Programming Language Semantics a Rewriting Approach

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Programming Language Semantics a Rewriting Approach Programming Language Semantics A Rewriting Approach Grigore Ros, u University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign Chapter 2 Background and Preliminaries 15 2.6 Complete Partial Orders and the Fixed-Point Theorem This section introduces a fixed-point theorem for complete partial orders. Our main use of this theorem is to give denotational semantics to iterative (in Section 3.4) and to recursive (in Section 4.8) language constructs. Complete partial orders with bottom elements are at the core of both domain theory and denotational semantics, often identified with the notion of “domain” itself. 2.6.1 Posets, Upper Bounds and Least Upper Bounds Here we recall basic notions of partial and total orders, such as upper bounds and least upper bounds, and discuss several examples and counter-examples. Definition 14. A partial order, or a poset (from partial order set) (D, ) consists of a set D and a binary v relation on D, written as an infix operation, which is v reflexive, that is, x x for any x D; • v ∈ transitive, that is, for any x, y, z D, x y and y z imply x z; and • ∈ v v v anti-symmetric, that is, if x y and y x for some x, y D then x = y. • v v ∈ A partial order (D, ) is called a total order when x y or y x for any x, y D. v v v ∈ Here are some examples of partial or total orders: ( (S ), ) is a partial order, where (S ) is the powerset of a set S , that is, the set of subsets of S . • P ⊆ P (Nat, ), the set of natural numbers ordered by “less than or equal to”, is a total order. • ≤ (Nat, ), the set of natural numbers ordered by “larger than or equal to”, is a total order. • ≥ (Nat , ), the naturals plus infinity, where infinity is larger than any number, is a total order. • ∪ {∞} ≤ (Int, ), the set of integer numbers, is a total order. • ≤ (Real, ), the set of real numbers, is a total order. • ≤ (S, =), a flat set S where the only partial ordering is the identity, is a partial order. • (S , S ), a set S extended with a bottom element with the property that for any a, b S , • ∪ {⊥} ≤ ⊥ ∈ ∪ {⊥} a S b if and⊥ only if a = b or a = , is a partial order. Such extensions of sets with bottom elements ≤ ⊥ are⊥ common in denotational semantics (Section 3.4), where the intuition for the is undefined. They ⊥ are commonly written more simply as S and are often called primitive or flat domains. ⊥ A partial order which is particularly important for denotational semantics (Section 3.4) is (A + B, ), • the set of partial functions from A to B partially ordered by the informativeness relation : given partial functions f, g : A + B, f is “less informative than or as informative as” g, written f g, iff for any a A, it is either the case that f (a) is not defined or both f (a) and g(a) are defined and f (a) = g(a). ∈ 85 If (S , ) and (S , ) are partial or total orders and S S = then (S S , ) is a partial • 1 ≤1 2 ≤2 1 ∩ 2 ∅ 1 ∪ 2 ≤1 ∪ ≤2 order, where a( )b if and only if there is some i 1, 2 such that a, b S and a b. This ≤1 ∪ ≤2 ∈ { } ∈ i ≤i union partial order is typically not a total order; it is a total order only when (S , ) is total and 1 ≤1 S 2 = , or the other way around. More generally, if (S i, i) i I is a family of partial orders such ∅ def{ ≤ } ∈ that S i S j = for any i , j I, then i I(S i, i) = ( i I S i, i I ) is a partial order, where ∩ ∅ ∈ ∈ ≤ ∈ ∈ ≤ a ( i I i) b if and only if there is some i I such that a, b S i and a i b. ∈ ≤ ∈S S∈ S ≤ S def If (S i, i) i I is a family of partial orders then i I(S i, i) = ( i I S i, i I i) is also a partial • { ≤ } ∈ ∈ ≤ ∈ ∈ ≤ order, where ai i I ( i I i) bi i I iff ai i bi for all i I (i.e., the product partial order is defined { } ∈ ∈ ≤ { } ∈ ≤ ∈ component-wise). Q Q Q Q Definition 15. Given partial order (D, ) and a set of elements X D, an element p D is called an upper v ⊆ ∈ bound of X iff x p for any x X. Furthermore, p D is called the least upper bound (LUB) of X, written v ∈ ∈ X, iff p is an upper bound and for any other upper bound q of X it is the case that p q. t v Upper bounds and least upper bounds may not always