Logoi Spermatikoi and the Concept of Seeds in the Mineralogy and Cosmogony of Paracelsus Hiro HIRAI *

Abstract: Paracelsus’s concept of seeds is an important contribution to Renaissance theories of matter. Unlike the alchemists’ notion of metal seeds, it has a strong Christian orientation, based on a particular inter- pretation of the biblical Creation story. It is in this cosmogonical aspect that Paracelsian seeds are more akin to the seminal reasons of Augustine than to the logoi spermatikoi of the Stoics or Plotinus. The present study examines the Augustinian background of this Paracelsian concept and Marsilio Ficino’s intermediary role in its origination.

Document downloaded from www.cairn-int.info - 213.49.84.124 07/10/2014 22h45. © Armand Colin Keywords: Paracelsus, seeds, logoi spermatikoi, seminal reasons, Plotinus, Augustine, Marsilio Ficino.

Résumé : Le concept de semence de Paracelse constitue une contribu- tion importante aux théories de la matière de la Renaissance. À la dif- férence de la notion alchimique des semences des métaux, ce concept prend une orientation nettement chrétienne fondée sur l’interprétation singulière du récit de la Création. C’est par cet aspect cosmogonique que les semences paracelsiennes s’approchent plus des raisons sémi- nales de saint Augustin que des logoi spermatikoi des stoïciens ou de Plotin. La présente étude examine le fond augustinien du concept para- celsien et le rôle qu’a joué Marsile Ficin dans la genèse de ce concept.

Mots-clés : Paracelse ; semences ; logoi spermatikoi ; raisons séminales ; Plotin ; Augustin ; Marsile Ficin.

Introduction Historians have recently started taking an interest in the inluence of Stoic physics on scientiic thought in the sixteenth and seven- teenth centuries. However, when faced with the dificulty of sur- veying all writings containing Stoic ideas – a dificulty on which Gérard Verbeke has remarked – the best approach is without a doubt to identify and trace the Stoic themes that were gradually

* Hiro Hirai, Vice Editor, Early Science and Medicine, Radboud University Nijmegen (Netherlands).

Revue d’histoire des sciences I Volume 61-2 I July-December 2008 I Document downloaded www.cairn-int.info - 213.49.84.124 07/10/2014 22h45. © Armand Colin Hiro HIRAI

incorporated into Western thought.1 It appears to me that, com- pared to the well-known related doctrine of pneuma (spiritus, mind, or Geist),2 the theory of logoi spermatikoi is not as exhaus- tively explored.3

This theory is an ingenious invention of Stoic physics. Granted, the pre-Socratic philosophers freely used the metaphor of “seed” (sperma) in reference to the origin of material or quantitive exis- tence in their theories of nature. For instance, Anaxagoras used the word “sperma” to refer to the beginning of natural things, while the ancient Pythagoreans considered the irst step of the formation of the entire universe to be a “seminal point.”4 As for the notion of the seminal principle, which was regarded as a kind of creative force, it was developed in embryological speculations.5 It was with the Stoics that the active principle of the universe explic- itly became seminal for the irst time, unifying the role of creative

Document downloaded from www.cairn-int.info - 213.49.84.124 07/10/2014 22h45. © Armand Colin power and that of the origin of being. This was the doctrine of the logoi spermatikoi.

In the monistic, deterministic system of the Stoics, the logoi sper- matikoi were responsible for the transmission and preservation of the speciicity of each type of natural thing. The inluence of this doctrine can be found in the Hellenistic and Latin philoso- phers, as well as among the Christian apologists of the irst century

1 - See Gérard Verbeke, The Presence of in Medieval Thought (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 1983), 1-19. 2 - See Gérard Verbeke, L’Évolution de la doctrine du pneuma du stoïcisme à saint Augustin (Paris: Desclée de Brouwer, 1945); Marta Fattori and Massimo Bianchi (ed.), Spiritus: IV° colloquio internazionale del lessico intellettuale europeo (Rome: Laterza, 1984); James J. Bono, “Medical spirits and the medieval language of life,” Traditio 40 (1984): 91-130; Daniel P. Walker, Spiritual and demonic magic from Ficino to Campanella (London: Warburg, 1958); Antonio Clericuzio, “The Internal Laboratory: The Chemical Reinterpretation of Medical Spirits in England (1650-1680),” in Alchemy and Chemistry in the 16th and 17th Centuries, ed. Piyo Rattansi and Antonio Clericuzio (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1994), 51-83. 3 - On Greco-Roman antiquity, Heinz Meyer, Geschichte der Lehre von den Keimkräften von der Stoa bis zum Ausgang der Patristik (Bonn: Hansteins, 1914), remains a very useful reference. 4 - Geoffrey E. R. Lloyd, Polarity and Analogy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1966), 237-51; David E. Hahm, The Origins of Stoic Cosmology (Columbus, OH: Ohio State University Press, 1977), 60-90. 5 - Anthony Preus, “Science and Philosophy in Aristotle’s Generation of Animals,” Journal of the History of Biology 3(1970): 1-52; Iain M. Lonie, The Hippocratic Treatises “On Generation,” “On the Nature of the Child,” “Diseases IV”: A Commentary (Berlin: De Gruyter, 1981).

II Document downloaded www.cairn-int.info - 213.49.84.124 07/10/2014 22h45. © Armand Colin Logoi Spermatikoi and the Concept of Seeds...

A.D.,6 most prominent of which were Plotinus (205-270 A.D.) and Augustine (354-430 A.D.). Plotinius used the Stoic idea of logoi spermatikoi while modifying and spiritualizing its materialist con- tent. Likewise, Augustine’s theory of “seminal reasons” (rationes seminales) is based on the logoi spermatikoi of the Stoics and of Plotinus. It was through the Augustinian tradition that the idea of the logoi spermatikoi was transmitted to the Latin world of the Middle Ages.7

Once scholastic Aristotelianism came to dominate Western intel- lectual life, the idea of the seminal principle became less promi- nent. Its role was often replaced by a composite of various natu- ral forces, a typical example of which was the idea advanced by Albert the Great (c. 1193-1280): a combination of the forces of the four elements, the celestial bodies, and the prime mover.8 As for Thomas Aquinas (c. 1225-1274) with his theory of the “substantial

Document downloaded from www.cairn-int.info - 213.49.84.124 07/10/2014 22h45. © Armand Colin form,” he preferred the potentiality of matter to seminal reasons that are immanent to matter. The perpetuation of the concept after Aquinas is therefore little studied by historians.

