An Emergentist Coalition Model for the Origins of Word Learning Author(S): George J

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

An Emergentist Coalition Model for the Origins of Word Learning Author(S): George J Breaking the Language Barrier: An Emergentist Coalition Model for the Origins of Word Learning Author(s): George J. Hollich, Kathy Hirsh-Pasek, Roberta Michnick Golinkoff, Rebecca J. Brand, Ellie Brown, He Len Chung, Elizabeth Hennon, Camille Rocroi and Lois Bloom Source: Monographs of the Society for Research in Child Development, Vol. 65, No. 3, Breaking the Language Barrier: An Emergentist Coalition Model for the Origins of Word Learning (2000), pp. i-vi+1-135 Published by: Wiley on behalf of the Society for Research in Child Development Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3181533 Accessed: 16-05-2016 20:50 UTC Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://about.jstor.org/terms JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Wiley, Society for Research in Child Development are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Monographs of the Society for Research in Child Development This content downloaded from 128.175.197.251 on Mon, 16 May 2016 20:50:43 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms MONOGRAPHS OF THE SOCIETY FOR RESEARCH IN CHILD DEVELOPMENT Serial No. 262, Vol. 65, No. 3, 2000 BREAKING THE LANGUAGE BARRIER: AN EMERGENTIST COALITION MODEL FOR THE ORIGINS OF WORD LEARNING George J. Hollich Kathy Hirsh-Pasek Roberta Michnick Golinkoff IN COLLABORATION WITH Rebecca J. Brand Ellie Brown He Len Chung Elizabeth Hennon Camille Rocroi WITH COMMENTARY BY Lois Bloom This content downloaded from 128.175.197.251 on Mon, 16 May 2016 20:50:43 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms II This content downloaded from 128.175.197.251 on Mon, 16 May 2016 20:50:43 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms MONOGRAPHS OF THE SOCIETY FOR RESEARCH IN CHILD DEVELOPMENT Serial No. 262, Vol. 65, No. 3, 2000 CONTENTS ABSTRACT v I. WHAT DOES IT TAKE TO LEARN A WORD? 1 II. THE EMERGENTIST COALITION MODEL 17 III. THE INTERACTIVE INTERMODAL PREFERENTIAL LOOKING PARADIGM Camille Rocroi 30 IV. LEARNING NOVEL NOUNS: CHILDREN USE MULTIPLE CUES Rebecca J. Brand 41 V. WHAT DOES IT TAKE FOR 12-MONTH-OLDS TO LEARN A WORD? Elizabeth Hennon, He Len Chung, and Ellie Brown 62 VI. IS 12-MONTH-OLD WORD LEARNING DOMAIN-GENERAL, SOCIALLY DETERMINED, OR EMERGENT? 85 VII. GENERAL DISCUSSION 101 REFERENCES 115 ACKNOWLEDGMENTS 123 COMMENTARY PUSHING THE LIMITS ON THEORIES OF WORD LEARNING Lois Bloom 124 CONTRIBUTORS 136 STATEMENT OF EDITORIAL POLICY 138 This content downloaded from 128.175.197.251 on Mon, 16 May 2016 20:50:43 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms IV This content downloaded from 128.175.197.251 on Mon, 16 May 2016 20:50:43 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms ABSTRACT HOLLICH, GEORGE J.; HIRSH-PASEK, KATHY; and GOLINKOFF, ROBERTA MICHNICK; in collaboration with BRAND, REBECCA J.; BROWN, ELLIE; CHUNG, HE LEN; HENNON, ELIZABETH; and ROCROI, CAMILLE. Breaking the Language Barrier: An Emergentist Coalition Model of the Origins of Word Learning. Monographs of the Society for Research in Child Development, 2000, 65(3, Serial No. 262). How do children learn their first words? The field of language de- velopment has been polarized by responses to this question. Explana- tions range from constraints/principles accounts that emphasize the importance of cognitive heuristics in language acquisition, to social- pragmatic accounts that highlight the role of parent-child interaction, to associationistic accounts that highlight the role of "dumb attentional mechanisms" in word learning. In this Monograph, an alternative to these accounts is presented: the emergentist coalition theory. A hybrid view of word learning, this theory characterizes lexical acquisition as the emergent product of multiple factors, including cognitive con- straints, social-pragmatic factors, and global attentional mechanisms. The model makes three assumptions: (a) that children cull from multi- ple inputs available for word learning at any given time, (b) that these inputs are differentially weighted over development, and (c) that chil- dren develop emergent principles of word learning, which guide sub- sequent word acquisition. With few exceptions, competing accounts of the word learning process have examined children who are already vet- eran word learners. By focusing on the very beginnings of word learning at around 12 months of age, however, it is possible to see how social and cognitive factors are coordinated in the process of vocabulary devel- opment. After presenting a new method for investigating word learning, the development of reference is used as a test case of the theory. In 12 experiments, with children ranging in age from 12 