An ∞-Category? Jacob Lurie

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

An ∞-Category? Jacob Lurie WHAT IS... ? an ∞-Category? Jacob Lurie ∗ One of the most celebrated invariants in alge- map f : Singn X → Singm X, given by composition braic topology is the fundamental group : given with a linear map of simplices ∆m → ∆n. For exam- a topological space X with a base point x, the ple, if we take f : {0, 1,...,n − 1}→{0, 1,...,n} fundamental group π1(X, x) is defined to be the to be the injective map that omits the value i, set of paths in X from x to itself, taken modulo then we obtain a map di : Singn X → Singn−1 X, homotopy. If we do not want to choose abasepoint which carries an n-simplex of X to its ith face. x ∈ X, we can consider instead the fundamental The simplicial set Sing X is sometimes called the groupoid π≤1X: this is a category whose objects singular complex of the topological space X. are the points of X, in which morphisms are given It turns out that the answer to question (B) is by paths between points (again taken modulo ho- “essentially everything”, at least to an algebraic motopy). The fundamental groupoid of X contains topologist. More precisely, we can use the singular slightly more information than the fundamental complex Sing X to construct a topological space group of X: it determines the set of path com- that is (weakly) homotopy equivalent to the origi- ponents π X (these are the isomorphism classes 0 nal space X. Consequently, no information is lost of objects in π X) and also the fundamental ≤1 by discarding the original space X and working group of each component (the fundamental group directly with the simplicial set Sing X. In fact, it is π (X, x) is the automorphism group of x in the 1 possible to develop the theory of algebraic topolo- category π X). The language of category theory ≤1 gy in entirely combinatorial terms, using simplicial allows us to package this information together in sets as surrogates for topological spaces. However, a very convenient form. not every simplicial set S behaves like the singular The fundamental groupoid π≤1X does not con- tain any information about the higher homotopy complex of a space; it is therefore necessary to single out a class of “good” simplicial sets to groups {πn(X, x)}n≥2. In order to recover infor- mation of this sort, it is useful to consider not work with. For this, we need to introduce a bit of only points and paths in X, but also the set of terminology. ∆n Let S = {Sn}n≥0 be a simplicial set. Here we continuous maps Singn X = Hom( , X) for ev- ery nonnegative integer n; here ∆n denotes the imagine that Sn denotes the set of all continuous n topological n-simplex. This raises three questions: maps from an n-simplex ∆ into a topological (A) What kind of a mathematical object is the space X, although such a space need not exist. For 0 ≤ i ≤ n, we define another set Λn(S), which we collection of sets {Sing X}n≥0? i n ∆n (B) How much does this object know about X? think of as a set of partially defined maps from (C) To what extent does this object behave into X: namely, maps whose domain consists of all n like a category? faces of ∆ that contain the ith vertex (this subset ∆n To address question (A), we note that Sing X = of is sometimes called an i-horn). Formally, we Λn define i (S) to be the collection of all sequences {Singn X}n≥0 has the structure of a simplicial set. That is, for every nondecreasing function f : {σj }0≤j≤n,j≠i of elements of Sn−1, which “fit togeth- {0, 1,...,m}→{0, 1,...,n}, there is an induced er” in the following sense: if 0 ≤ j < k ≤ n and j ≠ i ≠ k, then dj σk = dk−1σj ∈ Sn−2. There is a Λn Jacob Lurie is professor of mathematics at the Mas- restriction map Sn → i (S), given by the formula sachusetts Institute of Technology. His email address is τ ֏ (d0τ, d1τ,...,di−1τ, di+1τ,...dnτ). [email protected]. September 2008 Notices of the AMS 949 Definition 1. A simplicial set S ={Sn}n≥0 is a Kan category. The objects of S are the elements of S0, Λn complex if the map Sn → i (S) is surjective for all and the morphisms of S are the elements of S1. 