exist. For example, if D = X = x, y and is the { } v identity relation, then X has no upper bounds. Least upper bounds may not exist even though upper bounds exist. For example, if D = a, b, c, d, e and is defined by a c, a d, b c, b d, c e, d e, then any { } v v v v v v v subset of D admits upper bounds, but the set a, b does not have a LUB. Due to the anti-symmetry property, { } least upper bounds are unique when they exist, which justifies the notation X in Definition 15. t As an analogy with mathematical analysis, we can think of the LUB of a set of elements as their limit. For example, in (Real, ) the LUB of the set n/(n + 1) n Nat coincides with its limit in the mathematical ≤ { | ∈ } analysis sense, namely 1. Note that ([0, 1), ) does not admit LUBs for all its subsets, e.g., n/(n+1) n Nat ≤ { | ∈ } does not have a LUB. One might think that this happens because ([0, 1), ) does not even admit upper bounds ≤ for all its subsets. If we add the interval (4, 5] to the set above, for example, then the resulting (total) order admits upper bounds for any of its subsets (e.g., 5 is such an upper bound) but the set n/(n + 1) n Nat still { | ∈ } does not have a LUB. However, if we add the interval [4, 5] to the original interval [0, 1) then the resulting (total) order admits LUBs for all its subsets; for example, the LUB of n/(n + 1) n Nat is 4. { | ∈ } 2.6.2 Complete Partial Orders In the decimal representation of real numbers, completeness means that any infinite string of decimal digits is actually the decimal representation for some real number. In mathematical analysis in general, a set of real numbers is complete iff the limit of any converging sequence of real numbers is also in the set. For example, the interval [0, 1) open in 1 is not complete, because the sequence 1 1/n for n > 0 converges to 1 but 1 is − not in the set. On the other hand, the interval [0, 1] is complete. Many particular variants of completeness that appear in the literature are in fact instances a general notion or completeness for partial orders. Definition 16. Given a poset (D, ), a chain in D is an infinite sequence d d d d ... of v 0 v 1 v 2 v · · · v n v elements in D, also written using the set notation as d n Nat . Such a chain is called stationary when { n | ∈ } there is some n Nat such that d = d for all m n. ∈ m m+1 ≥ If D is finite then any chain is stationary. More generally, if for a given x D there are only finitely many ∈ elements y D such that x y, then any chain containing x is stationary. ∈ v Definition 17. A poset (D, ) is called a complete partial order (CPO) iff any of its chains has a LUB. (D, ) v v is said to have bottom iff it has a minimal element. Such an element is typically written , and the poset ⊥ 86 with bottom is written (D, , ). CPOs with bottom are also called bottomed complete partial orders. If ⊥ v ⊥ d n Nat is a chain in (D, ), then we also let d , or simply d , denote its LUB, d n Nat . { n | ∈ } v n t n t{ n | ∈ } n Nat G∈ Let us follow up on the examples underneath Definition 14 and discuss which of them are CPOs with botom and which are not: ( (S ), , ) is a bottomed CPO. • P ⊆ ∅ (Nat, ) has bottom 0 but is not complete: the chain 0 1 2 n has no upper bound. • ≤ ≤ ≤ ≤ · · · ≤ ≤ · · · (Nat, ) is a CPO but has no bottom. • ≥ (Nat , , 0) is a CPO with bottom 0: it is a CPO because any chain is either stationary, in which • ∪ {∞} ≤ case its LUB is obvious, or is unbounded by any natural number, in which case is its LUB. ∞ (Int, ) is not a CPO and has no bottom. • ≤ (S, =) is always a CPO, and it has bottom if and only if S has only one element. • (S , S , ) is a bottomed CPO. It is common to use the same notation S , used for the partial • ∪ {⊥} ≤ ⊥ ⊥ order (S ⊥ , S ), to also denote its corresponding bottomed CPO (S , S , ). It is interesting ∪ {⊥} ≤ ∪ {⊥} ≤ ⊥ and particularly important⊥ in denotational semantics to note that the primitive domain⊥ S is equivalent ⊥ to the set of partial functions + S , where is the singleton set. {∗} {∗} (A + B, , ), the set of partial functions A + B ordered by the informativeness relation , is a CPO • ⊥ with bottom : A + B, the partial function which is undefined in each element of A.