to 25 months of age, data are described that support the emergentist coalition model. This V This content downloaded from 128.175.197.251 on Mon, 16 May 2016 20:50:43 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms HOLLICH ET AL. fundamentally developmental theory posits that children construct prin- ciples of word learning. As children's word learning principles emerge and develop, the character of word learning changes over the course of the 2nd year of life. VI This content downloaded from 128.175.197.251 on Mon, 16 May 2016 20:50:43 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms I. WHAT DOES IT TAKE TO LEARN A WORD? Before children can tie their shoes, they have mastered thousands of words. At the outset (around 12 months of age), the character of word learning is slow and laborious with infants producing, on average, only two words per week (Carey, 1978). By approximately 19 months of age, however, children's vocabulary rapidly expands as they transform into what Pinker (1994) referred to as "vacuum cleaners" for words, acquiring up to nine new words per day (Bloom, 1973; Clark, 1973; Nelson, 1973; Tem- plin, 1957). The challenge for developmental psychology is to understand how chil- dren break the language barrier with their first words and turn into mas- ter word learners within a year's time. There have been a number of responses to this challenge. The constraints/principles theories empha- size the importance of cognitive heuristics in word acquisition (e.g., Mark- man, 1989; Merriman & Bowman, 1989; Waxman & Kosowski, 1990). Children operate with a set of word learning biases that assist them in link- ing words to objects, actions, and events. The social-pragmatic view, in stark contrast, highlights the role of parent-child interaction in priming word learning. Parents attuned to the child's intent supply the word for the rel- evant object, action, or event, thereby facilitating the child's lexical devel- opment (Nelson, 1988). Furthermore, the social-pragmatists assert that children are fundamentally social creatures and do not come to the word learning task "blind" to the essentials of communication (Carpenter, Nagell, & Tomasello, 1998). Rather, the children's driving need to communicate is the force that propels them to understand the meaning of a novel word (Bloom, 1993). Finally, the newest response to the word learning chal- lenge is an associationistic account that highlights the role of "dumb at- tentional mechanisms" and memory processes. Children attach labels to the items that recruit their attention and stand out from the context. Cal- culating the frequency of co-occurrence between words and referents, chil- dren form the associations that constitute vocabulary acquisition (Plunkett, 1997; Smith, 1995, in press; Smith, Jones, & Landau, 1996). 1 This content downloaded from 128.175.197.251 on Mon, 16 May 2016 20:50:43 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms HOLLICH ET AL. While each of these potential answers to the word learning challenge seems plausible, we believe they are flawed in two ways. First, each em- phasizes a single mechanism that is responsible for lexical develop- ment. Second, despite the fact that the character of word learning changes over the 2nd year of life (e.g., Clark, 1993; Golinkoff, Mervis, & Hirsh-Pasek, 1994), data in support of these theories are often from chil- dren who have already amassed a large number of words. Mechanisms used by expert word learners might not be characteristic of those used by novice learners. To address these issues, in chapter 2, using these theories as a base, a new theory of word learning is presented, the emergentist coalition theory. The emergentist coalition theory offers a developmental account that ex- plains the shift in word learning from the 1-year-old to 2-year-old as a change in the weighting of multiple factors, including attentional, social, and linguistic factors. In subsequent chapters, we offer a new method for testing this theory (chapter 3), data that substantiate the theory for the development of the "principle of reference" (Golinkoff et al., 1994) (chap- ters 4-6), and a discussion of how this theory can further a more com- plete understanding of word learning by embracing a hybrid view of this complex process (chapter 7). The remainder of this chapter contains an overview of the various approaches and the polarizing effect they have had on the field. THEORIES OF WORD LEARNING Current theories of word learning have been polarized by emphasiz- ing a single word learning strategy to the relative exclusion of others (Golinkoff, Hirsh-Pasek, & Hollich, 1999; Hirsh-Pasek, Golinkoff, & Hol- lich, in press; Hollich, Hirsh-Pasek, Tucker, & Golinkoff, 2000; Woodward & Markman, 1998). Much of this polarization occurred in response to a philosophical conundrum introduced by Willard Quine (1960).
