Consequentialism Graduate Seminar Peter Singer CHV523/PHI517 Topics and Reading Readings Identified with “CM” Are Available

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Consequentialism Graduate Seminar Peter Singer CHV523/PHI517 Topics and Reading Readings Identified with “CM” Are Available Consequentialism Graduate Seminar Peter Singer CHV523/PHI517 Topics and Reading Readings identified with “CM” are available in Blackboard/Course. Materials. Readings identified with “ER” are available on the Library’s Electronic Reserve. If you have difficulty in obtaining any of the readings, please let me know immediately at [email protected]. 1. 9/20: Sidgwick’s argument for impartial consequentialism Sidgwick is the most philosophically careful of the classical utilitarians, and C.D. Broad, J.J.C. Smart and Derek Parfit have all described The Methods of Ethics as the best book on ethics ever written. We will therefore begin the semester by examining how Sidgwick argues for impartial consequentialism. Reading: Katarzyna de Lazari-Radek and Peter Singer, The Point of View of the Universe, pp.14-22, 33-41,66-77, 94-96, 115-164. Available from the library on 3-hr reserve or electronic access available through the PU library catalogue. Henry Sidgwick, The Methods of Ethics Bk I, Ch. 1; Bk III, Chs. 11 & 13. Available from the library on 3-hr reserve or electronic access available through the PU library catalogue. 2. 9/27: Can Sidgwick’s Dualism of Practical Reason be overcome? Although Sidgwick is generally regarded as a utilitarian, and there is no doubt that his sympathies were in that direction, he was deeply troubled by his inability to show that egoism is irrational. This left him with a “dualism of practical reason” – that is, with the conclusion that both impartial consequentialism and egoistic consequentialism are rational. Katarzyna de Lazari-Radek and I have suggested a way in which this dualism can be overcome, but it would be fair to say that our proposal has not met with widespread acceptance. Essential Reading: Henry Sidgwick,The Methods of Ethics, Concluding Chapter. Katarzyna de Lazari-Radek and Peter Singer, The Point of View of the Universe, pp. 174-199. Derek Parfit, “Conflicting Reasons,” Etica & Politica / Ethics & Politics, XVIII, 2016, 1, pp. 169-186. CM Recommended Reading: Roger Crisp, “Rossian Pluralism, Egoism, and Pleasure, Etica & Politica / Ethics & Politics, XVIII, 2016, 1, pp. 124-129. CM Brad Hooker, “Wrongness, Evolutionary Debunking, Public Rules,” Etica & Politica / Ethics & Politics, XVIII, 2016, 1, pp. 138-143. CM Peter Singer and Katarzyna de Lazari-Radek, “Doing Our Best for Hedonistic Utilitarianism: Reply to Critics,” Etica & Politica / Ethics & Politics, XVIII, 2016, 1, pp. 187-195. CM . 3. 10/4: Do Findings in Cognitive Science Support Consequentialism? Guest presenter: Joshua Greene. Over the past fifteen years, research in cognitive science – much of it pioneered by Josh Greene – has provided new information on how we make moral judgments. Greene now argues that this information tends to support consequentialism. Does it? Or are facts and values strictly separate? Essential Reading: Joshua D. Greene, “Beyond Point-and-Shoot Morality: Why Cognitive (Neuro)Science Matters for Ethics,” Ethics 124 (July 2014): 695–726. ER Julia Driver, “The Limits of the Dual Process View” CM Stephen Darwall, “Getting Moral Wrongness Into the Picture” CM Joshua D. Greene, “Reply to Driver and Darwall” CM Note: the papers by Driver and Darwall, with Greene’s reply, are forthcoming in S. Matthew Liao, ed., Moral Brains: The Neuroscience of Morality, OUP, September 2016. Recommended Reading: Joshua D. Greene, Moral Tribes, Penguin, 2013. Library physical reserve. 4. 10/11: Portmore’s argument for “Commonsense Consequentialism” Guest presenter: Douglas Portmore. In Commonsense Consequentialism Douglas Portmore presents a view of rationality, morality and the connections between them that, he argues, points to a version of consequentialism that is more in accordance with commonsense than the usual impartial form of consequentialism. Essential Reading: Douglas Portmore, Commonsense Consequentialism, OUP, 2011, Chs 1-4. CM 5. 