Recommended publications
  • Slides by Akihisa
    Complete non-orders and fixed points Akihisa Yamada1, Jérémy Dubut1,2 1 National Institute of Informatics, Tokyo, Japan 2 Japanese-French Laboratory for Informatics, Tokyo, Japan Supported by ERATO HASUO Metamathematics for Systems Design Project (No. JPMJER1603), JST Introduction • Interactive Theorem Proving is appreciated for reliability • But it's also engineering tool for mathematics (esp. Isabelle/jEdit) • refactoring proofs and claims • sledgehammer • quickcheck/nitpick(/nunchaku) • We develop an Isabelle library of order theory (as a case study) ⇒ we could generalize many known results, like: • completeness conditions: duality and relationships • Knaster-Tarski fixed-point theorem • Kleene's fixed-point theorem Order A binary relation ⊑ • reflexive ⟺ � ⊑ � • transitive ⟺ � ⊑ � and � ⊑ � implies � ⊑ � • antisymmetric ⟺ � ⊑ � and � ⊑ � implies � = � • partial order ⟺ reflexive + transitive + antisymmetric Order A binary relation ⊑ locale less_eq_syntax = fixes less_eq :: 'a ⇒ 'a ⇒ bool (infix "⊑" 50) • reflexive ⟺ � ⊑ � locale reflexive = ... assumes "x ⊑ x" • transitive ⟺ � ⊑ � and � ⊑ � implies � ⊑ � locale transitive = ... assumes "x ⊑ y ⟹ y ⊑ z ⟹ x ⊑ z" • antisymmetric ⟺ � ⊑ � and � ⊑ � implies � = � locale antisymmetric = ... assumes "x ⊑ y ⟹ y ⊑ x ⟹ x = y" • partial order ⟺ reflexive + transitive + antisymmetric locale partial_order = reflexive + transitive + antisymmetric Quasi-order A binary relation ⊑ locale less_eq_syntax = fixes less_eq :: 'a ⇒ 'a ⇒ bool (infix "⊑" 50) • reflexive ⟺ � ⊑ � locale reflexive = ... assumes
    [Show full text]
  • Mathematical Tools MPRI 2–6: Abstract Interpretation, Application to Verification and Static Analysis
    Mathematical Tools MPRI 2{6: Abstract Interpretation, application to verification and static analysis Antoine Min´e CNRS, Ecole´ normale sup´erieure course 1, 2012{2013 course 1, 2012{2013 Mathematical Tools Antoine Min´e p. 1 / 44 Order theory course 1, 2012{2013 Mathematical Tools Antoine Min´e p. 2 / 44 Partial orders Partial orders course 1, 2012{2013 Mathematical Tools Antoine Min´e p. 3 / 44 Partial orders Partial orders Given a set X , a relation v2 X × X is a partial order if it is: 1 reflexive: 8x 2 X ; x v x 2 antisymmetric: 8x; y 2 X ; x v y ^ y v x =) x = y 3 transitive: 8x; y; z 2 X ; x v y ^ y v z =) x v z. (X ; v) is a poset (partially ordered set). If we drop antisymmetry, we have a preorder instead. course 1, 2012{2013 Mathematical Tools Antoine Min´e p. 4 / 44 Partial orders Examples of posets (Z; ≤) is a poset (in fact, completely ordered) (P(X ); ⊆) is a poset (not completely ordered) (S; =) is a poset for any S course 1, 2012{2013 Mathematical Tools Antoine Min´e p. 5 / 44 Partial orders Examples of posets (cont.) Given by a Hasse diagram, e.g.: g e f g v g c d f v f ; g e v e; g b d v d; f ; g c v c; e; f ; g b v b; c; d; e; f ; g a a v a; b; c; d; e; f ; g course 1, 2012{2013 Mathematical Tools Antoine Min´e p.