Recommended publications
  • An Example of Sharing Information Expressed with Vague Terms
    Talking about Forests: an Example of Sharing Information Expressed with Vague Terms Luc´ıa Gomez´ Alvarez´ a, Brandon Bennett a and Adam Richard-Bollans a a University of Leeds, The United Kingdom Abstract. Most natural language terms do not have precise universally agreed defi- nitions that fix their meanings. Even when conversation participants share the same vocabulary and agree on taxonomic relationships (such as subsumption and mutual exclusivity, which might be encoded in an ontology), they may differ greatly in the specific semantics they give to the terms. We illustrate this with the example of ‘forest’, for which the problematic arising of the assignation of different meanings is repeatedly reported in the literature. This is especially the case in the context of an unprecedented scale of publicly available geographic data, where information and databases, even when tagged to ontologies, may present a substantial semantic variation, which challenges interoperability and knowledge exchange. Our research addresses the issue of conceptual vagueness in ontology by pro- viding a framework based on supervaluation semantics that explicitly represents the semantic variability of a concept as a set of admissible precise interpretations. Moreover, we describe the tools that support the conceptual negotiation between an agent and the system, and the specification and reasoning within standpoints. Keywords. concept negotiation, supervaluation, standpoint, forest, GIS, vagueness 1. Introduction Since the shift in philosophy of language from logical positivism to behaviourism and pragmatism, it is widely accepted that most natural language terms do not have precise universally agreed definitions that fix their meanings. Even when conversation partici- pants share the same vocabulary and agree on taxonomic relationships (such as subsump- tion and mutual exclusivity, which might be encoded in an ontology), they may differ greatly in the specific semantics they give to the terms in a particular situation.
    [Show full text]
  • Jonah N. Schupbach: Curriculum Vitae
    Jonah N. Schupbach Department of Philosophy, University of Utah [email protected] 402 CTIHB, 215 S. Central Campus Drive jonahschupbach.com Salt Lake City, Utah 84112 (801) 585-5810 Areas of Specialization Areas of Competence Epistemology (including Formal Epistemology) Philosophy of Religion Logic Metaphysics Philosophy of Science Philosophy of Cognitive Science Appointments University of Utah Associate Professor (tenure granted 2017), Department of Philosophy, 2017–present. Assistant Professor, Department of Philosophy, 2011–2017. Tilburg University Visiting Fellow, Tilburg Center for Logic & Philosophy of Science (TiLPS), September 2008– June 2009. Education Ph.D. History & Philosophy of Science, University of Pittsburgh, 2011. Dissertation: Studies in the Logic of Explanatory Power (defended June 14, 2011). Co-directors: John Earman (Pittsburgh, HPS), Edouard Machery (Pittsburgh, HPS). M.A. Philosophy, Western Michigan University, 2006. M.A. Philosophy of Religion, Denver Seminary, 2004. B.S.E. Industrial Engineering, University of Iowa, 2001. Jonah N. Schupbach,Curriculum Vitae 2 Publications Books Conjunctive Explanations: The Nature, Epistemology, and Psychology of Explanatory Multiplicity. New York: Routledge (to appear in Routledge’s Studies in the Philosophy of Science series). Co-edited with David H. Glass. Bayesianism and Scientific Reasoning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press (to appear in Cambridge’s Elements in the Philosophy of Science series). Book Chapters “William Paley,” in Stewart Goetz and Charles Taliaferro (eds.), The Encyclopedia of Philosophy of Religion. Malden, MA: Wiley (forthcoming). “Inference to the Best Explanation, Cleaned Up and Made Respectable,” in Kevin McCain and Ted Poston (eds.), Best Explanations: New Essays on Inference to the Best Explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press, (2017): 39-61.
