines what a species is across all humans (e.g.
    [Show full text]
  • Evolutionary Dynamics of Speciation and Extinction
    Scholars' Mine Doctoral Dissertations Student Theses and Dissertations Fall 2015 Evolutionary dynamics of speciation and extinction Dawn Michelle King Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarsmine.mst.edu/doctoral_dissertations Part of the Biophysics Commons Department: Physics Recommended Citation King, Dawn Michelle, "Evolutionary dynamics of speciation and extinction" (2015). Doctoral Dissertations. 2464. https://scholarsmine.mst.edu/doctoral_dissertations/2464 This thesis is brought to you by Scholars' Mine, a service of the Missouri S&T Library and Learning Resources. This work is protected by U. S. Copyright Law. Unauthorized use including reproduction for redistribution requires the permission of the copyright holder. For more information, please contact [email protected]. 1 EVOLUTIONARY DYNAMICS OF SPECIATION AND EXTINCTION by DAWN MICHELLE KING A DISSERTATION Presented to the Faculty of the Graduate Faculty of the MISSOURI UNIVERSITY OF SCIENCE AND TECHNOLOGY and UNIVERSITY OF MISSOURI AT SAINT LOUIS In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY in PHYSICS 2015 Approved by: Sonya Bahar, Advisor Ricardo Flores Nevena Marić Paul Parris Thomas Vojta 1 iii ABSTRACT Presented here is an interdisciplinary study that draws connections between the fields of physics, mathematics, and evolutionary biology. Importantly, as we move through the Anthropocene Epoch, where human-driven climate change threatens biodiversity, understanding how an evolving population responds to extinction stress could be key to saving endangered ecosystems. With a neutral, agent-based model that incorporates the main principles of Darwinian evolution, such as heritability, variability, and competition, the dynamics of speciation and extinction is investigated. The simulated organisms evolve according to the reaction-diffusion rules of the 2D directed percolation universality class.
    [Show full text]
  • Why Was Darwin's View of Species Rejected by Twentieth Century
    Biol Philos (2010) 25:497–527 DOI 10.1007/s10539-010-9213-7 Why was Darwin’s view of species rejected by twentieth century biologists? James Mallet Published online: 1 May 2010 Ó Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2010 Abstract Historians and philosophers of science agree that Darwin had an understanding of species which led to a workable theory of their origins. To Darwin species did not differ essentially from ‘varieties’ within species, but were distin- guishable in that they had developed gaps in formerly continuous morphological variation. Similar ideas can be defended today after updating them with modern population genetics. Why then, in the 1930s and 1940s, did Dobzhansky, Mayr and others argue that Darwin failed to understand species and speciation? Mayr and Dobzhansky argued that reproductively isolated species were more distinct and ‘real’ than Darwin had proposed. Believing species to be inherently cohesive, Mayr inferred that speciation normally required geographic isolation, an argument that he believed, incorrectly, Darwin had failed to appreciate. Also, before the sociobiology revolution of the 1960s and 1970s, biologists often argued that traits beneficial to whole populations would spread. Reproductive isolation was thus seen as an adaptive trait to prevent disintegration of species. Finally, molecular genetic markers did not exist, and so a presumed biological function of species, repro- ductive isolation, seemed to delimit cryptic species better than character-based criteria like Darwin’s. Today, abundant genetic markers are available and widely used to delimit species, for example using assignment tests: genetics has replaced a Darwinian reliance on morphology for detecting gaps between species.
    [Show full text]
  • Alternative Adaptations, Speciation, and Phylogeny
    Proc. Nati. Acad. Sci. USA Vol. 83, pp. 1388-1392, March 1986 Evolution Alternative adaptations, speciation, and phylogeny (A Review) (polymorphism/epigenetlc plasticity/macroevolutlon/punctuated equilibria/regulatory evolution) MARY JANE WEST-EBERHARD* Smithsonian Tropical Research Institute, Balboa, Panama Communicated by Charles D. Michener, October 15, 1985 ABSTRACT Alternative adaptations-different adaptive Alternative adaptations are different, often complex, phenotypes maintained in the same life stage and the same evolved phenotypes occurring in the same lifestage and the population but not necessarily simultaneously expressed in the same population but not necessarily simultaneously ex- same individual-represent contrasting character sets pro- pressed in the same individual. [When "adaptation" sensu duced by the same genome, in effect allowing a single species Williams (5) is not applicable or intended I will use the more to occupy more than one sympatric niche. Such alternatives are general words "phenotype" or "form."] Examples are particularly likely to give rise to novel adaptations because of familiar to everyone. They include the "workers" and selection for extreme dissimilarity between them and because "queens" of social insects (6); males and females of sexually established traits buffer populations against extinction while reproducing species; and the contrasting morphs of batesian independently expressed alternatives evolve in new directions. mimics in butterflies (7). The particular phenotype expressed Particular alternatives can be suddenly fixed in populations in a given individual or at a given time depends on the state with little or no genetic change, leading to a period of rapid of a regulatory ("switch") mechanism, which can be either evolution (especially, of morphology) exaggerating the charac- condition-sensitive or genetic (allelic, chromosomal, or a teristics of the newly fixed form.
    [Show full text]
  • Hybrid Speciation
    Vol 446j15 March 2007jdoi:10.1038/nature05706 REVIEWS Hybrid speciation James Mallet1 Botanists have long believed that hybrid speciation is important, especially after chromosomal doubling (allopolyploidy). Until recently, hybridization was not thought to play a very constructive part in animal evolution. Now, new genetic evidence suggests that hybrid speciation, even without polyploidy, is more common in plants and also animals than we thought. innaeus stated in Systema Naturae that species have remained esculenta is a well known example: it is heterozygous for complete unchanged since the dawn of time, but he later experimented Rana lessonae and Rana ridibunda genomes16. Here, I exclude hybri- with hybrids and convinced himself that hybridization pro- dogenetic species because they do not breed true. vided a means of species modification. One hundred and L 1 eighty years later, Lotsy still argued that species were invariant Theory and background of hybrid speciation genetic types, and that novel lineages could evolve only by means Hybridization may be ‘‘the grossest blunder in sexual preference of hybridization. These peculiar ideas were overturned when the which we can conceive of an animal making’’17, but it is nonetheless concept emerged of species as reproductively isolated populations2–4. a regular event. The fraction of species that hybridize is variable, but In zoology, this concept discouraged the view that hybridization and on average around 10% of animal and 25% of plant species are gene flow (introgression) between species could be important evolu- known to hybridize with at least one other species18. Hybridization 2,5,6 tionary forces , even while botanists continued to argue for their is especially prevalent in rapidly radiating groups: 75% of British 4,7,8 significance .
    [Show full text]