    [Show full text]
  • The Poset of Closure Systems on an Infinite Poset: Detachability and Semimodularity Christian Ronse
    The poset of closure systems on an infinite poset: Detachability and semimodularity Christian Ronse To cite this version: Christian Ronse. The poset of closure systems on an infinite poset: Detachability and semimodularity. Portugaliae Mathematica, European Mathematical Society Publishing House, 2010, 67 (4), pp.437-452. 10.4171/PM/1872. hal-02882874 HAL Id: hal-02882874 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-02882874 Submitted on 31 Aug 2020 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Portugal. Math. (N.S.) Portugaliae Mathematica Vol. xx, Fasc. , 200x, xxx–xxx c European Mathematical Society The poset of closure systems on an infinite poset: detachability and semimodularity Christian Ronse Abstract. Closure operators on a poset can be characterized by the corresponding clo- sure systems. It is known that in a directed complete partial order (DCPO), in particular in any finite poset, the collection of all closure systems is closed under arbitrary inter- section and has a “detachability” or “anti-matroid” property, which implies that the collection of all closure systems is a lower semimodular complete lattice (and dually, the closure operators form an upper semimodular complete lattice). After reviewing the history of the problem, we generalize these results to the case of an infinite poset where closure systems do not necessarily constitute a complete lattice; thus the notions of lower semimodularity and detachability are extended accordingly.
    [Show full text]
  • Partial Orders — Basics
    Partial Orders — Basics Edward A. Lee UC Berkeley — EECS EECS 219D — Concurrent Models of Computation Last updated: January 23, 2014 Outline Sets Join (Least Upper Bound) Relations and Functions Meet (Greatest Lower Bound) Notation Example of Join and Meet Directed Sets, Bottom Partial Order What is Order? Complete Partial Order Strict Partial Order Complete Partial Order Chains and Total Orders Alternative Definition Quiz Example Partial Orders — Basics Sets Frequently used sets: • B = {0, 1}, the set of binary digits. • T = {false, true}, the set of truth values. • N = {0, 1, 2, ···}, the set of natural numbers. • Z = {· · · , −1, 0, 1, 2, ···}, the set of integers. • R, the set of real numbers. • R+, the set of non-negative real numbers. Edward A. Lee | UC Berkeley — EECS3/32 Partial Orders — Basics Relations and Functions • A binary relation from A to B is a subset of A × B. • A partial function f from A to B is a relation where (a, b) ∈ f and (a, b0) ∈ f =⇒ b = b0. Such a partial function is written f : A*B. • A total function or just function f from A to B is a partial function where for all a ∈ A, there is a b ∈ B such that (a, b) ∈ f. Edward A. Lee | UC Berkeley — EECS4/32 Partial Orders — Basics Notation • A binary relation: R ⊆ A × B. • Infix notation: (a, b) ∈ R is written aRb. • A symbol for a relation: • ≤⊂ N × N • (a, b) ∈≤ is written a ≤ b. • A function is written f : A → B, and the A is called its domain and the B its codomain.