    [Show full text]
  • Between Foundation and Convention
    NCCU Philosophical Journal Vol.10 (July 2003), pp.35-74 ©Department of Philosophy, National Chengchi University Between Foundation and Convention: Carnap’s Evolution between Schlick and Neurath in the Vienna Circle Jeu-Jenq Yuann Tunghai University Abstract For long the foundationalist image of logical positivism has been considered a matter of course. And it is basically accepted that R. Carnap has a great deal to do with this traditional image. Recent researches reveal that this image is not entirely true; Carnap can be deemed as a conventionalist also when some key conceptions are understood from a different point of view. Indeed, by examining some Carnap’s works, we are urged to realize that his view of science is somehow situated somewhere between foundationalism and conventionalism. We argue in this paper that Carnap’s weaving situation can be comprehended by taking into account the discussions taking place in the Vienna Circle and notably the debates among R. 36 NCCU Philosopical Journal Vol.10 Carnap, M. Schlick, and O. Neurath. We intend to make it explicit that Carnap’s stance was first in line with that of Schlick’s foundationalism and then moved to a more conventionalist one under the influence of Neurath. By this argument, we intend to demonstrate the following two points: 1) Discussions in the Vienna Circle were far from unanimous; 2) Carnap’s stance containing ‘an ethical attitude of tolerance’ proceeded mainly under Neurath’s influence. Key Words: Foundationalism, Conventionalism, R. Carnap, M. Schlick, O. Neurath * Received April 06, 2003; accepted July 16, 2003 Proofreaders: Bing-Jie Li Between Foundation and Convention 37 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Consciousness, the Unconscious and Mathematical Modeling of Thinking
    entropy Article On “Decisions and Revisions Which a Minute Will Reverse”: Consciousness, The Unconscious and Mathematical Modeling of Thinking Arkady Plotnitsky Literature, Theory and Cultural Studies Program, Philosophy and Literature Program, Purdue University, West Lafayette, IN 47907, USA; [email protected] Abstract: This article considers a partly philosophical question: What are the ontological and epistemological reasons for using quantum-like models or theories (models and theories based on the mathematical formalism of quantum theory) vs. classical-like ones (based on the mathematics of classical physics), in considering human thinking and decision making? This question is only partly philosophical because it also concerns the scientific understanding of the phenomena considered by the theories that use mathematical models of either type, just as in physics itself, where this question also arises as a physical question. This is because this question is in effect: What are the physical reasons for using, even if not requiring, these types of theories in considering quantum phenomena, which these theories predict fully in accord with the experiment? This is clearly also a physical, rather than only philosophical, question and so is, accordingly, the question of whether one needs classical-like or quantum-like theories or both (just as in physics we use both classical and quantum theories) in considering human thinking in psychology and related fields, such as decision Citation: Plotnitsky, A. On science. It comes as no surprise that many of these reasons are parallel to those that are responsible “Decisions and Revisions Which a for the use of QM and QFT in the case of quantum phenomena.
    [Show full text]
  • In Press at Cognition. This File Is a Pre-Print and May Contain Errors Or Omissions Not Present in the Final Published Version
    In press at Cognition. This file is a pre-print and may contain errors or omissions not present in the final published version. Linguistic Conventionality and the Role of Epistemic Reasoning in Children’s Mutual Exclusivity Inferences Mahesh Srinivasan,1 Ruthe Foushee,1 Andrew Bartnof,1 & David Barner2 1University of California, Berkeley 2University of California, San Diego Please address correspondence to: Mahesh Srinivasan Department of Psychology University of California, Berkeley Berkeley, CA 94720-1650 Phone: 650-823-9488 Email: [email protected] Mutual Exclusivity and Conventionality Abstract To interpret an interlocutor’s use of a novel word (e.g., “give me the papaya”), children typically exclude referents that they already have labels for (like an “apple”), and expect the word to refer to something they do not have a label for (like the papaya). The goal of the present studies was to test whether such mutual exclusivity inferences require children to reason about the words their interlocutors know and could have chosen to say: e.g., If she had wanted the “apple” she would have asked for it (since she knows the word “apple”), so she must want the papaya. Across four studies, we document that both children and adults will make mutual exclusivity inferences even when they believe that their interlocutor does not share their knowledge of relevant, alternative words, suggesting that such inferences do not require reasoning about an interlocutor’s epistemic states. Instead, our findings suggest that children’s own knowledge of an object’s label, together with their belief that this is the conventional label for the object in their language, and that this convention applies to their interlocutor, is sufficient to support their mutual exclusivity inferences.