Medieval alchemy, which favored sexual analogies and explicit hylozoism under the inluence of Stoic biocosmology, retained the metaphor of the seed in its theory on the formation of metals and minerals. The most popular version was that of the two principles of sulfur and mercury,9 which were often seen as being active or

6 - Meyer, Geschichte der Lehre vol. 3, 26-122; Michel Spanneut, Le stoïcisme des Pères de l’Église, 2nd ed. (Paris: Le Seuil, 1969); Michel Spanneut, Permanence du stoïcisme (Gembloux: Duculot, 1973); Marcia L. Colish, The Stoic Tradition from Antiquity to the Early Middle Ages (Leiden: Brill, 1985). 7 - On the philosophers of the twelfth century, see Michael Lapidge, “The Stoic Inheritance,” in A History of Twelfth-Century Western Philosophy, ed. Peter Dronke (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), 81-112, and especially 110-112. For (c. 1214-c. 1292), see Pierre Duhem, Le Système du monde. Histoire des doctrines cos- mologiques de Platon à Copernic (Paris: Hermann, 1917), vol. 5, 385-388. Gilles de Rome (c. 1247-1316) used this teaching in his embryology. See M. Anthony Hewson, Giles of Rome and the Medieval Theory of Conception (London: Athlone, 1975), 121-134. 8 - Albert the Great, De mineralibus, I, i, 8. On Albert the Great’s seminal reasons see Macarius Wengel, Die Lehre von den rationes seminales bei Albert dem Grossen (Würzburg: Mayr, 1937); Bruno Nardi, Studi di ilosoia medievale (Rome: Storia e letteratura, 1960). 9 - Edmund O. von Lippmann, Abhandlungen und Vorträge zur Geschichte der Naturwissenschaften (Leipzig, 1913), vol. II, 143-150; Reijer Hooykaas, The Concept of Element: Its Historical-Philosophical Development (s. l., 1983), 20-27 and 62-6; Paul Kraus, Jâbir ibn Hayyân: Contribution à l’histoire des idées scientiiques dans l’Islam, 2nd ed. (Paris: Belles Lettres, 1986), 1; Robert P. Multhauf, The Origins of Chemistry (London: Oldbourne, 1966), 126 and 131-133.

Revue d’histoire des sciences I Volume 61-2 I July-December 2008 III Document downloaded www.cairn-int.info - 213.49.84.124 07/10/2014 22h45. © Armand Colin Hiro HIRAI

volatile. The alchemists called them the “seeds” of metal. Using Aristotle’s embryology as a model, they assumed that sulfur had an active force similar to male seed, and that mercury embodied the feminine role, called “menstruum” or “female seed.” Despite the biblical analogy that developed over time around the notion of seed among Christian alchemists, the term “seed” largely came to refer to concrete matter that the alchemist could manipulate in the laboratory.

In the sixteenth century, we once again encounter a large num- ber of ideas derived from the seed in diverse scientiic ields, and called by different names: “seeds” (semina), “seeds of reasons” (semina rationum), “seminal reasons” (rationes seminales), “semi- nary” (seminarium), “seminal principle” (principium seminale), etc. To simplify the discussion, let us provisionally group them together under “the concept of seed.”10 In mineralogy, there was also a

Document downloaded from www.cairn-int.info - 213.49.84.124 07/10/2014 22h45. © Armand Colin trend in which the concept was used to explain mineral formation at least until the triumph of Newtonian atomism in the eighteenth century. Frank D. Adams has already shed light on this point, but without examining its philosophical origins.11 More recently, David R. Oldroyd and Norma E. Emerton have examined the issue by tracing it back to Stoicism.12 In reality, the work of these two his- torians largely depends on that of Walter Pagel, who emphasized the importance of the concept of seed in the natural philosophy of the Swiss doctor Theophrastus von Hohenheim, called Paracelsus (c. 1493-1541).13

Paracelsus applied his concept of seed not only to the generation of living beings, but also to the formation of inorganic things, and

10 - On the concept of seed in the Renaissance, see Hiro Hirai, Le concept de semence dans les théories de la matière à la Renaissance: De Marsile Ficin à Pierre Gassendi (Turnhout: Brepols, 2005). 11 - Frank D. Adams, The Birth and Development of the Geological Sciences, 2nd ed. (New York: Dover, 1954), 84-90 and 289-291. 12 - David R. Oldroyd, “Some Neo-Platonic and Stoic Inluences on Mineralogy in the Sixteenth and Seventeenth Centuries,” Ambix 21 (1974): 128-56; Norma E. Emerton, The Scientiic Reinterpretation of Form (New York: Cornell University Press, 1984), 193-208. 13 - Walter Pagel, Paracelsus: An Introduction to Philosophical Medicine in the Era of the Renaissance, 2nd ed. (Basel: Karger, 1982); Walter Pagel, “Paracelsus and the Neoplatonic and Gnostic Tradition,” Ambix 8 (1960): 125-166; Walter Pagel, “The Prime Matter of Paracelsus,” Ambix 9 (1961): 117-135; Walter Pagel, Das medizinische Weltbild des Paracelsus (Wiesbaden: Steiner, 1962).

IV Document downloaded www.cairn-int.info - 213.49.84.124 07/10/2014 22h45. © Armand Colin Logoi Spermatikoi and the Concept of Seeds...

used the theory in his etiology. He even links seeds to activities of the mind such as will, passion, and imagination. Although Paracelsus did not leave us any works that were exclusively on his concept of seed, he dealt with it on multiple occasions, scattered throughout his writings, neither claiming its originality nor citing any authority in connection with it.

Given the close resemblance between his worldview and alchemi- cal thinking, it would be natural to assume that his seed concept is derived speciically from medieval alchemy. Hence, Pagel writes, by generalizing the hylozoist seminal principle of the alchemists, Paracelsus introduced invisible seeds as the germs of every natural body.14 It was in this connection that Pagel emphasizes the inlu- ence of the Stoic doctrine of the logoi spermatikoi.

It is a well-known fact that Paracelsus added salt to sulfur and mer-

Document downloaded from www.cairn-int.info - 213.49.84.124 07/10/2014 22h45. © Armand Colin cury as the third principle of all things. This was his famous theory of the tria prima (Sulfur, Salt, and Mercury).15 According to Pagel, by looking for the logoi that reside in matter, Paracelsus found them in the seeds and the intelligence that they contained. To him, the tria prima were immanent to seeds as their main constituents. Conceived as invisible, spiritual forces, the tria prima were the true principles of all natural things. Recalling that the Alexandrine alchemists, inluenced by the Stoics, identiied in the pneuma and logoi spermatikoi the seeds and the souls of terrestrial things, and speciically metals, Pagel concludes that several Stoic ideas were revived in Paracelsus’s concept of seed.16

However, the sexual allegory used by the alchemists is largely absent from Paracelsus’s tria prima theory, as he no longer calls sulfur and mercury “male seed” and “female seed.” Did he sim- ply remove the sexual association from these principles, creating a

14 - Pagel, Paracelsus: An Introduction, 84-9 and 103. 15 - See Hooykaas, Concept of Element, 77-87; Reijer Hooykaas, “Chemical Trichotomy before Paracelsus?” Archives internationales d’histoire des sciences, II (1949): 1063-74; Kurt Goldammer, Paracelsus: Natur und Offenbarung (Hanovre: Oppermann, 1953), 36-37; Pagel, Paracelsus: An Introduction, 100-104. 16 - Pagel, Paracelsus: An Introduction, 85, 87-88, 100, and 103. Although he mentions other possible sources, like Plotinus, Augustine, and the Corpus Hermeticum, he does not fully develop his analysis. See Pagel, Paracelsus: An Introduction, 225; Pagel, Paracelsus and the Neoplatonic and Gnostic Tradition, 136-137 and 162-163; Pagel, Das medizinische Weltbild des Paracelsus, 45. According to Goldammer, Paracelsus: Natur und Offenbarung, 34, Augustine’s doctrine is unconsciously accepted in it.

