432 Antis Loizides in a Letter to CH Pearson of May 10Th, 1865

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

432 Antis Loizides in a Letter to CH Pearson of May 10Th, 1865 432 book Reviews Antis Loizides John Stuart Mill’s Platonic Heritage. Happiness Through Character (Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, 2013), xxvi + 248 pp. $75.00. ISBN 9780739173930. In a letter to C.H. Pearson of May 10th, 1865 Henry Sidgwick stated that John Stuart Mill ‘from 1860-1865 or thereabouts . ruled England in the region of thought as very few men ever did’. Mill was in a way meant to become a public intellectual, considering his radical and reformist education, his early partici- pation in Utilitarian intellectual enterprises and the character of his own phi- losophy, which stressed the public aspects of intellectual activity: this aimed at the ‘improvement of mankind’, and Mill always interpreted the role of the phi- losopher as consisting in advancing the intellectual condition of the age by questioning common opinion and combating prejudice. This is all well known. Less known, although well documented in Mill’s writings, starting with his Autobiography, is the classical inspiration of his view of philosophy and the role of the philosopher, which can be traced back to Plato; or rather, to Mill’s interpretation of the Platonic Socrates and his mission. This important aspect of Mill’s thought is explored by Antis Loizides’ insightful and well-documented work, which investigates Mill’s complex ‘Platonic heritage’ in two respects: the actual influence of Plato’s philosophy on Mill’s thought as well as the role model exercised by Plato’s Socrates on Mill’s conception of the philosopher’s activity. In the first part of the book Loizides examines the reception and the use of the classics (Greek, and especially Athenian and Spartan history, philosophy, literature) in nineteenth century England. He correctly emphasizes the politi- cal uses of the classics, which were exploited both by reformist and conserva- tive thinkers in writings and public debates on educational and social reforms; special attention is devoted to the role in these debates of Bentham and James Mill, who stressed the importance of classical studies for moulding individu- als endowed with a critical mind. This conviction countered the widespread view that classical education served the purpose of enforcing and maintaining class division. One of the most interesting parts of the book concerns the use of Athenian history by British historians in the late eighteenth and early nine- teenth century. Prompted by fear of radical reforms in the wake of the French revolution, many British historians portrayed Athenian democracy as a radical form of government in which the people were manipulated by demagogues and swayed by the sophists – a tyrannical regime to which they opposed the mixed constitution of England. In this context Loizides shows very well the importance of George Grote’s work in turning the tide of scholarly works, and public opinion, concerning the sophists and Athenian democracy. In the © koninklijke brill nv, leiden, ���4 | doi �0.��63/�05��996-��3400�5 book Reviews 433 second chapter Loizides examines the situation in the study of Plato in England at the beginning of the nineteenth century. He notices that lack of interest in Plato’s philosophy, attributable to the fact that Plato’s works were not avail- able in English translation until the end of the eighteenth century and to his association with the metaphysical speculations of the Cambridge Platonists; notwithstanding some previous notable attempts, the situation was to change radically only in the second half of the nineteenth century, with the works and powerful interpretations of Grote and Jowett. Here Loizides illustrates how Plato was appropriated by different thinkers and schools of thought, a process which gave rise to a prophetic Christian Plato, a radical sceptic Plato (Grote’s and the two Mills’), and an idealist Plato (Coleridge’s). James Mill’s view and use of Plato is the subject of the subsequent chapter. Loizides reminds the reader of James Mill’s reputation as a Greek scholar (he was even offered the Greek chair at the University of Glasgow in 1818) and then goes on to show how he appropriated many Platonic ideas and, more generally, Plato’s view on education, while rejecting his undemocratic conclusions. Mill, however, cred- ited Plato’s Republic with attempting to make the interest of the rulers coin- cide with that of the ruled (p. 49) – which was Mill’s own recipe for a good government. In the second part of the book Loizides examines John Stuart Mill’s modes and ways of appropriating Plato. He shows how Mill’s ‘first reading’ of Plato (in his translation of seven dialogues of 1834) is characterized by the emphasis put on Plato’s ‘innovative mode of pursuing truth’ rather than on his conclusions or alleged ‘system’ (p. 86). Mill’s ‘second reading’ of Plato is through the influ- ence of Grote, with whom he agrees almost completely in identifying Plato’s importance with his relentless pursuit of truth through negative dialectics: in this view, Plato was a radical reformer who wanted to fight ignorance and prej- udice. While the first two parts of Loizides’ book provide the context and the background information for Mill’s lifelong engagement with Plato, it is in the third part that the originality of the work mostly resides. Building on recent scholarship on the subject, Loizides identifies the central importance of Mill’s idea of an ‘art of life’ (which first appears in the third edition of his System of Logic) and emphasizes its significance for correctly interpreting Mill’s notion of happiness. Loizides follows the appearance and evolution of this notion in Mill’s works and argues that Mill’s reading of Plato strongly influenced his eudaimonistic conception of happiness as well as his choice of words: ‘art’ for Mill retains the connection between theory and practice and this concept has a directive role in Mill’s works, in that it consists in the first principles of con- duct. For Mill, the end of the art of life is the promotion of happiness of man- kind (p. 131); happiness, however, is the final end but not the sole end of human polis, The Journal for Ancient Greek Political Thought 31 (2014) 425-473.