    [Show full text]
  • Exclusivity, Teleology and Hierarchy: Our Aristotelean Legacy
    Know!. Org. 26(1999)No.2 65 H.A. Olson: Exclusivity, Teleology and Hierarchy: Our Aristotelean Legacy Exclusivity, Teleology and Hierarchy: Our Aristotelean Legacy Hope A. Olson School of Library & Information Studies, University of Alberta Hope A. Olson is an Associate Professor and Graduate Coordinator in the School of Library and Information Studies at the University of Alberta in Edmonton, Alberta, Canada. She holds a PhD from the University of Wisconsin-Madison and MLS from the University of Toronto. Her re­ search is generally in the area of subject access to information with a focus on classification. She approaches this work using feminist, poststructural and postcolonial theory. Dr. Olson teaches organization of knowledge, cataloguing and classification, and courses examining issues in femi­ nism and in globalization and diversity as they relate to library and information studies. Olson, H.A. (1999). Exclusivity, Teleology and Hierarchy: Our Aristotelean Legacy. Knowl· edge Organization, 26(2). 65-73. 16 refs. ABSTRACT: This paper examines Parmenides's Fragments, Plato's The Sophist, and Aristotle's Prior AnalyticsJ Parts ofAnimals and Generation ofAnimals to identify three underlying presumptions of classical logic using the method of Foucauldian discourse analysis. These three presumptions are the notion of mutually exclusive categories, teleology in the sense of linear progression toward a goal, and hierarchy both through logical division and through the dominance of some classes over others. These three presumptions are linked to classificatory thought in the western tradition. The purpose of making these connections is to investi­ gate the cultural specificity to western culture of widespread classificatory practice. It is a step in a larger study to examine classi­ fication as a cultural construction that may be systemically incompatible with other cultures and with marginalized elements of western culture.
    [Show full text]
  • A Bayesian Framework for Cross-Situational Word-Learning
    A Bayesian Framework for Cross-Situational Word-Learning Michael C. Frank, Noah D. Goodman, and Joshua B. Tenenbaum Department of Brain and Cognitive Science Massachusetts Institute of Technology fmcfrank, ndg, [email protected] Abstract For infants, early word learning is a chicken-and-egg problem. One way to learn a word is to observe that it co-occurs with a particular referent across different situations. Another way is to use the social context of an utterance to infer the in- tended referent of a word. Here we present a Bayesian model of cross-situational word learning, and an extension of this model that also learns which social cues are relevant to determining reference. We test our model on a small corpus of mother-infant interaction and find it performs better than competing models. Fi- nally, we show that our model accounts for experimental phenomena including mutual exclusivity, fast-mapping, and generalization from social cues. To understand the difficulty of an infant word-learner, imagine walking down the street with a friend who suddenly says “dax blicket philbin na fivy!” while at the same time wagging her elbow. If you knew any of these words you might infer from the syntax of her sentence that blicket is a novel noun, and hence the name of a novel object. At the same time, if you knew that this friend indicated her attention by wagging her elbow at objects, you might infer that she intends to refer to an object in a nearby show window. On the other hand if you already knew that “blicket” meant the object in the window, you might be able to infer these elements of syntax and social cues.