    [Show full text]
  • Formal Programming Language Semantics Note 12 Complete Partial
    Formal Programming Language Semantics note 12 CS4/MSc/TPG 18.11.02 Formal Programming Language Semantics note 12 Complete partial orders (CPOs) In this note we re-examine some of the ideas in the previous two notes from a slightly more abstract perspective. In particular, we are going to concentrate on the ideas behind the denotational semantics of while commands. By isolating the aspects of the situation which really made the semantics work, we will arrive at the basic concepts of a subject known as domain theory, which provides a general mathematical framework for much of denotational semantics. Complete partial orders. Let us write D for the set DCom = (S * S) from Note 9. Recall that we defined an element h ∈ D as the union of an increasing chain h0 ⊆ h1 ⊆ · · · . We now ask: what are the essential features of D that made this construction work? One reasonable answer (though not the only one!) is given by the following definitions: Definition 1 A partially ordered set, or poset, is a set D equipped with a binary relation v (called an order relation) such that the following hold for all x, y, z ∈ D: • x v x ( v is reflexive); • if x v y and y v z then x v z ( v is transitive); • if x v y and y v x then x = y ( v is antisymmetric). Definition 2 A complete partial order, or CPO, is a poset with the following prop- erty: every sequence of elements x0 v x1 v · · · in D has a limit or least upper F bound in D: that is, there is an element x ∈ D (written as i xi) such that • xi v x for all i (i.e.
    [Show full text]
  • Domain Theory: an Introduction
    Domain Theory: An Introduction Robert Cartwright Rebecca Parsons Rice University This monograph is an unauthorized revision of “Lectures On A Mathematical Theory of Computation” by Dana Scott [3]. Scott’s monograph uses a formulation of domains called neighborhood systems in which finite elements are selected subsets of a master set of objects called “tokens”. Since tokens have little intuitive significance, Scott has discarded neighborhood systems in favor of an equivalent formulation of domains called information systems [4]. Unfortunately, he has not rewritten his monograph to reflect this change. We have rewritten Scott’s monograph in terms of finitary bases (see Cartwright [2]) instead of information systems. A finitary basis is an information system that is closed under least upper bounds on finite consistent subsets. This convention ensures that every finite answer is represented by a single basis object instead of a set of objects. 1 The Rudiments of Domain Theory Motivation Programs perform computations by repeatedly applying primitive operations to data values. The set of primitive operations and data values depends on the particular programming language. Nearly all languages support a rich collection of data values including atomic objects, such as booleans, integers, characters, and floating point numbers, and composite objects, such as arrays, records, sequences, tuples, and infinite streams. More advanced languages also support functions and procedures as data values. To define the meaning of programs in a given language, we must first define the building blocks—the primitive data values and operations—from which computations in the language are constructed. Domain theory is a comprehensive mathematical framework for defining the data values and primitive operations of a programming language.
    [Show full text]
  • Two Counterexamples Concerning the Scott Topology on a Partial Order
    TWO COUNTEREXAMPLES CONCERNING THE SCOTT TOPOLOGY ON A PARTIAL ORDER PETER HERTLING Fakult¨atf¨urInformatik, Universit¨atder Bundeswehr M¨unchen, 85577 Neubiberg, Germany e-mail address: [email protected] Abstract. We construct a complete lattice Z such that the binary supremum function sup : Z × Z ! Z is discontinuous with respect to the product topology on Z × Z of the Scott topologies on each copy of Z. In addition, we show that bounded completeness of a complete lattice Z is in general not inherited by the dcpo C(X; Z) of continuous functions from X to Z where X may be any topological space and where on Z the Scott topology is considered. 1. Introduction In this note two counterexamples in the theory of partial orders are constructed. The first counterexample concerns the question whether the binary supremum function on a sup semilattice is continuous with respect to the product topology of the Scott topology on each copy of the sup semilattice. The second counterexample concerns the question whether bounded completeness of a complete lattice is inherited by the dcpo of continuous functions from some topological space to the complete lattice. The Scott topology on a partially ordered set (short: poset)(X; ) has turned out to v be important in many areas of computer science. Given two posets (X1; 1) and (X2; 2), v v one can in a natural way define a partial order relation × on the product X1 X2. This v × gives us two natural topologies on the product Z = X1 X2: × The product of the Scott topology on (X1; 1) and of the Scott topology on (X2; 2), • v v the Scott topology on (Z; ×).