Recommended publications
  • David Hume on Norms and Institutions"
    Max Weber Programme Conference "David Hume on Norms and Institutions" San Domenico di Fiesole, Villa la Fonte, 17 April 2008 Justice as Unintended Consequence Please do not cite without prior permission Russel Hardin Department of Politics, New York University © 2006, Russell Hardin 2008.04.14 Justice As Unintended Consequence Russell Hardin* NYU - Politics One of the most neglected of all major legal philosophers is David Hume. His neglect as a specifically legal philosopher has followed from at least two unrelated causes. First, Hume’s work on ethics and on political philosophy was widely opposed and even dismissed in his own time. Second, a generation or so after his death, the positive law tradition of Jeremy Bentham and John Austin took center-stage in legal philosophy and dominated the Anglo-Saxon tradition for more than a century thereafter. This latter phenomenon might not have occluded attention to Hume except that Bentham ([1789] 1970) and Austin ([1832] 1954) took over a continental and quasi Hobbesian principle that was not necessary for their approach but which came to define it in the view of many. That principle is that there must be a primary law giver who is above the law. One could read this principle as analogous to the Aristotelian assumption that there must be a first mover, in this case, a first mover to get law started. Or one could read it as a Hobbesian assumption that we require an all powerful sovereign who is above the law but who gives and enforces the law for all other citizens. Hobbes sees his requirement as both logically and causally necessary.
    [Show full text]
  • Three Dimensions of Classical Utilitarian Economic Thought ––Bentham, J.S
    July 2012 Three Dimensions of Classical Utilitarian Economic Thought ––Bentham, J.S. Mill, and Sidgwick–– Daisuke Nakai∗ 1. Utilitarianism in the History of Economic Ideas Utilitarianism is a many-sided conception, in which we can discern various aspects: hedonistic, consequentialistic, aggregation or maximization-oriented, and so forth.1 While we see its impact in several academic fields, such as ethics, economics, and political philosophy, it is often dragged out as a problematic or negative idea. Aside from its essential and imperative nature, one reason might be in the fact that utilitarianism has been only vaguely understood, and has been given different roles, “on the one hand as a theory of personal morality, and on the other as a theory of public choice, or of the criteria applicable to public policy” (Sen and Williams 1982, 1-2). In this context, if we turn our eyes on economics, we can find intimate but subtle connections with utilitarian ideas. In 1938, Samuelson described the formulation of utility analysis in economic theory since Jevons, Menger, and Walras, and the controversies following upon it, as follows: First, there has been a steady tendency toward the removal of moral, utilitarian, welfare connotations from the concept. Secondly, there has been a progressive movement toward the rejection of hedonistic, introspective, psychological elements. These tendencies are evidenced by the names suggested to replace utility and satisfaction––ophélimité, desirability, wantability, etc. (Samuelson 1938) Thus, Samuelson felt the need of “squeezing out of the utility analysis its empirical implications”. In any case, it is somewhat unusual for economists to regard themselves as utilitarians, even if their theories are relying on utility analysis.