0 ≤ i ≤ n. Suppose we are given two morphisms f , g ∈ S1 that are “composable” (that is, the source of g co- In other words, S is a Kan complex if every horn incides with the target of f ), as depicted in the fol- σ ∈ Λn(S) can be “filled” to an n-simplex of S. i lowing diagram Roughly speaking, a Kan complex is a simplicial set that resembles the singular complex of a topo- y logical space. In particular, the singular complex f g Sing X of a topological space X is always a Kan h complex. x z. We now address question (C): in what sense does the singular complex Sing X behave like a The morphisms f and g determine a horn σ0 ∈ category? To answer this, we observe that there is Λ2 1(S). If S is an ∞-category, then this horn can be a close connection between categories and simpli- filled to obtain a 2-simplex σ ∈ S2. We can then cial sets. For every category C and every integer define a new morphism h : x → z by passing to a n ≥ 0, let Cn denote the set of all composable face of σ ; this morphism can be viewed as a com- chains of morphisms position of g and f . The 2-simplex σ is generally = ◦ C0 → C1 → ... → Cn not unique, so that the composition h g f is not unambigiously defined. However, one can use the of length n. The collection of sets {C } has the n n≥0 horn-filling conditions of Definition 3 (for n > 2) structure of a simplicial set, which is called the to show that h is well-defined “up to homotopy”. nerve of the category C, and it determines C up This turns out to be good enough: there is a robust to isomorphism. For example, the objects of C are theory of ∞-categories, which contains generaliza- simply the elements of C , and the morphisms in 0 tions of most of the basic ideas of category theory C are the elements of C . 1 (limits and colimits, adjoint functors, ...). We may therefore view the notion of a simplicial Definition 3 is really only a first step towards a set as a generalization of the notion of a category. much more ambitious generalization of classical How drastic is this generalization? In other words, category theory: the theory of higher categories. how can we tell if a simplicial set arises as the One can think of ∞-categories as higher categories nerve of a category? The following result provides in which every k-morphism is required to be in- an answer: vertible for k > 1. = { } Proposition 2. Let S Sn n≥0 be a simplicial set. Example 5. For every topological space X, the C Then S is isomorphic to the nerve of a category if singular complex Sing X is an ∞-category. Since → Λn and only if, for each 0 <i<n, the map Sn i (S) Sing X determines the space X up to (weak) bijective. homotopy equivalence, we can view the theory The hypothesis of Proposition 2 resembles the of ∞-categories as a generalization of classical definition of a Kan complex but is different in homotopy theory. two important respects. Definition 1 requires that Examples 4 and 5 together convey the spirit ∈ Λn every horn σ i (S) can be filled to an n-simplex of the subject: the theory of ∞-categories can of S. Proposition 2 requires this condition only in be viewed as a combination of category theo- the case 0 <i<n but demands that the n-simplex ry and homotopy theory and has the flavor of be unique. Neither condition implies the other, but both. Where classical category theory provides they admit a common generalization: a language for the study of algebraic structures Definition 3. A simplicial set S is an ∞-category (groups, rings, vector spaces, ...), the theory of Λn ∞-categories provides an analogous language for if, for each 0 <i<n, the map Sn → i (S) is surjective. describing their homotopy-theoretic counterparts (loop spaces, ring spectra, chain complexes, ...). The notion of an ∞-category was originally The power of this language is only beginning to introduced (under the name weak Kan complex) be exploited. by Boardman and Vogt, in their work on homo- topy invariant algebraic structures (see [1]). The Further Reading theory has subsequently been developed more ex- [1] J. M. Boardman and R. M. Vogt, Homotopy In- tensively by Joyal (who refers to ∞-categories as variant Structures on Topological Spaces, Lecture quasicategories); a good reference is [2]. Notes in Mathematics 347, Springer-Verlag, Berlin and New York, 1973. Example 4. Let C be a category. Then the nerve [2] A. Joyal, Quasi-categories and Kan complexes, {C } ∞ C n n≥0 is an -category, which determines up Journal of Pure and Applied Algebra 175 (2002), to isomorphism. Consequently, we can think of an 207-222. ∞-category S = {Sn}n≥0 as a kind of generalized 950 Notices of the AMS Volume 55, Number 8.