Revue d’histoire des sciences I Volume 61-2 I July-December 2008 V Document downloaded www.cairn-int.info - 213.49.84.124 07/10/2014 22h45. © Armand Colin Hiro HIRAI

different seminal entity in its place? Moreover, the alchemists’ con- cept of seed usually refers only to the formation of metals, while that of Paracelsus addresses a broad range of natural phenomena, including the Creation of the world. Could it be that Paracelsus’s concept was inspired by currents of thought other than the Stoics’ doctrine of logoi spermatikoi transmitted by way of medieval alchemy? The concept appears to feature largely in Paracelsus’s writings on mineralogy. Hence, this article analyzes the place and nature of the Paracelsian concept in its own context, and compares it to the main variants of the doctrine of logoi spermatikoi in order to assess its true relationship with Stoic physics.

Logoi Spermatikoi according to the Stoics, Plotinus, and St. Augustine Before examining Paracelsus’s concept of seed, let us provide Document downloaded from www.cairn-int.info - 213.49.84.124 07/10/2014 22h45. © Armand Colin a brief overview of the main features of the doctrine of logoi spermatikoi in the three main systems: Stoic, Plotinian, and Augustinian.

With the Stoics, the doctrine of logoi spermatikoi was determined by the nature of their physics,17 which in turn were intended to explain plurality and teleology in a monistic system. To them, matter is completely formless and indeterminate, but not with- out an active principle: because the logoi spermatikoi, as the generative principles, are immanent to matter. They in turn orig- inate from , the craftsmanlike ire, who is Himself the Logos Spermatikos of the world. Derived from the analogy of animal sperm, the logoi spermatikoi, which were conceived as corpo- real, were said to contain the powers and laws for the growth of individuals. As latent causes, these logoi direct the progressive development of all living and non-living things in accordance with the passage of time.

17 - Hans von Arnim (ed.), Stoicorum veterum fragmenta (Leipzig: Teubner, 1903-1914), I, 102 (= II, 580), 497; II, 717, 739, 780, 885, 1027, 1074; III, 141; Marcus Aurelius, Meditations, IV, 14 and VI, 24; Seneca, Letters to Lucilius, 90, 29; Marcus Aurelius, Questions naturelles, III, 29, 2-3. See also Meyer, Geschichte der Lehre von den Keimkräften von der Stoa bis zum Ausgang der Patristik, 7-26; Joseph Moreau, L’âme du monde de Platon aux stoïciens (Paris: Belles Lettres, 1939), 167-169; Hahm, The Origins of Stoic Cosmology, 60-62 and 75-76; Anthony A. Long and David N. Sedley, The Hellenistic Philosophers (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987), 274-279.

VI Document downloaded www.cairn-int.info - 213.49.84.124 07/10/2014 22h45. © Armand Colin Logoi Spermatikoi and the Concept of Seeds...

When Plotinus appeared on the scene, he naturally adopted the doctrine of logoi spermatikoi, which already formed an integral part of the Platonic tradition inluenced by Stoicism. The irst char- acteristic of his logoi spermatikoi is the fact that they are not cor- poreal, but incorporeal (or spiritual), residing in the soul, whether the soul of the world or of a particular being.18 As they are utterly immaterial, they are the productive and vegetative agents of the soul, the dynamic forces and the internal laws of development that are subject to divine providence. A corporeal being is produced through the addition of a logos spermatikos of the soul to form- less matter. There are therefore as many logoi as there are individ- ual beings. Plotinus applied this theory to organic and inorganic nature. To him, the logoi embodied a mediatory function between the soul and corporeal beings.

The theory of seminal reasons of Augustine was the most powerful

Document downloaded from www.cairn-int.info - 213.49.84.124 07/10/2014 22h45. © Armand Colin Latin vehicle for the transmission of the doctrine of logoi sperma- tikoi to the Middle Ages.19 He used synonyms for seminal reasons such as “seeds” (semina), “primordial seeds” (primordia semina), “germs” (germina), and “implanted reasons” (rationes insita). He introduced this theory in order to resolve various physical, meta- physical, and theological problems, and tried to reconcile the bib- lical teachings with experiences of everyday life. By Christianizing the idea of logoi spermatikoi, he explained the development of natural, normal, and abnormal phenomena, spontaneous genera- tion, the controversies around the book of Genesis, the intellectual development of human beings and, inally, miracles.

18 - Plotinus, Enneads, III, 1, 7; III, 2, 2; III, 7, 11; IV, 3, 10; IV, 4, 29 and 39; V, 1, 5; V, 3, 8; V, 7, 3; V, 9, 6; VI, 3, 16; VI, 7, 5. See also Meyer, Geschichte der Lehre von den Keimkräften von der Stoa bis zum Ausgang der Patristik, 56-67; Arthur H. Armstrong, The Architecture of the Intelligible Universe in the Philosophy of Plotinus, 2nd ed. (Amsterdam: Hakkert, 1967), 61-3, 92-3 and 100; Andreas Graeser, Plotinus and the Stoics (Leiden: Brill, 1972), 41-3. 19 - Augustine, De Genesi ad litteram, II, 15, 30; III, 12, 19-20; IV, 33, 51; V, 7, 20; Id., De trinitate, III, 8, 13; III, 9, 16; Id, De civitate Dei, XII, 26; XXII, 14 and 24. See Paul Agaësse and Aimé Solignac (ed.), Saint Augustin: La Genèse au sens littéral (Œuvres de saint Augustin, series 7, vol. 48-49) (Paris: Desclée de Brouwer, 1972), vol. I, 653- 668; Meyer, Geschichte der Lehre von den Keimkräften von der Stoa bis zum Ausgang der Patristik, 123-224; Charles Boyer, “La théorie augustinienne des raisons sémina- les,” in Miscellanea Agostiniana (Rome: Ordine ermitano di s. Agostino, 1931), vol. II, 795-819; François-Joseph Thonnard, “Les raisons séminales selon saint Augustin,” in Proceedings of the 11th International Congress of Philosophy (Louvain: Nauwelaerts, 1953), vol. XII, 146-152; Jules M. Brady, “St. Augustine’s Theory of Seminal Reasons,” The New Scholasticism, 38 (1964): 141-158; Colish, The Stoic Tradition, 203-206.

Revue d’histoire des sciences I Volume 61-2 I July-December 2008 VII Document downloaded www.cairn-int.info - 213.49.84.124 07/10/2014 22h45. © Armand Colin Hiro HIRAI

According to Augustine, God instantly created all things in the original Creation in seminal form through the seminal reasons, and creatures can come into existence when willed to do so by God. What followed the six days of Creation was the vital, organic unfolding of a history, the elements of which existed in a seminal state from the very beginning. For this reason, the Creator Himself communicates with natural things through the seminal reasons, which give beings intelligibility and rationality. They are immate- rial and remain distinct from both matter and the corporality of visible seeds.

The Concept of Seed in the Mineralogy of Paracelsus Let us now examine the concept of seed in Paracelsus, the most complete development of which can undoubtedly be found in his Document downloaded from www.cairn-int.info - 213.49.84.124 07/10/2014 22h45. © Armand Colin mineralogical treatise, De mineralibus (written in c. 1526-1527).20 In this slender book, Paracelsus explains his theory on the for- mation of minerals in detail, based on his vision of the Universe. From the beginning, he emphasized the importance of studying the end in order to understand the beginning, while introducing the idea of “ultimate matter” (materia ultima) and “prime matter” (materia prima).