10/18. Parfit on Moral Reasons, Self-Interested Reasons, and Impartial Reasons. This class will discuss issues raised by Parfit in Chapters 53-55 of On What Matters, Volume Three. This will return us to Sidgwick’s Dualism of Practical Reason, but also raise questions about a possible distinction between impartial reasons and moral reasons. Essential Reading: Derek Parfit, On What Matters, Volume Three, Part Ten, Chapters 53-55. CM 6. 10/25. Demandingness Guest presenter (by videolink): Alastair Norcross Is consequentialism – at least in its standard utilitarian form – too demanding? We will examine the objection and some possible responses. Essential Reading: Peter Singer, “What Should a Billionaire Give – and What Should You?” New York Times Magazine, December 17, 2006. CM Katarzyna de Lazari-Radek and Peter Singer, The Point of View of the Universe, Chapter 11, pp.317-336. Alastair Norcross, “The Scalar Approach to Utilitarianism”, Chapter 2 of a book in progress. CM (Note: this chapter draws on, and adds to, the author’s previously published work, including Alastair Norcross, “The Scalar Approach to Utilitarianism” in H. West (ed.), Blackwell Guide to Mill’s Utilitarianism (Oxford, 2006), 217-32. That article is available on ER, should you wish to refer to it, but the required reading is the draft version, not the published version.) Recommended Reading: Richard Arneson, “What Do We Owe to Distant Needy Strangers?” in Jeffrey Schaler, ed., Peter Singer Under Fire, Open Court, 2009, pp. 267-293.ER Peter Singer, “Reply to Richard Arneson,” in Jeffrey Schaler, ed., Peter Singer Under Fire, Open Court, 2009, pp. 294-99. ER R. Lawlor, "The Rejection of Scalar Consequentialism", Utilitas, 21 (2009), 100- 116. ER G. Lang, “Should Utilitarianism be Scalar?” Utilitas, 25 (2013), 80-95. ER MID-SEMESTER BREAK: NO CLASS 11/1. 7. 11/8 The “Separateness of Persons” Objection. Guest presenter (by videolink): Richard Chappell In A Theory of Justice John Rawls said that utilitarianism fails to take the distinction between persons seriously. Ever since, this has been seen as an important objection to utilitarianism. But what, exactly, is the objection? Can it be met? Essential Reading: John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (revised edition, 1999) sections 5 & 30. ER Katarzyna de Lazari-Radek and Peter Singer, The Point of View of the Universe, Chapter 5, sec 4 (ii), pp. 137-140. ER Derek Parfit, On What Matters, Volume Two, Chapter 21, pp.191-212. Available from the library on 3-hr reserve or electronic access through the PU library catalogue. Richard Chappell, “Value Receptacles,” Nous 49 (2015) pp. 322-332. (The online version is available on CM). Recommended Reading: Alex Voorhoeve, “How should we aggregate competing claims?” Ethics 125 (1):64-87 (2014) ER G.A. Cohen, “Rescuing Conservatism: A Defense of Existing Value,” in R.J. Wallace, Rahul Kumar and Samuel Freeman, eds., Reasons and Recognition: Essays in the Philosophy of T.M. Scanlon, available on electronic access through the PU library catalogue. 8. 11/15: The Non-Identity Problem: Theoretical Constraints on a Solution Guest Presenter: Melinda Roberts Essential Reading: Katarzyna de Lazari-Radek and Peter Singer, The Point of View of the Universe, Chapter 12, sec 5, pp. 361-377. ER Derek Parfit, Reasons and Persons, Chapter 16, pp. 351-379. Recommended Reading: Melinda Roberts, "The Nonidentity Problem and the Two-Envelope Problem" from Melinda Roberts and David Wasserman, eds., Harming Future Persons. ER Gregory Kavka, “The Paradox of Future Individuals,” Philosophy and Public Affairs, vol. 11, no. 2 (Spring 1982), pp. 93-112. 9. 11/22 Duties Not to Harm Essential Reading: Derek Parfit, On What Matters, Volume Three, Part Ten, Chapters 56-57. Further reading to come… 10. 