    [Show full text]
  • Mutual Exclusivity in Autism Spectrum Disorders
    Cognition xxx (2011) xxx–xxx Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Cognition journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/COGNIT Mutual exclusivity in autism spectrum disorders: Testing the pragmatic hypothesis ⇑ Ashley de Marchena a, , Inge-Marie Eigsti a, Amanda Worek b, Kim Emiko Ono b, Jesse Snedeker b a Department of Psychology, University of Connecticut, Storrs, 406 Babbidge Road, Unit 1020, CT 06269, United States b Department of Psychology, Harvard University, 33 Kirkland Street, Cambridge, MA 02138, United States article info abstract Article history: While there is ample evidence that children treat words as mutually exclusive, the cogni- Received 25 November 2009 tive basis of this bias is widely debated. We focus on the distinction between pragmatic Revised 7 December 2010 and lexical constraints accounts. High-functioning children with autism spectrum disor- Accepted 20 December 2010 ders (ASD) offer a unique perspective on this debate, as they acquire substantial vocabular- Available online xxxx ies despite impoverished social-pragmatic skills. We tested children and adolescents with ASD in a paradigm examining mutual exclusivity for words and facts. Words were Keywords: interpreted contrastively more often than facts. Word performance was associated with Mutual exclusivity vocabulary size; fact performance was associated with social-communication skills. Thus Word learning Pragmatics mutual exclusivity does not appear to be driven by pragmatics, suggesting that it is either Autism a lexical constraint or a reflection of domain-general learning processes. Asperger’s syndrome Ó 2010 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved. 1. Introduction Smith, & Jones, 1988; Macnamara, 1982; Markman & Hutchinson, 1984). The experiments that followed demon- In Categorization and Naming in Children (1989), Ellen strated that young children do not learn words through Markman presented a set of questions and phenomena brute force associative learning; instead they approach that have fueled research on word learning for 20 years.
    [Show full text]
  • Mutual Exclusivity in Autism Spectrum Disorders: Testing the Pragmatic Hypothesis
    Mutual Exclusivity in Autism Spectrum Disorders: Testing the Pragmatic Hypothesis The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation De Marchena, Ashley, Inge-Marie Eigsti, Amanda Worek, Kim Emiko Ono, and Jesse Snedeker. 2010. Mutual exclusivity in autism spectrum disorders: testing the pragmatic hypothesis. Cognition 119(1): 96-113. Published Version doi:10.1016/j.cognition.2010.12.011 Citable link http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:5132922 Terms of Use This article was downloaded from Harvard University’s DASH repository, and is made available under the terms and conditions applicable to Open Access Policy Articles, as set forth at http:// nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:dash.current.terms-of- use#OAP Mutual Exclusivity 1 Running head: MUTUAL EXCLUSIVITY IN AUTISM Mutual Exclusivity in Autism Spectrum Disorders: Testing the Pragmatic Hypothesis Ashley de Marchena University of Connecticut, Storrs Inge-Marie Eigsti University of Connecticut, Storrs Amanda Worek Harvard University Kim Emiko Ono Harvard University Jesse Snedeker Harvard University Mutual Exclusivity 2 Abstract While there is ample evidence that children treat words as mutually exclusive, the cognitive basis of this bias is widely debated. We focus on the distinction between pragmatic and lexical constraints accounts. High-functioning children with autism spectrum disorders (ASD) offer a unique perspective on this debate, as they acquire substantial vocabularies despite impoverished social-pragmatic skills. We tested children and adolescents with ASD in a paradigm examining mutual exclusivity for words and facts. Words were interpreted contrastively more often than facts. Word performance was associated with vocabulary size; fact performance was associated with social-communication skills.