    [Show full text]
  • Sidgwick's Philosophical Intuitions
    Etica & Politica / Ethics & Politics, X, 2008, 2, pp. 185-209 Sidgwick’s Philosophical Intuitions Anthony Skelton Department of Philosophy University of Western Ontario [email protected] ABSTRACT Sidgwick famously claimed that an argument in favour of utilitarianism might be provided by demonstrating that a set of defensible philosophical intuitions undergird it. This paper focuses on those philosophical intuitions. It aims to show which specific intuitions Sidgwick endorsed, and to shed light on their mutual connections. It argues against many rival interpretations that Sidgwick maintained that six philosophical intuitions constitute the self- evident grounds for utilitarianism, and that those intuitions appear to be specifications of a negative principle of universalization (according to which differential treatments must be based on reasonable grounds alone). In addition, this paper attempts to show how the intuitions function in the overall argument for utilitarianism. The suggestion is that the intuitions are the main positive part of the argument for the view, which includes Sidgwick's rejection of common-sense morality and its philosophical counterpart, dogmatic intuitionism. The paper concludes by arguing that some of Sidgwick's intuitions fail to meet the conditions for self-evidence which Sidgwick himself established and applied to the rules of common-sense morality. 0. One aim of Henry Sidgwick’s The Methods of Ethics is to provide an argument for utilitarianism, the view that an agent acts rightly insofar as she performs that
    [Show full text]
  • The Methods of Ethics
    The Methods of Ethics Henry Sidgwick Copyright © Jonathan Bennett 2017. All rights reserved [Brackets] enclose editorial explanations. Small ·dots· enclose material that has been added, but can be read as though it were part of the original text. Occasional •bullets, and also indenting of passages that are not quotations, are meant as aids to grasping the structure of a sentence or a thought. Every four-point ellipsis . indicates the omission of a brief passage that seems to present more difficulty than it is worth. Longer omissions are reported between brackets in normal-sized type.—The division of the work into Books, chapters, and numbered sections is Sidgwick’s. —Cross-references follow this system: ‘chapter 3’ means ‘chapter 3 of this Book’. ‘chapter 4.2’ means ‘chapter 4, section 2, of this Book’. ‘II/3’ means ‘Book II, chapter 3’. ‘IV/3.4’ means ‘Book IV, chapter 3, section 4’. An accompanying page-number refers to the page where the passage in question starts.—This version omits most of the 2,000+ cautions that Sidgwick includes, such as ‘I think. ’, ‘I conceive. ’, ‘it seems. ’ and so on. Even with these out of the way, the work doesn’t come across as bullyingly dogmatic.—In this version, most notably on pages 166 and 196, the author addresses the reader (‘you’), but in the original it is always ‘the reader’ and ‘he’.—This version is based on the sixth edition of the work (1901), the last non-posthumous one. The first edition appeared in 1874, the year after Mill died. First launched: October 2011 The Methods of Ethics Henry Sidgwick Contents BOOK I 1 Chapter 1: Introduction........................................................1 Chapter 2: The relation of ethics to politics.............................................7 Chapter 3: Ethical judgments...................................................
    [Show full text]
  • On Sidgwick's Demise: a Reply to Professor Deigh
    On Sidgwick’s Demise: A Reply to Professor Deigh ANTHONY SKELTON The University of Western Ontario In ‘Sidgwick’s Epistemology’, John Deigh argues that Henry Sidgwick’s The Methods of Ethics ‘was not perceived during his lifetime as a major and lasting contribution to British moral philosophy’ and that interest in it declined considerably after Sidgwick’s death because the epistemology on which it relied ‘increasingly became suspect in analytic philosophy and eventually [it was] discarded as obsolete’. In this article I dispute these claims. In a recent article in this journal, John Deigh1 argues that Henry Sidgwick’s The Methods of Ethics2 ‘was not perceived during his lifetime as a major and lasting contribution to British moral philosophy’ (438), and that interest in it declined considerably after Sidgwick’s death because the epistemology on which it relied ‘increasingly became suspect in analytic philosophy and eventually [it was] discarded as obsolete’ (439). In this article I dispute these claims. I Deigh argues that Sidgwick’s Methods ‘was not perceived during his lifetime as a major and lasting contribution to British moral philosophy’ (438). However, this is far from clear. First, to make his point Deigh relies on an article in Encyclopaedia Britannica and an obituary in Mind by Leslie Stephen.3 These are not decisive. Stephen announces at the outset of his obituary that he is not concerned to provide an estimate of Sidgwick’s work in philosophy, though he notes that Methods is a ‘great book’ and that Sidgwick’s work in ethics gave ‘the most important of all modern contributions towards a clear realisation of the conditions of approaching the problems involved’.4 The encyclopaedia article does not deny that Methods is a major contribution; instead, it merely fails to single it out.5 Second, a number of important philosophers were sent copies of Methods when the first edition was published in 1874, 1 John Deigh, ‘Sidgwick’s Epistemology’, Utilitas 19 (2007), pp.