11/29: Uncertainty and Deontology (Presentation by Douglas Portmore; response by Michael Smith) Essential Reading: Frank Jackson and Michael Smith, “Absolutist Moral Theories and Uncertainty,” Journal of Philosophy, 103 (2006) 267-83. CM Seth Lazar, “In Dubious Battle: Uncertainty and the Ethics of Killing” (unpublished, 2016) CM Optional Reading: Ron Aboodi, Adi Borer & David Enoch, “Deontology, Individualism, and Uncertainty: A Reply to Jackson and Smith.” Journal of Philosophy, 105 (2008) 259-272. CM Yoaav Isaacs, “Duty and Knowledge,” Philosophical Perspectives, 28 (2014) 95- 110. CM Details for classes 11 & 12 will be provided later, but tentatively, class 11 will be on intrinsic value, and 12 will be on consequentialism and effective altruism. .
Recommended publications
  • David Hume on Norms and Institutions"
    Max Weber Programme Conference "David Hume on Norms and Institutions" San Domenico di Fiesole, Villa la Fonte, 17 April 2008 Justice as Unintended Consequence Please do not cite without prior permission Russel Hardin Department of Politics, New York University © 2006, Russell Hardin 2008.04.14 Justice As Unintended Consequence Russell Hardin* NYU - Politics One of the most neglected of all major legal philosophers is David Hume. His neglect as a specifically legal philosopher has followed from at least two unrelated causes. First, Hume’s work on ethics and on political philosophy was widely opposed and even dismissed in his own time. Second, a generation or so after his death, the positive law tradition of Jeremy Bentham and John Austin took center-stage in legal philosophy and dominated the Anglo-Saxon tradition for more than a century thereafter. This latter phenomenon might not have occluded attention to Hume except that Bentham ([1789] 1970) and Austin ([1832] 1954) took over a continental and quasi Hobbesian principle that was not necessary for their approach but which came to define it in the view of many. That principle is that there must be a primary law giver who is above the law. One could read this principle as analogous to the Aristotelian assumption that there must be a first mover, in this case, a first mover to get law started. Or one could read it as a Hobbesian assumption that we require an all powerful sovereign who is above the law but who gives and enforces the law for all other citizens. Hobbes sees his requirement as both logically and causally necessary.
    [Show full text]
  • 7 Aristotle on Greatness of Soul
    7 Aristotle on Greatness of Soul Roger Crisp n the recent revival of interest in Aristotelian ethics, relatively little attention has been paid to the virtue of greatness of soul (megalopsuchia). This is partly Ibecause of the focus on the more structurally central concepts of Aristotle’s theory, in particular happiness (eudaimonia) and virtue (aret¯e). But in fact a study of greatness of soul can reveal important insights into the overall shape of Aristotelian ethics, including the place of external goods and luck in the virtuous life, and the significance of “the noble” (to kalon). Further, Aristotle describes the great-souled person in more detail than any other, and calls greatness of soul a “sort of crown of the virtues” (NE IV.3.1124a1–2). Many have found aspects of the portrait of the great-souled person in the Nicomachean Ethics repellent or absurd, but that is no good reason for the student of Aristotle to shy away from it. In this chapter, I shall elucidate Aristotle’s account of greatness of soul, addressing some puzzles internal to that account and bringing out its place in, and implications for, the ethics of Aristotle and of those modern writers influenced by him. Greatness of Soul as a Virtue To understand greatness of soul as an Aristotelian virtue requires first understand- ing Aristotle’s conception of virtue itself. Aristotle distinguishes virtues into two classes – intellectual virtues and virtues of character – corresponding to distinct aspects of the human soul (NE I.13). Greatness of soul is a virtue of character, though, like all such virtues, it requires its possessor to have the intellectual virtue of practical wisdom (phron¯esis; NE VI.13).