    [Show full text]
  • CONTRASTIVE BAYESIANISM 1. What Is
    2 BRANDEN FITELSON Hopefully, this will give some sense of how “Bayesian philosophers” (broadly con- strued) think about “contrastivism” and its philosophical significance. To this end, I will examine several recent case studies from the contemporary literature on CONTRASTIVE BAYESIANISM Bayesian confirmation theory, which, as we shall see, is implicated in Bayesian phi- losophy of science, Bayesian epistemology, and Bayesian cognitive science. BRANDEN FITELSON 3. Likelihoodism, Bayesianism, and Contrastive Confirmation Abstract. Bayesianism provides a rich theoretical framework, which lends itself It is useful to begin with a discussion of a prominent “contrastivist” probabilis- rather naturally to the explication of various “contrastive” and “non-contrastive” concepts. In this (brief) discussion, I will focus on issues involving “contrastivism”, tic account that has appeared in contemporary philosophy of science. This will as they arise in some of the recent philosophy of science, epistemology, and cog- simultaneously set the theoretical stage for subsequent sections, and illustrate a nitive science literature surrounding Bayesian confirmation theory. concrete example of “contrastivism” in (broadly) Bayesian philosophy of science. Elliott Sober has been defending what he calls “contrastive empiricism” (CE) for over 20 years. In his original statement and defense of (CE), Sober [44] explains: . theory testing is a contrastive activity. If you want to test a theory T , 1. What is “Bayesianism”? you must specify a range of alternatives — you must say what you want to test T against. There is a trivial reading of this thesis that I do not intend. I.J. Good [19] once estimated that there are 46,656 varieties of Bayesianism. He To find out if T is plausible is simply to find out if T is more plausible based his estimate on a number of “dimensions” along which different sorts of than not-T .
    [Show full text]
  • Retribution's Role. John Bronsteen Loyola University Chicago, [email protected]
    Loyola University Chicago, School of Law LAW eCommons Faculty Publications & Other Works 2009 Retribution's Role. John Bronsteen Loyola University Chicago, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://lawecommons.luc.edu/facpubs Part of the Criminal Law Commons Recommended Citation Bronsteen, John, Retribution's Role, 84 Indiana L.J. 1129 (2009). This Article is brought to you for free and open access by LAW eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Publications & Other Works by an authorized administrator of LAW eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Retribution's Role JOHN BRONSTEEN* Two main types of principle, retributive and consequentialist, have long been identified as the main approaches to justifying criminalpunishment. Retributivists deem punishment justified by the wrongdoing of the offender, whereas utilitarians deem itjustfied by its good consequences such as deterringfuture crime. Over the pastfifty years, each has spent decades as the dominant theory, and many hybrid theories have also been advanced. But few, if any, of the hybrid approaches have valued heavily both retributiveand consequentialistconsiderations while locatingthe particularjustificatoryrole each categoryplays. This Article points in that direction by reframing the central question ofpunishmentjustification as two questions: Why does the state have a right to punish, and why does it choose to exercise that right? The first question is answered most naturally by retributive considerations,whereas the second identifies the most naturalspace for utilitarianvalues. Thisframing device, it is hoped, resolves some of the disputes between retributivistsand utilitarianswhile sharpeningthe focus on those that remain. INTRODUCTION What gives a state the right to imprison a person? The simplest answer is that the person broke the law.
    [Show full text]
  • Three Models of Legal Ethics Anthony D'amato Northwestern University School of Law, [email protected]
    Northwestern University School of Law Northwestern University School of Law Scholarly Commons Faculty Working Papers 2010 Three Models of Legal Ethics Anthony D'Amato Northwestern University School of Law, [email protected] Edward J. Eberle Roger Williams School of Law Repository Citation D'Amato, Anthony and Eberle, Edward J., "Three Models of Legal Ethics" (2010). Faculty Working Papers. Paper 73. http://scholarlycommons.law.northwestern.edu/facultyworkingpapers/73 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Northwestern University School of Law Scholarly Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Working Papers by an authorized administrator of Northwestern University School of Law Scholarly Commons. Three Models of Legal Ethics, by Anthony D'Amato* and Edward J. Eberle** 27 Saint Louis University Law Journal, pp.761-799 (1983) Abstract: This article presents a picture of each of the three theoretical models—autonomy, socialist, and deontological—and indicates how they differ from one another in their application to some aspects of attorney- client confidentiality, one of the most hotly debated topics of professional ethics. Tags: legal ethics, ethical theory, attorney-client confidentiality, professional ethics, Model Rules of Professional Conduct, Model Code, Lawyers’ Code of Conduct [pg761]“Any occupation or profession is unworthy if it requires of us that we do as a functionary what we would be ashamed to do as a private person."—Sydney J. Harris TABLE OF CONTENTS I. INTRODUCTION 762 II. THREE MODELS OF LEGAL ETHICS 764 A. The Autonomy Model 764 1. Description 764 2. Critique 765 B. The Socialist Model 770 1.
    [Show full text]