To him, ultimate matter is the inal state of development of each natural entity, while prime matter is the original state of the entity.21 “Prime matter” is not used in the sense of the “irst, formless mat- ter” of the Greeks and the alchemists.22 These two types of matter (prime and ultimate) are simply the start and the inish of natural development. As ores, the minerals extracted from mines there- fore exist as ultimate matter. Paracelsus blames Aristotle, Avicenna,

20 - On his mineralogy, see Joachim Schroeter, “Die Stellung des Paracelsus in der Mineralogie des 16. Jahrhunderts,” Schweizerische mineralogische und petrogra- phische Mitteilungen 21(1941): 313-31; Johann E. Hiller, “Die Mineralogie des Paracelsus,” Philosophia naturalis 2 (1952-1954): 293-331 and 435-78. These his- torians did not describe enough of the “biological mode” of the mineral world in Paracelsus. 21 - Paracelsus, De mineralibus (Huser, VIII, 334 = Sudhoff, III, 31). See also Karl Sudhoff, Paracelsus: Sämtliche Werke 1. Abteilung, 14 vol. (Hildesheim: Olms, 1996), which is based on Jean Huser, Bücher und Schriften, 10 vol. (Basel: 1589-1591). 22 - See Marcelin Berthelot, La chimie au Moyen Âge (Paris: 1893), vol. I, 276-7.

VIII Document downloaded www.cairn-int.info - 213.49.84.124 07/10/2014 22h45. © Armand Colin Logoi Spermatikoi and the Concept of Seeds...

Albert the Great and their successors for disregarding ultimate mat- ter in their description of the formation of minerals.23

Paracelsus then explains the formation of minerals from the point of view of his theory of the tria prima, or three principles. He states that all minerals and metals, like all other natural things, are formed only from these three principles. However, each of these three principles is multiple so that each metal formed from its own Sulfur, Salt, and Mercury. In fact, Paracelsus states that there are as many different types of Salts, Sulfurs, and Mercuries as there are natural things in the world. Salt lends color, balsam, and solidity (“coagulation”); Sulfur gives body, substance, and structure; and Mercury lends virtues, power, and arcana. These three principles necessarily combine to form and perfect a mineral body.24 They are distinct from the natural substances of the same name, the names “Sulfur,” “Mercury,” and “Salt” being symbolic terms related to

Document downloaded from www.cairn-int.info - 213.49.84.124 07/10/2014 22h45. © Armand Colin their functions. They should therefore not be understood in the same way as the material causes of the scholastics by placing them at the same level as the Aristotelian elements.

As to the four traditional elements (ire, air, water, and earth), to Paracelsus they are no longer the material causes of natural things, but are the “mothers” (Müter), cosmological matrices from which natural things are born and grow.25 By using this notion of the four mothers, Paracelsus places the formation of minerals in the context of the biblical Creation. He states that at the beginning God created the element “water,” endowing it with the power to give rise to minerals on an ongoing basis. In doing so, God desig- nated water as the “mother” of minerals. God also placed in it the tria prima for future minerals. Paracelsus states that the tria prima are placed in the element “water” as the soul, the spirit, and the essence of this element.26

23 - De mineralibus (Huser, VIII, 334 and 344 = Sudhoff, III, 31 and 42). 24 - De mineralibus (Huser, VIII, 344-345 = Sudhoff, III, 42-43). 25 - See Hooykaas, The Concept of Element, 91-94; Hooykaas, “Die Elementenlehre des Paracelsus,” Janus 29 (1935): 175-187; Pagel (1982), Paracelsus: An Introduction, 82, 95-97 and 129-130. 26 - De mineralibus (Huser, VIII, 343 = Sudhoff, III, 41). On the tricotomy of soul, mind, and body according to Paracelsus, see Ernst W. Kämmere, “Le problème du corps, de l’âme et de l’esprit chez Paracelse et chez quelques auteurs du XVIIe siècle,” in Lucien Braun et al., Paracelse (Paris: Albin Michel, 1980), 89-231.

Revue d’histoire des sciences I Volume 61-2 I July-December 2008 IX Document downloaded www.cairn-int.info - 213.49.84.124 07/10/2014 22h45. © Armand Colin Hiro HIRAI

Minerals play the role of the “fruits” (Früchte) of their mother. As God admirably created the element “water” as the mother of the minerals, the resultant minerals must be its progeny. Note that the notion of “growth” (wachsen) is important in Paracelsus’s natural philosophy. To him, all things that grow have a kind of life force in the form of the spiritus vitae. In addition, he preferred to think of growth in plant-like terms rather than animal-like terms; the growth of minerals is therefore described in plant-like language. According to Paracelsus, minerals have a liquid body called a “tree,”27 which grows in a highly branched form throughout the world. This plant-like image of metallic veins seems to origi- nate from the beliefs of the miners among whom Paracelsus was raised.28 This ancient belief was also strengthened by the inluence of medieval alchemy. Works from the irst half of the sixteenth cen- tury such as Ein nützlich Bergbüchlein (c. 1500) by Ulrich Rülein von Calw of Freiberg, Bergmannus (1530) by Georg Agricola, De

Document downloaded from www.cairn-int.info - 213.49.84.124 07/10/2014 22h45. © Armand Colin la pirotechnia (1540) by Vannoccio Biringuccio, and De subtilitate (1550) by Girolamo Cardano have much common ground with the writings of Paracelsus.29

Thus Paracelsus introduces the concept of seeds through which God’s plan is transmitted to the mineral kingdom in order to form each individual mineral. How, then, should we understand the rela- tionship between seeds, which communicate this Divine design to future minerals, and the element water, which is the mother of the minerals? Paracelsus writes:

27 - De mineralibus (Huser, VIII, 339-340 = Sudhoff, III, 37). On plant terms used by Paracelsus, see Kurt Goldammer, “Planze und planzliches Wachstum als Symbolkomplex bei Paracelsus,” Salzburger Beiträge zur Paracelsusforschung 8 (1969): 115-131. 28 - See Auguste Daubrée, “La génération des minéraux métalliques dans la pratique des mineurs du Moyen Âge, d’après le Bergbüchlein,” Journal des savants 1890, 379-392 and 441-452; Paul Sébillot, Les travaux publics et les mines dans les traditions et les superstitions de tous les pays (Paris: J. Rothschild, 1894), 389-402; Katharine B. Collier, Cosmogonies of Our Fathers (New York: Columbia University Press, 1934), 417-427; Adams, The Birth and Development of the Geological Sciences, 286-307; Gaston Bachelard, La Terre et les rêveries de la volonté (Paris: Corti, 1948), 244-249; Mircea Eliade, Forgerons et alchimistes (Paris: Flammarion, 1956), 45-56; Robert Halleux, “Fécondité des mines et sexualité des pierres dans l’Antiquité gréco-romaine,” Revue belge de philologie et d’histoire 49 (1970): 16-25. 29 - On the Bergbüchlein, see Daubrée, “La génération des minéraux métalliques.” Agricola, Bermannus sive de re metallica (Basel, 1530). See also Robert Halleux and Albert Yans, Georg Agricola: Bermannus (Le mineur) (Paris: Belles Lettres, 1990), 74. Biringuccio, De la pirotechnia (Venice, 1540), I, préface. See Cyril S. Smith and Martha T. Gnudi, The Pirotechnia of Vannoccio Biringuccio (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1950), 13. Cardan, De subtilitate (Nuremberg, 1550), Vol. 5, 107.