    [Show full text]
  • The Profoundest Problem of Ethics: About the Possibility of a Profound Solution
    Louisiana State University LSU Digital Commons LSU Master's Theses Graduate School April 2019 The rP ofoundest Problem of Ethics: About the Possibility of a Profound Solution Pol Pardini Gispert [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_theses Part of the Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Pardini Gispert, Pol, "The rP ofoundest Problem of Ethics: About the Possibility of a Profound Solution" (2019). LSU Master's Theses. 4915. https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_theses/4915 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at LSU Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in LSU Master's Theses by an authorized graduate school editor of LSU Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE PROFOUNDEST PROBLEM OF ETHICS: ABOUT THE POSSIBILITY OF A PROFOUND SOLUTION A Thesis Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College in partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in The Department of Philosophy & Religious Studies by Pol Pardini Gispert B.A., Universitat de Girona, 2001 May 2019 For my mother and father, For as many books as I read, your actions are still my moral compass. ii Table of Contents Abstract ........................................................................................................................................... iv Preface ............................................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Non-Religious Ethics? a Critical Notice of Derek Parfit, on What Matters
    Non-Religious Ethics? A critical notice of Derek Parfit, On What Matters The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation Rosen, Michael. 2013. “Non-Religious Ethics? A critical notice of Derek Parfit, On What Matters.” International Journal of Philosophical Studies 21, no. 5: 755–772. Published Version doi:10.1080/09672559.2013.857818 Citable link http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:12967839 Terms of Use This article was downloaded from Harvard University’s DASH repository, and is made available under the terms and conditions applicable to Open Access Policy Articles, as set forth at http:// nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:dash.current.terms-of- use#OAP Non-Religious Ethics? A critical notice of Derek Parfit, On What Matters The History Workshop was a movement of radical social historians which flourished in Britain in the 1960s and 70s. Its goal was to promote “history from below” – to tell the stories of those left out of conventional narratives, and, at the same time, to open up the practice of history itself. Anyway, when the group decided to start a journal, there was a debate over whether it should carry book reviews. Weren’t book reviews – the ranking of others’ work, delivered in a tone of apparent omniscience – examples of exactly the kind of academic gate-keeping against which they had set themselves? So, in its early issues at least, the History Workshop Journal didn’t carry reviews but “Enthusiasms” – contributions in which someone would introduce a new book to readers in positive terms, without pretending to be marking it in some transcendental Prize Fellowship Examination.
    [Show full text]
  • Three Dimensions of Classical Utilitarian Economic Thought ––Bentham, J.S
    July 2012 Three Dimensions of Classical Utilitarian Economic Thought ––Bentham, J.S. Mill, and Sidgwick–– Daisuke Nakai∗ 1. Utilitarianism in the History of Economic Ideas Utilitarianism is a many-sided conception, in which we can discern various aspects: hedonistic, consequentialistic, aggregation or maximization-oriented, and so forth.1 While we see its impact in several academic fields, such as ethics, economics, and political philosophy, it is often dragged out as a problematic or negative idea. Aside from its essential and imperative nature, one reason might be in the fact that utilitarianism has been only vaguely understood, and has been given different roles, “on the one hand as a theory of personal morality, and on the other as a theory of public choice, or of the criteria applicable to public policy” (Sen and Williams 1982, 1-2). In this context, if we turn our eyes on economics, we can find intimate but subtle connections with utilitarian ideas. In 1938, Samuelson described the formulation of utility analysis in economic theory since Jevons, Menger, and Walras, and the controversies following upon it, as follows: First, there has been a steady tendency toward the removal of moral, utilitarian, welfare connotations from the concept. Secondly, there has been a progressive movement toward the rejection of hedonistic, introspective, psychological elements. These tendencies are evidenced by the names suggested to replace utility and satisfaction––ophélimité, desirability, wantability, etc. (Samuelson 1938) Thus, Samuelson felt the need of “squeezing out of the utility analysis its empirical implications”. In any case, it is somewhat unusual for economists to regard themselves as utilitarians, even if their theories are relying on utility analysis.