    [Show full text]
  • HUME and MILL on "UTILITY of RELIGION": a BORGEAN GARDEN of FORKING PATHS?L
    TEAO~ Reuista Iberoamericana de Estudios Utilitaristas-2005, XlVII: 117-129 ISSN 1132-0877 HUME AND MILL ON "UTILITY OF RELIGION": A BORGEAN GARDEN OF FORKING PATHS?l JOSE L. TASSET2 University ofA Coruiia ABSTRACT This work is not a specific assessment of Utility ofReligion by John Stuart Mill, but a defence of what I think is a utilitarian, but not millian, view on the problem that work states, the question of the utility of religion in contemporary societies. I construct that view from neohumeanism more than from millian positions, notwithstanding, I postulate that view as a genuine utilitarian one. Every cultural tradition makes a different approach to ethical and political theories. Spanish and Ibero-American utilitarians make precisely it with Clas­ sical Utilitarianism. From that point of view, Ibero-American people identifies utilitarianism with radical and enlightened tradition linked with the reform that through XVIIIth and XIXth centuries tried to undermine the foundations of conservative society in our nations. This aim was not achieved, at least not completely; because of that, the pursuit of Utilitarianism remains opened between us. In the end,I will argue that Spanish and Ibero-American utilitarians connect utilitarianism with philosophical and political radicalism, and inside that His­ panic utilitarianism, plays an important role the criticism of social and political functions of Religion. Maybe, part of the future of Utilitarianism in our cultural context depends on a return of the Theory to its radical roots, also in religious subjects. Keywords: J ohn Stuart Mill, David Hume, Jorge Luis Borges, religion, deism, theism, functionalism, truth. RESUMEN Este trabajo no pretende ser una evaluaci6n especifica de la Utilidad de la Religi6n de John Stuart Mill, sino una defensa de 10 que creo es una posici6n 1 Date of acceptance: 26/07/2006.
    [Show full text]
  • The Dualism of Practical Reason and the Autonomy: Sidgwick's
    UDK: 141.2 FILOZOFIJA I DRUŠTVO XXVII (4), 2016. DOI: 10.2298/FID1604749D Original scientific article Received: 4.11.2016 — Accepted: 29.11.2016 Aleksandar Dobrijević The Dualism of Practical Reason and the Autonomy: Sidgwick’s Pessimism and Kant’s Optimism Abstract The question this paper is concerned with is: what if Immanuel Kant found a solution to the problem of the dualism of practical reason before Henry Sidgwick even came to formulate it? A comparison of Sidgwick’s and Kant’s approach to the problem of the dualism of practical reason is presented only in general terms, but the author concludes that this is sufficient for grasping the advantage of Kant’s solution to the problem. Keywords: Henry Sidgwick, Immanuel Kant, the dualism of practical reason, autonomy, pessimism, optimism An amusing and persistent anecdote that had followed Henry Sidgwick 749 for decades – namely, that he is the most famous philosopher that no one has ever heard of – cannot really be associated with his name any more.1 To become aware of this one needs only to take a look at the monographs written in the past several years about or inspired by his ethics.2 Surely, in professional academic circles Sidgwick’s book The Methods of Ethics (1981 [1907]) has been acknowledged since it’s first edition (1874) as one of the most important achievements in the history of ethics, as a classic work – and it’s still recognized as such.3 However, even those who proclaim the book to be an unsurpassable study in philosophical ethics admit that it is sometimes dull (Parfit 2011: xxxiii), written in the style of a complicated, technical treatise (Singer 2000: xiv).