X Document downloaded www.cairn-int.info - 213.49.84.124 07/10/2014 22h45. © Armand Colin Logoi Spermatikoi and the Concept of Seeds...

Thus, the irst was with God, the beginning, that is, the ultimate matter. God transformed this ultimate matter into prime matter. Like a fruit that must engender another fruit, it contains a seed: the seed is in the prime matter. Hence, the ultimate matter of min- erals is transformed into a prime matter, that is, a seed, and this seed is the element water. God determined that water should exist; He created it in nature for it to produce ultimate matter, which is in water and takes what is in it, subjected to its power and its preparation. He separates that which belongs to metals into metals and classiies each metal according to its kind. [He also separates] what belongs to stones, and likewise also rocks, and likewise the marcasites and other species. Next, God created time so that there might be a harvest time for wheat and an autumn for fruit. In the same way, He also created for the element water a harvest and an autumn so that all things should have their harvest time and their autumn. Hence, water is an element and a mother, a seed and a root of all minerals.30

Document downloaded from www.cairn-int.info - 213.49.84.124 07/10/2014 22h45. © Armand Colin In this way, according to Paracelsus, God indirectly created the inal state (ultimate matter) of individual minerals in the form of prime matter, and ultimate matter is latent in prime matter. It should be noted that prime matter and ultimate matter are therefore deter- mined by God’s Creation and by divine providence. Paracelsus states that the seed is the prime matter in same way that a fruit includes in itself the seeds of future fruits, and the prime matter resides in the element water. A mineral exists in a dormant state as a seed contained in the prime matter, which, in turn, resides in the element water. Although Paracelsus sometimes says that the seed is

30 - De mineralibus (Huser, VIII, 337 = Sudhoff, III, 34-35). “Nun ist das erst gewesen bei got, der anfang, das ist ultima materia, die selbige ultimam materiam hat er gemacht in primam materiam. Als ein frucht, die ein ander frucht sol geben, die selbige hat ein semen: der sam ist in prima materia. Also ist nun der mineralium ultima materia in ein primam materiam gemachet, das ist in ein sam und der samen ist elementum aquae, und hats resolvirt, das ein wasser ist. Nun zu dem hat er im die natur geschaffen, das sie sol die ultimam materiam machen, die selbig ist im wasser und nimbt, was im wasser ist, das selbig under sein gewalt und praeparation. Was zu metallen gehört, das separirts in metallen und ein ieglich metall für sich selbs. Was zu edlen gesteinen ge- hört also auch in sein art.Was zu steinen gehört der gleichen. Und also mit den marca- siten und andern speciebus. Dan hat got die zeit beschaffen, das ein ernde ist im korn, ein herbst im obst, so hat er auch beschaffen dem element wasser sein ernt und herbst auch. Also das alle ding zu seiner zeit sein ernt und herbst haben. Also ist das wasser ein element und ein muter, ein sam und ein wurzen der mineralien aller.” According to Pagel (1961), Paracelsus: An Introduction, 119-120, the irst “ultimate matter” in the quote is not the ultimate matter of individuals, but the primordial matter of the world. It is that which was in the beginning with God like the spiritual Logos in verse one of the irst chapter of the Gospel of John.

Revue d’histoire des sciences I Volume 61-2 I July-December 2008 XI Document downloaded www.cairn-int.info - 213.49.84.124 07/10/2014 22h45. © Armand Colin Hiro HIRAI

the water, this seed is most probably not the same as the element itself, because water is the seed’s matrix (mother).

In another place, Paracelsus describes in more general terms the relationship between the seed and the element water:

When someone who has all the seeds in the world all mixed up together in a bag and sows them in his garden: this is what nature is like. And nature gives each seed its own fruit in the end, such that each seed realizes its essence and perfection without harming any others. This should not only be understood in this sense, but also in the case of water, as if it was a bag containing all the seeds and all these seeds were sown – thus each genus and each species grows according to its nature and properties. Thus God ordained the mira- cles of His Creation in the four elements, and these are the elements from which the fruits come so that man may use them, created by God, each individual type with its own character and essence.31 Document downloaded from www.cairn-int.info - 213.49.84.124 07/10/2014 22h45. © Armand Colin To Paracelsus, the element water is a matricial “sower’s bag” con- taining the mineral seeds, while nature, also seen as a sower’s bag, contains all the seeds of natural things. Each type of mineral grows according to its seed, in accordance with the speciicity of its type already programmed in the form of the tria prima contained in the seed. Its propagation takes place through the power and the preparation of the Creator. As a plant seed bears its fruits in the harvest season, the mineral seed also bears its mineral fruits in the term biologically predetermined by God.32 The development of each individual mineral is simply the organic unfolding of that which is contained in the seed from the very beginning. The pre- dominant idea is that of “predestination” (praedestinatio).33 This is

31 - De mineralibus (Huser, VIII, 343-344 = Sudhoff, III, 41-42): “Als wan einer het in einem sack durch einander aller der samen, so nun auf der welt seind, bei einander. Und so ers nun in garten seet, so ist die natur do und gibt einem ietlichen samen sein eigne frucht zum end, also das ein ietlicher semen in sein wesen kompt und perfection, dem andern on schaden. Wie nun nicht alein hie also verstanden sol werden, sonder auch im element wasser, als wer es ein sack, in dem alle samen werent und würden geseet, so wechst ein ietlichs genus und species in sein art und eigensschaft. Also hat nun got verordnet die wunderwerk seiner geschöpf in die vier elementen. Und das seind element, aus dem die frücht gên, als das dan der mensch gebrauchen sol, und von got geschaffen, ein ietliche art in ir eigenschaft und wesen.” 32 - Paracelsus, De mineralibus (Huser, VIII, 337 = Sudhoff, III, 35). 33 - Paracelsus, De mineralibus (Huser, VIII, 343 = Sudhoff, III, 41). See also Goldammer, Paracelsus: Natur und Offenbarung, 41; Pagel, Paracelsus: An Introduction, 95 and 118; Jean-Pierre Brach, “Quelques aspects de la doctrine de la prédestination chez Paracelse,” Aries 19 (1995): 20-25.

XII Document downloaded www.cairn-int.info - 213.49.84.124 07/10/2014 22h45. © Armand Colin Logoi Spermatikoi and the Concept of Seeds...

in conformance with the doctrine of logoi spermatikoi: the seed is the message-bearer of the speciicity of each mineral. It is possible to say that the seed is the “vehicle” of the tria prima that are imma- nent and dormant in the seed like genetic code.

On the one hand, it should be recalled that the tria prima of Paracelsus are spiritual, dynamic powers, akin to the doctrine of Plotinus, while also being immanent to matter as with the Stoics and the alchemists. On the other hand, it is uncontestable that Paracelsus’s “sower” is the Judeo-Christian God who sowed the primordial Word at the beginning of Creation. This biblical inspira- tion requires a different image of the world than that of the Stoics and Plotinus. In order to clarify this point, it would be necessary to examine the origin of the mineral seeds in turn, but Paracelsus does not tell any more on the subject in De mineralibus.

Document downloaded from www.cairn-int.info - 213.49.84.124 07/10/2014 22h45. © Armand Colin Seeds in Paracelsus’s Interpretation of Genesis Let us now examine Paracelsus’s other writings for additional infor- mation that might explain the origin of mineral seeds in the context of the biblical Creation. For instance, in the treatise De matrice, the fourth book of his Opus Paramirum (1531), Paracelsus states that all creatures were brought into being by the invisible matrix. In his view, the primordial waters over which the Spirit of the Lord hov- ered (Genesis 1:2) is the irst matrix (mother) of the world, that is, the irst receptacle for the seed of the world.34 Although the identity of this primordial seed of the world is not speciied, it is possible to assume that it is either the very Spirit of the Lord from Genesis, or what this Spirit conveys.