    [Show full text]
  • University of Birmingham Review of Katarzyna De Lazari-Radek And
    University of Birmingham Review of Katarzyna De Lazari-Radek and Peter Singer's The point of view of the universe - Sedgwick and contemporary ethics Suikkanen, Jussi DOI: 10.5840/tpm201467125 License: None: All rights reserved Document Version Early version, also known as pre-print Citation for published version (Harvard): Suikkanen, J 2014, 'Review of Katarzyna De Lazari-Radek and Peter Singer's The point of view of the universe - Sedgwick and contemporary ethics', The Philosophers' Magazine, vol. 67, no. 4, pp. 114-118. https://doi.org/10.5840/tpm201467125 Link to publication on Research at Birmingham portal General rights Unless a licence is specified above, all rights (including copyright and moral rights) in this document are retained by the authors and/or the copyright holders. The express permission of the copyright holder must be obtained for any use of this material other than for purposes permitted by law. •Users may freely distribute the URL that is used to identify this publication. •Users may download and/or print one copy of the publication from the University of Birmingham research portal for the purpose of private study or non-commercial research. •User may use extracts from the document in line with the concept of ‘fair dealing’ under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988 (?) •Users may not further distribute the material nor use it for the purposes of commercial gain. Where a licence is displayed above, please note the terms and conditions of the licence govern your use of this document. When citing, please reference the published version. Take down policy While the University of Birmingham exercises care and attention in making items available there are rare occasions when an item has been uploaded in error or has been deemed to be commercially or otherwise sensitive.
    [Show full text]
  • Sidgwick's Philosophical Intuitions
    Etica & Politica / Ethics & Politics, X, 2008, 2, pp. 185-209 Sidgwick’s Philosophical Intuitions Anthony Skelton Department of Philosophy University of Western Ontario [email protected] ABSTRACT Sidgwick famously claimed that an argument in favour of utilitarianism might be provided by demonstrating that a set of defensible philosophical intuitions undergird it. This paper focuses on those philosophical intuitions. It aims to show which specific intuitions Sidgwick endorsed, and to shed light on their mutual connections. It argues against many rival interpretations that Sidgwick maintained that six philosophical intuitions constitute the self- evident grounds for utilitarianism, and that those intuitions appear to be specifications of a negative principle of universalization (according to which differential treatments must be based on reasonable grounds alone). In addition, this paper attempts to show how the intuitions function in the overall argument for utilitarianism. The suggestion is that the intuitions are the main positive part of the argument for the view, which includes Sidgwick's rejection of common-sense morality and its philosophical counterpart, dogmatic intuitionism. The paper concludes by arguing that some of Sidgwick's intuitions fail to meet the conditions for self-evidence which Sidgwick himself established and applied to the rules of common-sense morality. 0. One aim of Henry Sidgwick’s The Methods of Ethics is to provide an argument for utilitarianism, the view that an agent acts rightly insofar as she performs that
    [Show full text]
  • The Methods of Ethics
    The Methods of Ethics Henry Sidgwick Copyright © Jonathan Bennett 2017. All rights reserved [Brackets] enclose editorial explanations. Small ·dots· enclose material that has been added, but can be read as though it were part of the original text. Occasional •bullets, and also indenting of passages that are not quotations, are meant as aids to grasping the structure of a sentence or a thought. Every four-point ellipsis . indicates the omission of a brief passage that seems to present more difficulty than it is worth. Longer omissions are reported between brackets in normal-sized type.—The division of the work into Books, chapters, and numbered sections is Sidgwick’s. —Cross-references follow this system: ‘chapter 3’ means ‘chapter 3 of this Book’. ‘chapter 4.2’ means ‘chapter 4, section 2, of this Book’. ‘II/3’ means ‘Book II, chapter 3’. ‘IV/3.4’ means ‘Book IV, chapter 3, section 4’. An accompanying page-number refers to the page where the passage in question starts.—This version omits most of the 2,000+ cautions that Sidgwick includes, such as ‘I think. ’, ‘I conceive. ’, ‘it seems. ’ and so on. Even with these out of the way, the work doesn’t come across as bullyingly dogmatic.—In this version, most notably on pages 166 and 196, the author addresses the reader (‘you’), but in the original it is always ‘the reader’ and ‘he’.—This version is based on the sixth edition of the work (1901), the last non-posthumous one. The first edition appeared in 1874, the year after Mill died. First launched: October 2011 The Methods of Ethics Henry Sidgwick Contents BOOK I 1 Chapter 1: Introduction........................................................1 Chapter 2: The relation of ethics to politics.............................................7 Chapter 3: Ethical judgments...................................................