    [Show full text]
  • The Scholarship and Praxis of Communication Ethics
    Duquesne University Duquesne Scholarship Collection Electronic Theses and Dissertations Fall 2005 The cholS arship and Praxis of Communication Ethics: Rhetorical Interruptions in Historical Narratives Melissa Cook Follow this and additional works at: https://dsc.duq.edu/etd Recommended Citation Cook, M. (2005). The choS larship and Praxis of Communication Ethics: Rhetorical Interruptions in Historical Narratives (Doctoral dissertation, Duquesne University). Retrieved from https://dsc.duq.edu/etd/433 This Immediate Access is brought to you for free and open access by Duquesne Scholarship Collection. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Duquesne Scholarship Collection. For more information, please contact [email protected]. DUQUESNE UNIVERSITY THE SCHOLARSHIP AND PRAXIS OF COMMUNICATION ETHICS: RHETORICAL INTERRUPTIONS IN HISTORICAL NARRATIVES A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF THE DEPARTMENT OF COMMUNICATION & RHETORICAL STUDIES MCANULTY COLLEGE AND GRADUATE SCHOOL OF LIBERAL ARTS IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY BY MELISSA A. COOK PITTSBURGH, PENNSYLVANIA CONVOCATION DECEMBER 2005 The Scholarship and Praxis of Communication Ethics Copyright © August 22, 2005 Melissa A. Cook ii The Scholarship and Praxis of Communication Ethics Acknowledgements It is with heartfelt gratitude that I thank the following people who have supported my completion of the Ph.D. Program in Rhetoric at Duquesne University: The students who agreed to join my first Communication Ethics seminar held during Intercession of 2004 at Washington & Jefferson College. My current students at St. Vincent College, and those who joined the special topics class on communication ethics in the spring of 2005. This is the reason for my passion .
    [Show full text]
  • “Nothing to Invite Or to Reward a Separate Examination”: Sidgwick and Whewell
    Etica & Politica / Ethics & Politics, X, 2008, 2, pp. 137-184 “Nothing to invite or to reward a separate examination”: Sidgwick and Whewell Sergio Cremaschi Dipartimento di Studi Umanistici Università del Piemonte orientale [email protected] ABSTRACT In this paper I discuss Sidgwick’s reaction to Whewell’s moral philosophy. I show how, to Sidgwick’s eyes, Whewell’s philosophy looked as an emblem of the set of be- liefs, primarily religious, into which he had been socialised, and that his reaction was over-determined by both his own ambivalent feelings to his own Anglican upbringing and his subtle rhetorical strategy practised by presenting new shocking ideas hidden between an amount of platitudes and playing the neutral observer or the ‘philosopher of morality’ instead than acting the part of the preacher of a new morality. Then I discuss Sidgwick’s assessment of Whewell’s doctrine as an idle systematisation of re- ceived opinion and the reasons why in the Methods he feels entitled to dismiss histori- cally given intuitionism as ‘dogmatic intuitionism’ without detailed criticism and dis- cusses instead a so-called ‘intuitional method’ as one of the procedures allegedly used by common sense. Besides, I show how individual instances of detailed criticism to Whewell’s doctrines are meant to be not ‘real’ criticism of a rival outlook but instead illustrations of the limits of ‘common-sense morality’. My final claims are: first, Sidg- wick ends with a short-circuit between a inner dialectic of his own argument and dis- cussion of rival doctrines; second, the weight of Whewell’s legacy in Sidgwick’s ethics has been heavily underemphasized.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction to G.E. Moore's Principia Ethica G
    University of Richmond UR Scholarship Repository Religious Studies Faculty Publications Religious Studies 2005 Introduction to G.E. Moore's Principia Ethica G. Scott aD vis University of Richmond, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.richmond.edu/religiousstudies-faculty- publications Part of the Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Davis, G. Scott. "Introduction." In Principia Ethica, by George E. Moore, ix-xvi. Barnes & Noble Library of Essential Reading. New York: Barnes & Noble, 2005. This Book Chapter is brought to you for free and open access by the Religious Studies at UR Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Religious Studies Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of UR Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. INTRODUCTION WHEN Principia Ethica appeared, in 1903, it became something of a sacred text for the Cambridge-educated elite-Lytton Strachey, Leonard Woolf, john Maynard Keynes-who, along with Virginia Woolf, would form the core of the Bloomsbury Group. In a letter of October 1 1, 1903, Strachey confesses to Moore that he is "car­ ried away" by Principia, which inaugurates, for him, "the beginning of the Age of Reason." Moore's critique of convention, his caustic dismissal of his philosophical predecessors, and the relentless rigor of his method promised a revolution in morality commensu­ rate with the modernist transformation of art and literature. Principia Ethica shifted the study of ethics away from normative questions to issues of "metaethics," the study of ethical concepts. Realism vs. relativism, the relation of goodness to rightness, and the logic of moral argument would come to dominate philosophi­ cal ethics for the next century, even when Moore's philosophical heirs differed from him in their conclusions.