In the treatise entitled Labyrinthus medicorum errantium (1537- 1538), Paracelsus writes of the origin of the primordial seed in the context of the creatio ex nihilo. According to him, God created all things by bringing about “something” (etwas) out of “nothing” (nichts). He clearly identiies that “something” with seed.35 This “something” is speciied in The Book of the Generation and the Fruits of the Four Elements (date of writing unknown), in which Paracelsus says that in the beginning of Creation, that nothing was

34 - Paracelsus, De matrice, in Opus Paramirum IV (Sudhoff, IX, 191). 35 - Paracelsus, Labyrinthus medicorum errantium, chap. 5 (Huser, II, 213 = Sudhoff, XI, 187).

Revue d’histoire des sciences I Volume 61-2 I July-December 2008 XIII Document downloaded www.cairn-int.info - 213.49.84.124 07/10/2014 22h45. © Armand Colin Hiro HIRAI

transformed into the “great Iliaster” (großen Yliaster).36 To him, this spiritual Iliaster consisted of four parts that developed into the four matricial elements through the intervention of the tria prima. Hence, the initial Iliaster is the seed of these four elements, and is the “something” in question. He further states that minerals already existed in the Iliaster, even though they were not yet formed. Likewise, the seeds of natural things were contained in the four elements.37 Hence, the archetypes of mineral seeds already resided in the seeds of the four elements, i.e., in the Iliaster.

Finally, in the treatise De meteoris (date of writing uncertain), Paracelsus develops this point around the notion of the primor- dial Word of God based on his interpretation of Genesis. In his view, the body of each element was created out of nothing simply by the Word “iat” of God. Through this Word, this nothing, out of which “something” was created, became the substantial body

Document downloaded from www.cairn-int.info - 213.49.84.124 07/10/2014 22h45. © Armand Colin of the element. To Paracelsus, each element has a ternary body due to the tria prima, just as the Word “iat” is a ternary entity that corresponds to the Holy Trinity.38 Here, it is clear that Paracelsus is referring to the theological concept of the Word of God accord- ing to which this Word was with God at the beginning and was sown in the form of “iat” as the seed of the world.39 To Paracelsus, God created the seed of the elements out of nothing through the Word of God. This seed then turned into four elements, which contained all creatures in seminal form, i.e., the seeds of things. Previously, these seeds were in the seeds of the elements, and originally in the Word of God, the seed of the world, not created but co-eternal with God.

36 - Paracelsus, Philosophia de generationibus et fructibus quatuor elementorum, I, i (Huser, VIII, 55 = Sudhoff, XIII, 9) and III, 1, i (Huser, VIII, 97 = Sudhoff, XIII, 56). 37 - Paracelsus, Philosophia de generationibus, I, vi (Huser, VIII, 58 = Sudhoff, XIII, 12-13). 38 - Paracelsus, De meteoris, ii (Huser, VIII, 184-186 = Sudhoff, XIII, 134-136). On Paracelsus’s cosmology and his doctrine of the Trinity see Hartmut Rudolph, “Kosmosspekulation und Trinitätslehre: Ein Beitrag zur Beziehung zwischen Weltbild und Theologie bei Paracelsus,” Salzburger Beiträge zur Paracelsusforchung 21 (1980): 32-47. 39 - On the doctrine of the Word (Logos), see for instance Jules Lebreton, “Les théories du Logos au début de l’ère chrétienne,” Études 106 (1906): 54-84, 310-332 and 764- 795; Jules Lebreton, Histoire du dogme de la Trinité vol. I, Les Origines du dogme de la Trinité (Paris: Beauchesne, 1919); Spanneut, Permanence du stoïcisme, 295-323; Charles H. Dodd, The Interpretation of the Fourth Gospel (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1953), 263-285; Marie-Émile Boismard, Le Prologue de saint Jean (Paris: Cerf, 1953), 15-21 and 109-142; Charles K. Barrett, The Gospel According to St. John (London: SPCK, 1956), 126-141.

XIV Document downloaded www.cairn-int.info - 213.49.84.124 07/10/2014 22h45. © Armand Colin Logoi Spermatikoi and the Concept of Seeds...

There are therefore three major steps in this unfolding of seeds: 1) Word-seed, 2) seeds of the elements, and 3) particular seeds of natural things. It should be recalled that according to Augustine, the “unchangeable and eternal reasons” (rationes incommutabiles et aeternae), the archetypes of seminal reasons, of all creatures were irst in the Word of God.40

Although Augustine did not say as such, it is possible to understand that even minerals that have not yet been created and are eternal were in the Word of God in a state of “unchangeable and eternal reasons.” Here is an important passage from his treatise The Literal Meaning of Genesis, which elucidates this seminal unfolding:

Nevertheless, under one aspect these things are in the Word of God, where they are not made but eternally existing; under another aspect they are in the elements of the universe, where all things destined to be were made simultaneously [. . .]; under Document downloaded from www.cairn-int.info - 213.49.84.124 07/10/2014 22h45. © Armand Colin another aspect they are in seeds, in which they are found again as quasi-primordial causes which derive from creatures that have come forth according to the causes which God irst stored up in the world [. . .].

In all these things, beings already created received at their own proper time their manner of being and of acting, which developed into visible forms and natures from the hidden and invisible rea- sons which are latent in creation as causes. Thus the crops came forth on the earth, and man was made as a living being, and so of the other creatures, whether plants or animals, belonging to the work of God as He works even at this time. But these beings have duplicates of themselves, as it were, carried invisibly within them by reason of the hidden power of reproduction that they possess. They have this power through their primordial causes, in which they were placed in the created world when day was made, before they came forth in the visible shape proper to their kind.41

Although Augustine only gives living beings as examples of crea- tures, it should be recalled that with Paracelsus everything that grows has a kind of life force in the form of the spiritus vitae. The above quote from Augustine can therefore also apply to the min- eral kingdom. Granted, it is very dificult to say whether Augustine

40 - , De Genesi ad litteram V, xii, 29, trans. John Hammond Taylor (Mahwah, NJ: Paulist Press, 1982), 163. 41 - Augustine, De Genesi VI, x, 17, 189-90.

Revue d’histoire des sciences I Volume 61-2 I July-December 2008 XV Document downloaded www.cairn-int.info - 213.49.84.124 07/10/2014 22h45. © Armand Colin Hiro HIRAI

was a direct source of inspiration to Paracelsus,42 but the way in which Augustine describes the will of God being transmitted over time from Creation to today by means of seminal reasons is similar to the way in which the seeds of things act according to Paracelsus. Likewise, both Augustine’s seminal reasons and Paracelsus’s seeds originate in the Word of God, and the biblical Creation acts as a common framework for both systems. From that point on we notice many similarities.

The Intermediary Role of Marsilio Ficino In closing, let us examine a point that has been little studied by historians to date. It was through the Latin translation by Marsilio Ficino of Florence (1433-1499) that Renaissance scholars were able to read the teachings of Plotinus for the irst time.43 It is natu- ral to assume that the writings of Plotinus would favor a revival in

Document downloaded from www.cairn-int.info - 213.49.84.124 07/10/2014 22h45. © Armand Colin the doctrine of logoi spermatikoi, but Ficino’s own writings contain a singular elaboration of the Plotinian concept.