    [Show full text]
  • On Sidgwick's Demise: a Reply to Professor Deigh
    On Sidgwick’s Demise: A Reply to Professor Deigh ANTHONY SKELTON The University of Western Ontario In ‘Sidgwick’s Epistemology’, John Deigh argues that Henry Sidgwick’s The Methods of Ethics ‘was not perceived during his lifetime as a major and lasting contribution to British moral philosophy’ and that interest in it declined considerably after Sidgwick’s death because the epistemology on which it relied ‘increasingly became suspect in analytic philosophy and eventually [it was] discarded as obsolete’. In this article I dispute these claims. In a recent article in this journal, John Deigh1 argues that Henry Sidgwick’s The Methods of Ethics2 ‘was not perceived during his lifetime as a major and lasting contribution to British moral philosophy’ (438), and that interest in it declined considerably after Sidgwick’s death because the epistemology on which it relied ‘increasingly became suspect in analytic philosophy and eventually [it was] discarded as obsolete’ (439). In this article I dispute these claims. I Deigh argues that Sidgwick’s Methods ‘was not perceived during his lifetime as a major and lasting contribution to British moral philosophy’ (438). However, this is far from clear. First, to make his point Deigh relies on an article in Encyclopaedia Britannica and an obituary in Mind by Leslie Stephen.3 These are not decisive. Stephen announces at the outset of his obituary that he is not concerned to provide an estimate of Sidgwick’s work in philosophy, though he notes that Methods is a ‘great book’ and that Sidgwick’s work in ethics gave ‘the most important of all modern contributions towards a clear realisation of the conditions of approaching the problems involved’.4 The encyclopaedia article does not deny that Methods is a major contribution; instead, it merely fails to single it out.5 Second, a number of important philosophers were sent copies of Methods when the first edition was published in 1874, 1 John Deigh, ‘Sidgwick’s Epistemology’, Utilitas 19 (2007), pp.
    [Show full text]
  • Review of Parfit, on What Matters
    Draft for London Review of Books Review of Parfit, On What Matters Allan Gibbard Morality can’t just be a system of arbitrary taboos. We want its protections, and others need those protections from us. A morality worth heeding must have a rationale, and considerations like these must somehow drive it. A chief job of moral philosophers is to discern such a rationale, and to shape it by criticism and argument. Utilitarians Bentham and John Stuart Mill grounded morality in the general happiness—but at times, duty and total happiness seem to conflict. If a dead husband had led a secret life, then a sweet lie told to the widow may forestall even greater misery, but if she would really want to know the truth however bitter, the lie wrongs her. Utilitarianism is sometimes at odds, it seems, with our moral intuitions. Henry Sidgwick’s The Methods of Ethics in 1874—“his great, drab book”, as Derek Parfit calls it—argued over hundreds of pages that whereas moral knowledge must rest ultimately on intuition, “the morality of common sense is unconsciously utilitarian.” Utilitarianism, in Sidgwick’s version, is the doctrine that morally right acts are those that produce the greatest total happiness for all. When Parfit and I were young in the 1960’s, utilitarianism or something close was widely accepted among leading moral philosophers. Parfit developed the astoundingly original ideas of his youth in his vast 1984 book Reasons and Persons. His line was more or less utilitarian, scrutinizing with avid precision the logic of alternative forms of utilitarianism and supporting concern for others by a set of Bhuddist-like arguments that there need be no clear boundary between one person’s experience and another’s.