Recommended publications
  • A Few Points in Topos Theory
    A few points in topos theory Sam Zoghaib∗ Abstract This paper deals with two problems in topos theory; the construction of finite pseudo-limits and pseudo-colimits in appropriate sub-2-categories of the 2-category of toposes, and the definition and construction of the fundamental groupoid of a topos, in the context of the Galois theory of coverings; we will take results on the fundamental group of étale coverings in [1] as a starting example for the latter. We work in the more general context of bounded toposes over Set (instead of starting with an effec- tive descent morphism of schemes). Questions regarding the existence of limits and colimits of diagram of toposes arise while studying this prob- lem, but their general relevance makes it worth to study them separately. We expose mainly known constructions, but give some new insight on the assumptions and work out an explicit description of a functor in a coequalizer diagram which was as far as the author is aware unknown, which we believe can be generalised. This is essentially an overview of study and research conducted at dpmms, University of Cambridge, Great Britain, between March and Au- gust 2006, under the supervision of Martin Hyland. Contents 1 Introduction 2 2 General knowledge 3 3 On (co)limits of toposes 6 3.1 The construction of finite limits in BTop/S ............ 7 3.2 The construction of finite colimits in BTop/S ........... 9 4 The fundamental groupoid of a topos 12 4.1 The fundamental group of an atomic topos with a point . 13 4.2 The fundamental groupoid of an unpointed locally connected topos 15 5 Conclusion and future work 17 References 17 ∗e-mail: [email protected] 1 1 Introduction Toposes were first conceived ([2]) as kinds of “generalised spaces” which could serve as frameworks for cohomology theories; that is, mapping topological or geometrical invariants with an algebraic structure to topological spaces.
    [Show full text]
  • Picard Groupoids and $\Gamma $-Categories
    PICARD GROUPOIDS AND Γ-CATEGORIES AMIT SHARMA Abstract. In this paper we construct a symmetric monoidal closed model category of coherently commutative Picard groupoids. We construct another model category structure on the category of (small) permutative categories whose fibrant objects are (permutative) Picard groupoids. The main result is that the Segal’s nerve functor induces a Quillen equivalence between the two aforementioned model categories. Our main result implies the classical result that Picard groupoids model stable homotopy one-types. Contents 1. Introduction 2 2. The Setup 4 2.1. Review of Permutative categories 4 2.2. Review of Γ- categories 6 2.3. The model category structure of groupoids on Cat 7 3. Two model category structures on Perm 12 3.1. ThemodelcategorystructureofPermutativegroupoids 12 3.2. ThemodelcategoryofPicardgroupoids 15 4. The model category of coherently commutatve monoidal groupoids 20 4.1. The model category of coherently commutative monoidal groupoids 24 5. Coherently commutative Picard groupoids 27 6. The Quillen equivalences 30 7. Stable homotopy one-types 36 Appendix A. Some constructions on categories 40 AppendixB. Monoidalmodelcategories 42 Appendix C. Localization in model categories 43 Appendix D. Tranfer model structure on locally presentable categories 46 References 47 arXiv:2002.05811v2 [math.CT] 12 Mar 2020 Date: Dec. 14, 2019. 1 2 A. SHARMA 1. Introduction Picard groupoids are interesting objects both in topology and algebra. A major reason for interest in topology is because they classify stable homotopy 1-types which is a classical result appearing in various parts of the literature [JO12][Pat12][GK11]. The category of Picard groupoids is the archetype exam- ple of a 2-Abelian category, see [Dup08].