In order to refer to the seminal principle in his cosmological , Ficino amply used multiple terms, including “seeds of things” (semina rerum), “seeds of forms” (semina formarum), “seminal reasons” (rationes seminales), “seminary of the world” (seminarium mundi), and “seminal reason of the world” (ratio sem- inaria mundi). Already in the Commentary on Plato’s Symposium (written between 1468 and 1482 and published in Florence in 1484), Ficino developed his concept of seed and established the hierarchy of hypostatic substances based especially on Plotinus and Proclus.44

42 - De Genesi ad litteram was published by Johann Amerbach in Basel in 1506, then by Johann Froben, under the direction of Erasmus of Rotterdam, in Basel in 1528. 43 - On Ficino, see Paul O. Kristeller, The Philosophy of Marsilio Ficino (New York: Columbia University Press, 1943); Raymond Marcel, Marsile Ficin (Paris: Belles Lettres, 1958); Gian Carlo Garfagnini (ed.), Marsilio Ficino e il ritorno di Platone (Florence: Olschki, 1986); Michael J. B. Allen and Valery Rees (eds.), Marsilio Ficino: His , His Philosophy, His Legacy (Leiden: Brill, 2002). 44 - On Ficino’s ive hypostases, see especially Kristeller, The Philosophy of Marsilio Ficino, 106-108, 167-169, 370, 384, 400-401; Michael J. B. Allen, “Ficino’s Theory of the Five Substances and the Neoplatonists’ Parmenides,” Journal of Medieval and Renaissance Studies 12 (1982): 19-44; Tamara Albertini, Marsilio Ficino: Das Problem der Vermittlung von Denken und Welt in einer Metaphysik der Einfachheit (Munich: Fink, 1997).

XVI Document downloaded www.cairn-int.info - 213.49.84.124 07/10/2014 22h45. © Armand Colin Logoi Spermatikoi and the Concept of Seeds...

According to Ficino, after transcendental God, whose substance is at the center of the universe, comes divine Intelligence. From this Intelligence emanates the soul of the world, surrounding it. From the soul of the world comes nature, and from nature the body or matter with its full extension. Thus, the metaphysical universe is made up of the ive hypostatic substances, which are arranged con- centrically and are connected by the “divine species” (species div- inae). The archetypical Idea can be found in the Good, which is the substance of God. From this come the “ideas” (ideae) that connect God to the divine Intelligence. The Intelligence and the soul of the world communicate through the “reason-principles” (rationes) that leave the Intelligence and enter the soul. The soul and nature are connected through the mediation of the “seeds” (semina). Finally, nature and matter communicate through “forms” (formae).45 These divine species (ideas, reason-principles, seeds, and forms) share a common source and nature is full of invisible seeds. Document downloaded from www.cairn-int.info - 213.49.84.124 07/10/2014 22h45. © Armand Colin Then, in his Platonic Theology on the Immortality of Souls (Florence, 1482), Ficino admitted the seeds of forms hidden in the prime, formless matter.46 According to Ficino, the life force of these “spir- itual and life-giving seeds” (semina spiritualia et viviica) that com- pensates for the lack of corporeal seeds, draws the substantial forms of the elements from the bosom of formless matter.47 Then, in De vita coelitus comparanda, the third book of De vita libri tres, a work that was widely read and highly inluential in the sixteenth century, Ficino, much like Plotinus, advanced the idea of seminal reasons located in the soul of the world (anima mundi). The passage reads:

Moreover, the soul of the world, by its divine power, has at least as many seminal reasons as there are ideas in the divine intelligence. By means of these seminal reasons, it produces the same number of species in matter. This is why each species corresponds to its own idea through its own seminal reason. And often, through this special reason, it can easily receive something of the idea, if it was produced from the idea through this reason. This is why, if at any moment a species degenerates in its form, it can be formed once

45 - Marsilio Ficino, Commentary on Plato’s Symposium on Love, II, iii-iv, in the Latin text edited by Raymond Marcel: Marsile Ficin, Commentaire sur le Banquet de Platon (Paris: Les Belles Lettres, 1956), 149-151. 46 - Marsilio Ficino, Platonic Theology, I, vi, transl. Michael J. B. Allen and John Warden (Boston: Harvard University Press, 2001). 47 - Ficino, Platonic Theology, IV, i.

Revue d’histoire des sciences I Volume 61-2 I July-December 2008 XVII Document downloaded www.cairn-int.info - 213.49.84.124 07/10/2014 22h45. © Armand Colin Hiro HIRAI

more through this intermediary reason, very close to it, and easily reformed by this intermediary of the idea.48

De vita coelitus comparanda was originally intended to be a com- mentary on Plotinus’s Ennead IV, 3, 11, but Ficino only published the Commentary on Plotinus’s Enneads (Florence, 1492) much later. In this work, he amply applied the seminal principle to his cosmology. He wrote that, through the seminal reasons, the world receives everywhere its generative power from the soul of the world. Hence, nature contains in itself as many seeds as things.49

This frequent use of the concept of seeds is remarkable. This fea- ture is primarily Plotinian, with certain modiications due to some fairly heterogeneous ideas. According to Brian P. Copenhaver, Ficino certainly linked the theory of logoi spermatikoi to Thomas Aquinas’s doctrine of the substantial form.50 From my side, I have

Document downloaded from www.cairn-int.info - 213.49.84.124 07/10/2014 22h45. © Armand Colin shown in a previous study that he also adopted the notion of the “seeds of things” (semina rerum) from atomist Lucretius (c. 98-55 B.C.). In addition, we know that Augustine was one of Ficino’s favorite authors, although Ficino did not mention him in con- nection with his concept of seeds; his work drew more on that of Plotinus.51 What is particularly signiicant from our point of view, however, is the fact that Ficino advanced the idea of the omnipres- ence of invisible, spiritual seeds in nature throughout his writings.

It should be recalled that in De vita coelitus comparanda, Ficino also expounded his famous theory of the spiritus mundi, which became immensely successful in the sixteenth century. It was to

48 - Marsilio Ficino, De Vita Libri Tres, III, i (Carol V. Kaske and John R. Clark, Marsilio Ficino: Three Books On Life [New York: Renaissance Society of America, 1989], 242): “Accedit ad haec quod anima mundi totidem saltem rationes rerum seminales divinitus habet, quot ideae sunt in mente divina, quibus ipsa rationibus totidem fabricat species in materia. Unde unaquaeque species per propriam rationem seminalem propriae re- spondet ideae, facileque potest per hanc saepe aliquid illinc accipere, quandoquidem per hanc illinc est effecta. Ideoque si quando a propria forma degeneret, potest hoc medio sibi proximo formari rursum perque id medium inde facile reformari.” 49 - Marsilio Ficino, Opera Omnia (Basel, 1575), 1634, 1640, 1697 and 1737. 50 - See Brian P. Copenhaver, “Renaissance Magic and Neoplatonic Philosophy: Ennead 4. 3-5 in Ficino’s De vita coelitus comparanda,” in Garfagnini, Marsilio Ficino e il ritorno di Platone, vol. II, 351-369. 51 - On Ficino’s concept of seeds, see Hiro Hirai, “Concepts of Seeds and Nature in the Work of Marsilio Ficino,” in Allen and Rees, Marsilio Ficino, 257-84; Hiro Hirai, “La fortune du concept de semence de Marsile Ficin au XVIe siècle,” Accademia: Revue de la société Marsile Ficin 4 (2002): 109-32.