    [Show full text]
  • Meaning in Life: a Wittgensteinian Approach
    Meaning in Life: A Wittgensteinian Approach by Seyed Reza Hosseini Submitted in fulfillment of the requirements of the degree DOCTOR LITTERARUM ET PHILOSOPHIAE in Philosophy in the Faculty of Humanities at the University of Johannesburg Supervisor: Professor Thaddeus Metz Co-supervisor: Professor Johan Snyman May 2013 Acknowledgements An idea expands like a seed in the soil. So many things have to happen so it grows. There are people involved here; places too, like the streets of Tehran. That’s what an acknowledgement is about. I am grateful to my supervisors, Professor Metz and Professor Snyman, whose comments and suggestions have been crucial in the development of my thoughts in this work. But, of course, there are more important things that you taught me, to which I express my deepest gratitude. I am grateful to the Philosophy Department at the University of Johannesburg for providing generous financial support for me to present a paper at the 35th International Ludwig Wittgenstein Symposium in Kirchberg am Wechsel, Austria and attending the 19th conference of the European Society for Philosophy of Religion in Utrecht, Netherland. On both occasions, I had the opportunity to share my ideas and seek feedback and comments. Some of those comments made some impacts on my writing. I am especially grateful to Professor Hans Sluga for his comments on my paper, which was a shorter version of Chapter Four. I am also thankful to my friend, Oisín Eoin Keohane for proofreading chapters Five and Six and giving some precious comments on them. Finally, I want to thank my family, my wife, Lebo.
    [Show full text]
  • The History of Modern Moral Philosophy
    Philosophy 172 The History of Modern Moral Philosophy I. Instructor: Chris Korsgaard 205 Emerson Hall Office Telephone: 617-495-3916 [email protected] Office Hours: Thursdays, 2:00-4:00, or by appointment II. Teaching Fellow: Douglas Blue: [email protected] III. Description: A study of the development of modern moral philosophy from its origins in the natural law theories of Hobbes and Pufendorf to the emergence of the two most influential theories of the modern period, utilitarianism and Kantianism, in the works of Bentham and Kant. Selections from the works of Hobbes, Clarke, Butler, Hutcheson, Hume, Smith, Price, and others. *Note: This course, when taken for a letter grade, meets the General Education requirement in Ethical Reasoning. IV. Scheduling Information: We will ordinarily meet for lecture on Mondays and Wednesdays from 12:00 until approximately 1:00. We will have at least two Friday lectures, during the first two weeks on September 7th and September 14. We may use the other Fridays for overflow lectures or for a section meeting. IV. Required Books: D. D. Raphael, ed., British Moralists 1650-1800 (2 volumes). Hackett, 1991. J. B. Schneewind, ed., Moral Philosophy from Montaigne to Kant. Cambridge, 2003. V. Recommended Books: Stephen Darwall, The British Moralists and the Internal ‘Ought’: 1640-1740. Cambridge, 1995. Christine M. Korsgaard, The Sources of Normativity. Cambridge, 1996. J. B. Schneewind, The Invention of Autonomy. Cambridge, 1998. Henry Sidgwick, Outlines of the History of Ethics for English Readers (1902). Hackett, 1988. VI. Link to the Coop: https://tinyurl.com/300-PHIL-172-F18 Philosophy 172: The History of Modern Moral Philosophy, p.
    [Show full text]