    [Show full text]
  • INTRODUCTION to ALGEBRAIC TOPOLOGY 1 Category And
    INTRODUCTION TO ALGEBRAIC TOPOLOGY (UPDATED June 2, 2020) SI LI AND YU QIU CONTENTS 1 Category and Functor 2 Fundamental Groupoid 3 Covering and fibration 4 Classification of covering 5 Limit and colimit 6 Seifert-van Kampen Theorem 7 A Convenient category of spaces 8 Group object and Loop space 9 Fiber homotopy and homotopy fiber 10 Exact Puppe sequence 11 Cofibration 12 CW complex 13 Whitehead Theorem and CW Approximation 14 Eilenberg-MacLane Space 15 Singular Homology 16 Exact homology sequence 17 Barycentric Subdivision and Excision 18 Cellular homology 19 Cohomology and Universal Coefficient Theorem 20 Hurewicz Theorem 21 Spectral sequence 22 Eilenberg-Zilber Theorem and Kunneth¨ formula 23 Cup and Cap product 24 Poincare´ duality 25 Lefschetz Fixed Point Theorem 1 1 CATEGORY AND FUNCTOR 1 CATEGORY AND FUNCTOR Category In category theory, we will encounter many presentations in terms of diagrams. Roughly speaking, a diagram is a collection of ‘objects’ denoted by A, B, C, X, Y, ··· , and ‘arrows‘ between them denoted by f , g, ··· , as in the examples f f1 A / B X / Y g g1 f2 h g2 C Z / W We will always have an operation ◦ to compose arrows. The diagram is called commutative if all the composite paths between two objects ultimately compose to give the same arrow. For the above examples, they are commutative if h = g ◦ f f2 ◦ f1 = g2 ◦ g1. Definition 1.1. A category C consists of 1◦. A class of objects: Obj(C) (a category is called small if its objects form a set). We will write both A 2 Obj(C) and A 2 C for an object A in C.
    [Show full text]
  • Directed Homotopy Hypothesis'. (,1)-Categories
    Steps towards a `directed homotopy hypothesis'. (1; 1)-categories, directed spaces and perhaps rewriting Steps towards a `directed homotopy hypothesis'. (1; 1)-categories, directed spaces and perhaps rewriting Timothy Porter Emeritus Professor, University of Wales, Bangor June 12, 2015 Steps towards a `directed homotopy hypothesis'. (1; 1)-categories, directed spaces and perhaps rewriting 1 Introduction. Some history and background Grothendieck on 1-groupoids `Homotopy hypothesis' Dwyer-Kan loop groupoid 2 From directed spaces to S-categories and quasicategories A `dHH' for directed homotopy? Some reminders, terminology, notation, etc. Singular simplicial traces Suggestions on how to use T~ (X ) Models for (1; 1)-categories Quasi-categories 3 Back to d-spaces 4 Questions and `things to do' Steps towards a `directed homotopy hypothesis'. (1; 1)-categories, directed spaces and perhaps rewriting Introduction. Some history and background Some history (1; 0)-categories, spaces and rewriting. Letters from Grothendieck to Larry Breen (1975). Letter from AG to Quillen, [4], in 1983, forming the very first part of `Pursuing Stacks', [5], pages 13 to 17 of the original scanned file. Letter from TP to AG (16/06/1983). Steps towards a `directed homotopy hypothesis'. (1; 1)-categories, directed spaces and perhaps rewriting Introduction. Grothendieck on 1-groupoids Grothendieck on 1-groupoids (from PS) At first sight, it seemed to me that the Bangor group had indeed come to work out (quite independently) one basic intuition of the program I had envisaged in those letters to Larry Breen { namely the study of n-truncated homotopy types (of semi-simplicial sets, or of topological spaces) was essentially equivalent to the study of so-called n-groupoids (where n is a natural integer).
    [Show full text]
  • Groupoids, the Phragmen-Brouwer Property, and the Jordan Curve
    Groupoids, the Phragmen-Brouwer Property, and the Jordan Curve Theorem Ronald Brown University of Wales, Bangor∗ February 2, 2008 Abstract We publicise a proof of the Jordan Curve Theorem which relates it to the Phragmen-Brouwer Property, and whose proof uses the van Kampen theorem for the fundamental groupoid on a set of base points. 1 Introduction This article extracts from [Bro88] a proof of the Jordan Curve Theorem based on the use of groupoids, the van Kampen Theorem for the fundamental groupoid on a set of base points, and the use of the Phragmen-Brouwer Property. In the process, we give short proofs of two results on the Phragmen- Brouwer Property (Propositions 4.1, 4.3). There is a renewed interest in such classical results1, as shown in the article [Sie] which revisits proofs of the Schoenflies Theorem. There are many books containing a further discussion of this area. For more on the Phragmen- Brouwer property, see [Why42] and [Wil49]. Wilder lists five other properties which he shows for a connected and locally connected metric space are each equivalent to the PBP. The proof we give of the Jordan Curve Theorem is adapted from [Mun75]. Because he does not have our van Kampen theorem for non-connected spaces, he is forced into rather special covering space arguments to prove his replacements for Corollary 3.5 (which is originally due to Eilenberg [Eil37]), and for Proposition arXiv:math/0607229v1 [math.AT] 9 Jul 2006 4.1. The intention is to make these methods more widely available, since the 1988 edition of the book [Bro88] has been out of print for at least ten years, and the new edition is only just now available.