XVIII Document downloaded www.cairn-int.info - 213.49.84.124 07/10/2014 22h45. © Armand Colin Logoi Spermatikoi and the Concept of Seeds...

this universal spiritus of the world that he attributed a “seminary power” (virtus seminaria), derived from the seminal reasons of the soul of the world, through the heavens and their constellations. According to Ficino, whoever knows things that are “spirituous,” i.e., things rich in spiritus, that smell good, shine, or are warm, can effectively beneit from the gifts of heaven through the semi- nal reasons, which coordinate the ideas of the divine Intelligence. Thus, he advanced the possibility of capturing, even of manipu- lating, the seminary power conveyed by the spiritus that is also in natural things. He bases these notions in particular on the idea of quintessence, which originates from the tradition of pseudo-Lull- ian alchemy of the late Middle Ages.52 This approach to the natu- ral domains through the central notion of alchemia medica would clearly favor a good reception of his theory of the spiritus mundi with natural philosophers and doctors who were familiar with the thought of Paracelsus.53 Document downloaded from www.cairn-int.info - 213.49.84.124 07/10/2014 22h45. © Armand Colin Conclusion Although the biological aspect of Paracelsus’s mineralogy shows several hylozoist elements inluenced by medieval alchemy and the beliefs of miners, his concept of seeds falls largely under the interpretation of the biblical Creation story.54 According to

52 - See Sylvain Matton, “Marsile Ficin et l’alchimie, sa position, son inluence,” in Alchimie et philosophie à la Renaissance, ed. Jean-Claude Margolin and Sylvain Matton (Paris: Vrin, 1993), 123-192. On the idea of quintessence during the Middle Ages, see Robert Halleux, “Les ouvrages alchimiques de Jean de Rupescissa,” Histoire littéraire de la France 41(1981): 241-277; Michela Pereira, The Alchemical Corpus Attributed to Raymond Lull (London: Warburg, 1989); Udo Benzenhöfer, Johannes’ de Rupescissa Liber de consideratione quintae essentiae omnium rerum deutsch: Studien zur Alchemia medica des 15. bis 17. Jahrhunderts (Stuttgart: Steiner, 1989). 53 - On Ficino’s inluence on Paracelsus, see Pagel, Paracelsus: An Introduction, 174-177 and 218-226; Kurt Goldammer, “Die Paracelsische Kosmologie und Materietheorie in ihrer wissenschaftsgeschichtlichen Stellung und Eigenart,” Medizinhistorisches Journal 6(1971): 5-35; Ingo Schütze, “Zur Ficino-Rezeption bei Paracelsus,” in Joachim Telle (ed.), Parerga Paracelsica: Paracelsus in Vergangenheit und Gegenwart (Stuttgart: Steiner, 1991), 39-44. 54 - On the tradition of “chemical” interpretation of Genesis, see Michael T. Walton, “Genesis and chemistry in the sixteenth century,” in Reading the Book of Nature, ed. Allan G. Debus and Michael T.Walton (Kirksville: SCJ, 1998), 1-14; Norma E. Emerton, “Creation in the thought of J. B. Van Helmont and Robert Fludd,” in Rattansi and Clericuzio, “The Internal Laboratory,” 85-101; Hiro Hirai, “Paracelsisme, néoplatonisme et médecine hermétique dans la théorie de la matière de Joseph Du Chesne à travers son Ad ver- itatem hermeticae medicinae (1604),” Archives internationales d’histoire des sciences 51(2001): 9-37; Id., “Interprétation chymique de la création et origine corpusculaire de la vie chez Athanasius Kircher,” Annals of Science 64 (2007): 217-234.

Revue d’histoire des sciences I Volume 61-2 I July-December 2008 XIX Document downloaded www.cairn-int.info - 213.49.84.124 07/10/2014 22h45. © Armand Colin Hiro HIRAI

Paracelsus, God created the minerals in order for them to be born daily from their own seeds. These mineral seeds reside in the ele- ment water, which is their matrix. The seeds are the vehicles for the set of the tria prima (Sulfur, Salt, and Mercury). At the time of Creation, they were latent in the seed of the four elements (the Iliaster), which, in turn, was created out of nothing through the Word “iat” of God. This Word, which was not created but coe- ternal, was sown by God as the universal seed of the world at the beginning of Creation. It is clear that Paracelsus relied on the notion of the Word-seed of God as it originated in Christian theol- ogy. We have seen a very similar idea to that of Paracelsus in the theory of Augustine concerning the seminal unfolding from the primordial Word of God to the particular seeds of natural things. Even though Paracelsus did not directly know about the teachings of Augustine, the long Augustinian tradition likely provided him with the essential ingredients for developing his concept in the

Document downloaded from www.cairn-int.info - 213.49.84.124 07/10/2014 22h45. © Armand Colin context of biblical cosmogony.

Before Paracelsus, Marsilio Ficino adopted Plotinus’s idea of the seminal principle, which was derived from the Stoic doctrine of logoi spermatikoi. He developed it considerably in establishing his concept of seeds in his own philosophical writings. His cosmolog- ical metaphysics is characterized by the omnipresence of invisible, spiritual seeds in nature. This omnipresence of spiritual seeds is close to Paracelsus’s vision, although in principle Ficino’s theory still has its roots in the writings of Plotinus.

One may assume that Paracelsus was initially inspired by Ficino regarding this omnipresence of invisible, spiritual seeds in the same way as his contemporary, Jean Fernel (1497-1558), who conceived Ficino’s seeds as the instruments of the Word of God, who, as the “sower,” introduced procreative power into the sublunar world by means of these divine seeds. However, Fernel did not go so far as to identify this Word with the seed of the world.55 Preoccupied with interpreting the Creation story of Genesis, Paracelsus established

55 - See Hirai, Le concept, 83-103; Hirai, “Ficin, Fernel et Fracastor autour du concept de semence: Aspects platoniciens de seminaria,” in Girolamo Fracastoro fra medicina, ilosoia e scienze della natura, ed. Alessandro Pastore and Enrico Peruzzi (Florence: Olschki, 2006), 245-260. On Fernel’s Ficinism, see also Hiro Hirai, “Alter Galenus: Jean Fernel et son interprétation platonico-chrétienne de Galien,” Early Science and Medicine 10 (2005): 1-35.

XX Document downloaded www.cairn-int.info - 213.49.84.124 07/10/2014 22h45. © Armand Colin Logoi Spermatikoi and the Concept of Seeds...

his concept of seeds in a much more Christian framework. In my view, this is the result of the Christianization of the logoi sperma- tikoi after the manner of Augustine. Thus, the Paracelsian concept of seeds testiies to the complexity of the paths by which the themes of Stoic physics were included in writings as late as the sixteenth century, when they came to fruition. Document downloaded from www.cairn-int.info - 213.49.84.124 07/10/2014 22h45. © Armand Colin

Revue d’histoire des sciences I Volume 61-2 I July-December 2008 XXI Document downloaded www.cairn-int.info - 213.49.84.124 07/10/2014 22h45. © Armand Colin