    [Show full text]
  • Lattice Theory
    Chapter 1 Lattice theory 1.1 Partial orders 1.1.1 Binary Relations A binary relation R on a set X is a set of pairs of elements of X. That is, R ⊆ X2. We write xRy as a synonym for (x, y) ∈ R and say that R holds at (x, y). We may also view R as a square matrix of 0’s and 1’s, with rows and columns each indexed by elements of X. Then Rxy = 1 just when xRy. The following attributes of a binary relation R in the left column satisfy the corresponding conditions on the right for all x, y, and z. We abbreviate “xRy and yRz” to “xRyRz”. empty ¬(xRy) reflexive xRx irreflexive ¬(xRx) identity xRy ↔ x = y transitive xRyRz → xRz symmetric xRy → yRx antisymmetric xRyRx → x = y clique xRy For any given X, three of these attributes are each satisfied by exactly one binary relation on X, namely empty, identity, and clique, written respectively ∅, 1X , and KX . As sets of pairs these are respectively the empty set, the set of all pairs (x, x), and the set of all pairs (x, y), for x, y ∈ X. As square X × X matrices these are respectively the matrix of all 0’s, the matrix with 1’s on the leading diagonal and 0’s off the diagonal, and the matrix of all 1’s. Each of these attributes holds of R if and only if it holds of its converse R˘, defined by xRy ↔ yRx˘ . This extends to Boolean combinations of these attributes, those formed using “and,” “or,” and “not,” such as “reflexive and either not transitive or antisymmetric”.
    [Show full text]
  • Partial Order Techniques for the Analysis and Synthesis of Hybrid and Embedded Systems
    Partial order techniques for the analysis and synthesis of hybrid and embedded systems Organizer: Domitilla Del Vecchio EECS Systems Laboratory University of Michigan, Ann Arbor Abstract—The objective of this tutorial is to introduce in s. Min(T ) denotes the set of minimal elements of T and a tutorial fashion the employment of partial order techniques Max(T ) denotes the set of maximal elements of T . If Min(T ) for analysis and synthesis problems in hybrid systems. While is the singleton {s} then s is called the least element of T . familiar to computer scientists, partial order notions may be less familiar to a control audience. The session will present If Max(T ) is the singleton {s} then s is called the greatest fundamental notions in partial order theory including the element of T . We write Max⊑ and Min⊑ if we need to make definition of a partial order, properties of maps, and complete clear the underlying order. A partially ordered set (S, ⊑) is partial order (CPO) fix point theorems. The application of these a complete partial order, cpo for short, iff every chain of S notions to hybrid systems will be illustrated for the synthesis has a lub in S. of safety controllers, for the design of state estimators, for robust verification, and for the analysis of the dynamics. Finally, Example 1: Let us consider S = {s1,s2,s3}. In the S problems in the context of intelligent transportation will be partially ordered set (2 , ⊆), {s1,s3} is below {s1,s2,s3} introduced and the application of partial order tools will be as {s1,s3} ⊆ {s1,s2,s3}, Max({∅, {s1}, {s2,s3}}) = S S discussed.
    [Show full text]
  • Partial Order Theory in the Assessment of Environmental Chemicals: Formal Aspects of a Precautionary Pre-Selection Procedure
    Diss. ETH No 15433 Partial Order Theory in the Assessment of Environmental Chemicals: Formal Aspects of a Precautionary Pre-Selection Procedure A dissertation submitted to the Swiss Federal Institute of Technology Zurich¨ for the degree of Doctor of Natural Sciences presented by Olivier Schucht Dipl. natw. ETH born January 6, 1974 from Z¨urich (ZH) accepted on the recommendation of Prof. Dr. Ulrich M¨uller-Herold, examiner Prof. Dr. Konrad Hungerb¨uhler,co-examiner Prof. Dr. Nils-Eric Sahlin, co-examiner 2004 Abstract Man-made chemicals have been shown over recent decades to exhibit unwanted ef- fects on a global scale. The possible occurrence of such global effects have turned out to be difficult to model with traditional assessment procedures. Alternative, non-traditional procedures have been proposed in recent years as a response to this challenge. The present thesis proposes to develop such an alternative assessment procedure, namely one that is based on the concept of exposure (the physical oc- currence of a substance in the environment), rather than being based exclusively on known effects (which are inherently difficult to predict). This approach meets a restricted definition of the precautionary principle. Exposure of a chemical is presently modeled with two scenarios, while ensuring that the assessment procedure herein developed can allow for additional scenarios to be taken into consideration at a later stage. The validity of non-traditional assessments that aim at assessing chemical substances beyond known adverse effects is often doubted both inside and outside of the sci- entific community. In order to respond to these reservations the present thesis establishes a formal setting.