    [Show full text]
  • Note on the Gluing Theorem for Groupoids and Van Kampen's
    CAHIERS DE TOPOLOGIE ET GÉOMÉTRIE DIFFÉRENTIELLE CATÉGORIQUES KLAUS HEINER KAMPS Note on the gluing theorem for groupoids and Van Kampen’s theorem Cahiers de topologie et géométrie différentielle catégoriques, tome 28, no 4 (1987), p. 303-306 <http://www.numdam.org/item?id=CTGDC_1987__28_4_303_0> © Andrée C. Ehresmann et les auteurs, 1987, tous droits réservés. L’accès aux archives de la revue « Cahiers de topologie et géométrie différentielle catégoriques » implique l’accord avec les conditions générales d’utilisation (http://www.numdam.org/conditions). Toute utilisation commerciale ou impression systématique est constitutive d’une infraction pénale. Toute copie ou impression de ce fichier doit contenir la présente mention de copyright. Article numérisé dans le cadre du programme Numérisation de documents anciens mathématiques http://www.numdam.org/ CAHIERS DE TOPOLOGIE Vol. XXVIII-4 (1987) ET GÉOMÉTRIE DIFFÉPRENTIELLE CATEGORI QUES NOTE ON THE GLUING THEOREM FOR GROUPOIDS AND VAN KAMPEN’S THEOREM by Klaus Heiner KAMPS RÉSUMÉ. Le but de cette note est de montrer que le Théorème de van Kampen classique pour le groupe fondamental d’une union d’espaces peut 6tre d6duit du Théorème de van Kampen g6n6ral pour le gr-oupoi*de fondamental dans 121 (voir aussi (61) en appliquant le théorème de recollement pour les groupoides qui est un cas particulier d’un théarème g6n6ral de recollement en théorie de 1’homotopie abstraite (voir [7, 8]). The following classical van Kampen Theorem determines under suitable local conditions the fundamental group n1(X,xo) of a topo- logical space X at xo e X, when X is the union of two subspaces.
    [Show full text]
  • A Whirlwind Tour of the World of (∞,1)-Categories
    Contemporary Mathematics A Whirlwind Tour of the World of (1; 1)-categories Omar Antol´ınCamarena Abstract. This introduction to higher category theory is intended to a give the reader an intuition for what (1; 1)-categories are, when they are an appro- priate tool, how they fit into the landscape of higher category, how concepts from ordinary category theory generalize to this new setting, and what uses people have put the theory to. It is a rough guide to a vast terrain, focuses on ideas and motivation, omits almost all proofs and technical details, and provides many references. Contents 1. Introduction 2 2. The idea of higher category theory 3 2.1. The homotopy hypothesis and the problem with strictness 5 2.2. The 3-type of S2 8 2.3. Shapes for cells 10 2.4. What does (higher) category theory do for us? 11 3. Models of (1; 1)-categories 12 3.1. Topological or simplicial categories 12 3.2. Quasi-categories 13 3.3. Segal categories and complete Segal spaces 16 3.4. Relative categories 17 3.5. A1-categories 18 3.6. Models of subclasses of (1; 1)-categories 20 3.6.1. Model categories 20 3.6.2. Derivators 21 3.6.3. dg-categories, A1-categories 22 4. The comparison problem 22 4.1. Axiomatization 24 5. Basic (1; 1)-category theory 25 5.1. Equivalences 25 5.1.1. Further results for quasi-categories 26 5.2. Limits and colimits 26 5.3. Adjunctions, monads and comonads 28 2010 Mathematics Subject Classification. Primary 18-01.