    [Show full text]
  • HUME and MILL on "UTILITY of RELIGION": a BORGEAN GARDEN of FORKING PATHS?L
    TEAO~ Reuista Iberoamericana de Estudios Utilitaristas-2005, XlVII: 117-129 ISSN 1132-0877 HUME AND MILL ON "UTILITY OF RELIGION": A BORGEAN GARDEN OF FORKING PATHS?l JOSE L. TASSET2 University ofA Coruiia ABSTRACT This work is not a specific assessment of Utility ofReligion by John Stuart Mill, but a defence of what I think is a utilitarian, but not millian, view on the problem that work states, the question of the utility of religion in contemporary societies. I construct that view from neohumeanism more than from millian positions, notwithstanding, I postulate that view as a genuine utilitarian one. Every cultural tradition makes a different approach to ethical and political theories. Spanish and Ibero-American utilitarians make precisely it with Clas­ sical Utilitarianism. From that point of view, Ibero-American people identifies utilitarianism with radical and enlightened tradition linked with the reform that through XVIIIth and XIXth centuries tried to undermine the foundations of conservative society in our nations. This aim was not achieved, at least not completely; because of that, the pursuit of Utilitarianism remains opened between us. In the end,I will argue that Spanish and Ibero-American utilitarians connect utilitarianism with philosophical and political radicalism, and inside that His­ panic utilitarianism, plays an important role the criticism of social and political functions of Religion. Maybe, part of the future of Utilitarianism in our cultural context depends on a return of the Theory to its radical roots, also in religious subjects. Keywords: J ohn Stuart Mill, David Hume, Jorge Luis Borges, religion, deism, theism, functionalism, truth. RESUMEN Este trabajo no pretende ser una evaluaci6n especifica de la Utilidad de la Religi6n de John Stuart Mill, sino una defensa de 10 que creo es una posici6n 1 Date of acceptance: 26/07/2006.
    [Show full text]
  • Roger Crisp While Several Excellent Books on Sidgwick Have Been
    book reviews 233 Roger Crisp The Cosmos of Duty: Henry Sidgwick’s Methods of Ethics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2015), 234 pp. isbn: 9780198716358. Hardback: £35.00. While several excellent books on Sidgwick have been published in recent years, The Cosmos of Duty is the first comprehensive study of Sidgwick’s masterpiece, The Methods of Ethics (me). This book will obviously be of interest to Sidgwick scholars and those who do research on the history of ethics. But given the con- tinuing relevance of Sidgwick’s arguments, as well as Crisp’s fruitful engage- ment with current literature on topics such as non-naturalism, hedonism, and virtue ethics, anyone with a general interest in moral philosophy would benefit from reading this book. To alleviate problems presented by the complicated structure of the Meth- ods, Crisp adopts a thematic approach; each chapter is devoted to a topic (or topics) explored in various places throughout Sidgwick’s treatise. The book begins with a helpful elucidation of the general framework of Sidgwick’s project, including his views on metaethics, moral concepts, and the aims of philosophical ethics (Chapter 1). Crisp argues that while Sidgwick might have done better to frame the book as about ultimate principles rather than meth- ods, he was right to focus on the triad of utilitarianism, deontology, and ego- ism (pp. 21–28). One of the chief merits of the book is its detailed coverage of parts of the Methods that do not always receive adequate attention, such as Sidgwick’s discussion of free will (Chapter 2) and his accounts of virtue and the individual virtues respectively (Chapters 5 and 6).
    [Show full text]