    [Show full text]
  • Domain Theory Corrected and Expanded Version Samson Abramsky1 and Achim Jung2
    Domain Theory Corrected and expanded version Samson Abramsky1 and Achim Jung2 This text is based on the chapter Domain Theory in the Handbook of Logic in Com- puter Science, volume 3, edited by S. Abramsky, Dov M. Gabbay, and T. S. E. Maibaum, published by Clarendon Press, Oxford in 1994. While the numbering of all theorems and definitions has been kept the same, we have included comments and corrections which we have received over the years. For ease of reading, small typo- graphical errors have simply been corrected. Where we felt the original text gave a misleading impression, we have included additional explanations, clearly marked as such. If you wish to refer to this text, then please cite the published original version where possible, or otherwise this on-line version which we try to keep available from the page http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/˜axj/papers.html We will be grateful to receive further comments or suggestions. Please send them to [email protected] So far, we have received comments and/or corrections from Liang-Ting Chen, Francesco Consentino, Joseph D. Darcy, Mohamed El-Zawawy, Miroslav Haviar, Weng Kin Ho, Klaus Keimel, Olaf Klinke, Xuhui Li, Homeira Pajoohesh, Dieter Spreen, and Dominic van der Zypen. 1Computing Laboratory, University of Oxford, Wolfson Building, Parks Road, Oxford, OX1 3QD, Eng- land. 2School of Computer Science, University of Birmingham, Edgbaston, Birmingham, B15 2TT, England. Contents 1 Introduction and Overview 5 1.1 Origins ................................. 5 1.2 Ourapproach .............................. 7 1.3 Overview ................................ 7 2 Domains individually 10 2.1 Convergence .............................
    [Show full text]
  • Universal Partial Order Represented by Means of Oriented Trees and Other Simple Graphs
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Elsevier - Publisher Connector European Journal of Combinatorics 26 (2005) 765–778 www.elsevier.com/locate/ejc Universal partial order represented by means of oriented trees and other simple graphs Jan Hubicka,ˇ Jaroslav Nesetˇ rilˇ Department of Applied Mathematics and Institute of Theoretical Computer sciences (ITI), Charles University, Malostransk´en´am. 25, 11800 Praha, Czech Republic Received 8 May 2003; accepted 23 January 2004 Available online 22 January 2005 Abstract We present several simple representations of universal partially ordered sets and use them for the proof of universality of the class of oriented trees ordered by the graph homomorphisms. This (which we believe to be a surprising result) solves several open problems. It implies for example universality of cubic planar graphs. This is in sharp contrast with representing even groups (and monoids) by automorphisms (and endomorphisms) of a bounded degree and planar graph. Thus universal partial orders (thin categories) are representable by much simpler structures than categories in general. © 2003 Published by Elsevier Ltd 1. Introduction Acountable partially ordered set is said to be universal if it contains any countable partial order as an (induced) suborder. A universal partial order exist. This classical result has been proved several times [9, 14, 15]andinthe context of category theory motivated the whole research area. Particularly, Hedrl´ın [6]found examples of universal partial orders with easy representation and this line culminated in proving that many frequent categories induce universal partial orders. These include e.g.
    [Show full text]