    [Show full text]
  • The Fundamental Localic Groupoid of a Topos
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Elsevier - Publisher Connector Journal of Pure and Applied Algebra 77 (1992) 67-86 67 North-Holland The fundamental localic groupoid of a topos John F. Kennison Department of Mathematics, Clark University*, Worcester, MA 01610, USA Communicated by M. Barr Received 2 January 1991 Revised 9 May 1991 Abstract Kennison, J.F., The fundamental localic groupoid of a topos, Journal of Pure and Applied Algebra 77 (1992) 67-86. If 8 is a connected Grothendieck topos, then there is a prodiscrete localic groupoid n which plays the role of the fundamental group of 8. There is a ‘universal torso? which is a geometric morphism from 8 to Ba, the topos of all continuous r-actions. n classifies torsors since a G-torsor of 8 corresponds to a uniformly continuous functor from r to G. (If ‘Z is locally connected all such continuous functors are automatically uniform.) When 8 is locally connected, and has a point, then r is equivalent to a localic group, otherwise a groupoid is needed. The topos 8 is equivalent to BX for X a fully prodiscrete localic groupoid iff 8 is locally connected and generated by its split (or by its locally trivial) objects. A technical aspect of this paper shows how to use a prodiscrete localic groupoid to represent a 2-diagram of groups. For example, each pro-group is representable (in a 2-categorical sense) by a prodiscrete localic groupoid. Some curious counter-examples arise by considering toposes of infinitesimal group actions.
    [Show full text]
  • Fundamental Groupoids As Generalised Pushouts of Codiscrete Groupoids
    FUNDAMENTAL GROUPOIDS AS GENERALISED PUSHOUTS OF CODISCRETE GROUPOIDS ETTORE CARLETTI AND MARCO GRANDIS Abstract. Every differentiable manifold X has a `good cover', where all open sets and their finite intersections are 1-connected (and even contractible). Using a generalised van Kampen theorem for open covers we deduce that the fundamental groupoid of X (or any space admitting such an open cover) is a `generalised pushout' of codiscrete groupoids and inclusions. This fact motivates the present brief study of generalised pushouts. In particular, we show that every groupoid is, up to equivalence, a generalised pushout of codiscrete subgroupoids; moreover, in any category, generalised pushouts amount to connected colimits, and - in the finite case - to ordinary pushouts and coequalisers. 1. Introduction This article starts from two facts. (a) A well-known groupoid-version of the van Kampen theorem, by R. Brown [Bw1, Bw2], determines the fundamental groupoid of a space X as a pushout of fundamental groupoids of (convenient) subspaces X1;X2; the latter (and their intersection!) are not supposed to be path-connected - a crucial advantage with respect to the classical formulation for the fundamental group. This groupoid version can be easily extended to an open cover (Xi)i2I of the space X: then the fundamental groupoid π1X is the `gluing' of the fundamental groupoids π1Xi `over' the groupoids π1(Xi \ Xj) - a colimit of a particular form, that is called here a `generalised pushout' (see Sections 2 to 4). We readily note that generalised pushouts are connected, non simply connected colimits and therefore cannot be reduced to ordinary pushouts (see R.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction
    COVERING GROUPS OF NON-CONNECTED TOPOLOGICAL GROUPS REVISITED Ronald Brown and Osman Mucuk School of Mathematics University of Wales Bangor, Gwynedd LL57 1UT, U.K. Received 11 March 1993 , Revision 31 May 1993 Published in Math. Proc. Camb. Phil. Soc, 115 (1994) 97-110. This version: 18 Dec. 2006, with some new references. Introduction All spaces are assumed to be locally path connected and semi-locally 1-connected. Let X be a con- nected topological group with identity e, and let p : X~ ! X be the universal cover of the underlying space of X. It follows easily from classical properties of lifting maps to covering spaces that for any pointe ~ in X~ with pe~ = e there is a unique structure of topological group on X~ such thate ~ is the identity and p: X~ ! X is a morphism of groups. We say that the structure of topological group on X lifts to X~. It is less generally appreciated that this result fails for the non-connected case. The set ¼0X of path components of X forms a non-trivial group which acts on the abelian group ¼1(X; e) via conjugation in X. R.L. Taylor [20] showed that the topological group X determines an obstruction class kX in 3 H (¼0X; ¼1(X; e)), and that the vanishing of kX is a necessary and su±cient condition for the lifting of the topological group structure on X to a universal covering so that the projection is a morphism. Further, recent work, for example Huebschmann [15], shows there are geometric applications of the non-connected case.
    [Show full text]
  • Cohomology to Logic and Back Toposes in Como 2018
    torsors fundamental group cohomology Cohomology to logic and back Toposes in Como 2018 Tibor Beke University of Massachusetts tibor [email protected] June 28, 2018 Tibor Beke Cohomology to logic and back torsors motivation fundamental group simplicial cohomology classical Spaces have I Euler characteristic I Betti numbers I homology groups I cohomology rings(!) I set of connected components I fundamental group I homotopy groups Which of these generalize to toposes? Why should they even generalize? Tibor Beke Cohomology to logic and back torsors motivation fundamental group simplicial cohomology classical Tibor Beke Cohomology to logic and back torsors motivation fundamental group simplicial cohomology classical Tibor Beke Cohomology to logic and back Challenge: can your favorite functor C! Topoi be extended to a 2-functor? For example, can the category of topological spaces (of schemes, etc) be turned into a 2-category compatibly with the functor X 7! Sh(X )(X 7! Sh(Xet´ ) etc)? torsors motivation fundamental group simplicial cohomology classical I the category of Grothendieck toposes and geometric morphisms is excellent for representing categories of `locally structured objects' I functors C! Topoi are seldom full (Topoi is not locally small!) I some of these functors are onto (up to isomorphism) on objects, allowing one to express Topoi as a localization of C I Topoi is a 2-category: given morphisms f ; g : E ! F, a 2-arrow is a natural transformation from f ∗ to g ∗. Tibor Beke Cohomology to logic and back torsors motivation fundamental group simplicial cohomology classical I the category of Grothendieck toposes and geometric morphisms is excellent for representing categories of `locally structured objects' I functors C! Topoi are seldom full (Topoi is not locally small!) I some of these functors are onto (up to isomorphism) on objects, allowing one to express Topoi as a localization of C I Topoi is a 2-category: given morphisms f ; g : E ! F, a 2-arrow is a natural transformation from f ∗ to g ∗.
    [Show full text]
  • Higher Gauge Theory – I
    Higher Gauge Theory { I John C. Baez joint work with: Toby Bartels, Alissa Crans, James Dolan, Aaron Lauda, Urs Schreiber, Danny Stevenson. Barrett Lectures Saturday April 29th, 2006 1 G 3+ f1 D f2 Notes and references at: http://math.ucr.edu/home/baez/barrett/ 1 The Big Idea Using n-categories, instead of starting with a set of things: ¢ ¡¢ ¡ ¦ ¥¦ ¥ ¤ £¤ £ we can now start with a category of things and processes: ¨ §¨ § © © or a 2-category of things, processes, and processes be- tween processes: ... and so on. 2 I'll illustrate this with examples from higher gauge the- ory. This describes not only how particles transform as they move along paths in spacetime: but also how strings transform as they trace out surfaces: ... and so on. Where ordinary gauge theory uses groups, which are special categories: higher gauge theory uses 2-groups: which are special 2-categories. Where ordinary gauge theory uses bundles, higher gauge theory uses 2-bundles. Everything gets ‘categorified’! But first let's back up a bit.... 3 The Fundamental Groupoid Defining the fundamental group of a space X requires us to pick a basepoint ∗ 2 X. This is a bit ad hoc, and no good when X has several components. Sometimes it's better to use the fundamental groupoid of X. This is the category Π1(X) where: • objects are points of X: •x • morphisms are homotopy classes of paths in X: γ x • ( • y We compose homotopy classes of paths in the obvious way. Composition is associative, and every point has an identity path 1x : x ! x.
    [Show full text]