Chomsky's Lost Dialogue

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Chomsky's Lost Dialogue teorema Vol. XXVIII/1, 2009, pp. 191-197 [BIBLID 0210-1602 (2009) 28:1; pp. 191-197] Chomsky’s Lost Dialogue Cedric Boeckx and Ángel J. Gallego Pies y Cabeza. Una introducción a la sintaxis minimalista, de JUAN URIAGEREKA, traducción de JUAN ROMERO MORALES. MADRID, ANTONIO MACHADO LIBROS, 2005, 906 pp., 37,50 € (Versión original: Rhyme and rea- son. An introduction to minimalist syntax, Cambridge, MA., MIT Press, 1998.) The Socratic dialogues we owe to Plato are standardly described as an inquiry strategy whereby a questioner (who knows a lot, but pretends not to) explores the implications of others’ positions to promote rational thinking and spark the mind. Juan Uriagereka’s Pies y Cabeza (PyC) goes back precisely to such tradition (which includes Galileo and Hume), combining old and new methods to offer the reader a piece that guides her in a journey through the most defining property of human beings: language (or, as Noam Chomsky called it, the faculty of language). That is certainly the aim of PyC, but the re- sult is not quite that, since Uriagereka’s book is something else entirely. On the surface, PyC is an exploration of the faculty of language (FL) from the innatist perspective stemming from Chomskyan theorizing. The book contains a detailed discussion (molded as a dialogue between the Lin- guist – Socrates’ questioner– and the Other) that reviews the key aspects be- hind Chomsky’s thesis that language is an innate capacity, genetically encoded – an ‘organ’ or ‘faculty’, as just said. These aspects include well- known topics, like how language is acquired and put to use by children (re- viewing along the way key concepts such as critical period, poverty of stimu- lus, negative data, triggering, etc.), how language varies (both in the individual, and in time and space), or how many of the patterns of language can be found in other natural phenomena (plant growth, animal skeleton, etc.) The Linguist and the Other spend pages and pages (615, to be precise) discussing the architecture of FL and its interaction with other cognitive modules (known as sensorimotor and conceptual-intentional systems). As- suming the so-called Principles and Parameters framework, this odd couple (imagine Chomsky and Borges at a table) dedicate 6 entire days discussing both the philosophical foundations and technical details of generative grammar, 191 192 Cedric Boeckx and Ángel J. Gallego with intricate explorations of topics that have been in the linguistic arena for decades (e.g. movement, islands, cycles, phrase structure, morphology). PyC’s dialectic structure is coupled with continuous references and smooth jumps into other fields (physics, chemistry, philosophy, biology, art, etc.). The impression one has (certainly the impression we had) is not that of reading a linguistics textbook, but that of reading a book of sand where every- thing appears to be connected to everything, almost pantheistically. Juan Uriagereka’s PyC is the Spanish translation of Rhyme and Reason (R&R), published in 1998 by the MIT Press, some ten years ago.1 Given the expert consulting processes behind it, it took the linguist Juan Romero about two years to translate the English manuscript (which was originally designed as a dialogue between Noam Chomsky and Stephen Hawking), and the final result had to wait on the bench some more time to be released. Overall, PyC seems to us to be a fine version of the original piece: it is more manageable actually, since the format is that of regular books (R&R’s shape was much bulkier and Atlas-like,), but, stylistically speaking, the outcome reveals a somewhat careless editing – typos abound –, and the final index is far from straightforward. This should not, though, detract the reader from the bril- liance of the work. In our eyes, Uriagereka’s R&R quickly became the paradigm example of what one may call a new wave in biolinguistics. Biolinguistics has become something of a scientific buzzword in the area of language studies, but it rests on established ideas (and ideals), firmly rooted in what is often called the cog- nitive revolution of the 1950s spearheaded by Noam Chomsky, Morris Halle, and Eric Lenneberg. These individuals caused a paradigm change in the study of language. They took as their central goals the following five questions: 1. What is Knowledge of Language? 2. How is that Knowledge acquired? 3. How is that Knowledge put to use? 4. How is that Knowledge implemented in the brain? 5. How did that Knowledge emerge in the species? Today these five questions constitute the conceptual core and focus of inquiry in fields like theoretical linguistics (the traditional areas of syntax, semantics, morphology, and phonology), language acquisition, pragmatics, psycholinguis- tics, neurolinguistics, evolutionary studies on language, and beyond. What these research questions emphasize is the fact that language can, and should be studied like any other attribute of our species, and more spe- cifically, as an organ of the mind/brain. The past fifty years have shown, un- controversially in our opinion, that it makes eminent sense, at various levels, to regard the study of the FL as a branch of biology, at a suitable level of ab- straction – hence the term bio-linguistics. Chomsky’s Lost Dialogue 193 As Boeckx and Grohmann [(2007), p. 1] point out in their inaugural is- sue of the Biolinguistics journal, there is both a weak and a strong sense to the term ‘biolinguistics.’ The weak sense of the term refers to ‘business as usual’ for linguists, so to speak, to the extent they are seriously engaged in discovering the properties of grammar, in effect carrying out the research program Chomsky initiated in Syntactic Structures. The strong sense of the term ‘biolinguistics’ refers to attempts to provide explicit answers to ques- tions that necessarily require the combination of linguistic insights and in- sights from related disciplines (evolutionary biology, genetics, neurology, psychology, etc.). PyC is a brilliant demonstration of how to formulate hy- potheses about the biology of language in this strong sense, and as such should serve as a reference point for future studies. The recent resurgence of interest in ‘biolinguistics’ is due in large part to the advent of the Minimalist Program in linguistic theory [see Chomsky (1993) and subsequent work] , which PyC intends to introduce to a wide au- dience. At the heart of the minimalist program is the question of how much of the architecture of the language faculty can be given a principled explana- tion [See Longa (2005) and Lorenzo (2007)]. Specifically, minimalism asks how well the structure of language meets design requirements imposed by the cognitive systems it subserves (sound/sign and meaning). As such, linguists working in the context of the Minimalist Program are forced to address and sharpen questions of cognitive specificity, ontogeny, and phylogeny, etc., to even begin to understand the design requirements imposed on the LF. This is not to say that previous generations of linguists were not interested in such is- sues but in practice biolinguistics issues had little effect on empirical inquiry into questions of descriptive and explanatory adequacy. In a minimalist con- text, they are inevitable. Chomsky formulated this attempt to make sense of properties of lan- guage in the most ambitious form (what is known as the Strong Minimalist Thesis), in the form of a challenge to the linguistic community: Can it be shown that the computational system at the core of FL is optimally or per- fectly designed to meet the demands on the systems of the mind/brain it in- teracts with? By optimal or perfect design Chomsky meant to explore the idea that all properties of the computational system of language can be made to fol- low from minimal design specifications, a.k.a. ‘bare output conditions’ – the sort of properties that the system would have to have to be usable at all (e.g. all expressions generated by the computational system should be legible, i.e., formatted in a way that the external systems can handle/work with). Put yet another way, the computational system of language, minimalistically con- strued, would consist solely of the most efficient algorithm to interface with the other components of the mind, the simplest procedure to compute (generate) its outputs (expressions) and communicate them to the organs of the mind that will interpret them and allow them to be enter into thought and action. 194 Cedric Boeckx and Ángel J. Gallego As even a quick look at the current minimalist literature would reveal, the specific proposals made in PyC remain among the most promising ave- nues of inquiry within minimalism. They have inspired numerous research papers, monographs, and doctoral dissertations. And given the size and ambi- tion of the work, we think that it contains much more that remains to be ex- plored. To name but a few: Chomsky (2004) takes adjuncts to occupy “a different plane” (see R&R, pp. 281-281; PyC, pp. 395-397); both Medeiros (2008) and Soschen (2008) argue that the Fibonacci series is found in phrasal dependencies, an idea that was first explored with respect to phonological combinatorics (see R&R, pp. 191-193, pp. 482-488; PyC, pp. 283-286, pp. 642-647; and also Idsardi (2008) for the formal proof of PyC’s early conjec- ture); Chomsky (2001) endorses the hypotheses that (i) the operation of Spell-Out can take place more than one time (R&R, pp. 232-238; PyC, pp. 336-342) and (ii) morphology acts like a virus, forcing the system to close off a cycle (see R&R, p. 207; PyC, p. 306); Boeckx (2008) entertains the idea that chains and projections can be collapsed (see R&R, pp.
Recommended publications
  • The Empirical Base of Linguistics: Grammaticality Judgments and Linguistic Methodology
    UCLA UCLA Previously Published Works Title The empirical base of linguistics: Grammaticality judgments and linguistic methodology Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/05b2s4wg ISBN 978-3946234043 Author Schütze, Carson T Publication Date 2016-02-01 DOI 10.17169/langsci.b89.101 Data Availability The data associated with this publication are managed by: Language Science Press, Berlin Peer reviewed eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California The empirical base of linguistics Grammaticality judgments and linguistic methodology Carson T. Schütze language Classics in Linguistics 2 science press Classics in Linguistics Chief Editors: Martin Haspelmath, Stefan Müller In this series: 1. Lehmann, Christian. Thoughts on grammaticalization 2. Schütze, Carson T. The empirical base of linguistics: Grammaticality judgments and linguistic methodology 3. Bickerton, Derek. Roots of language ISSN: 2366-374X The empirical base of linguistics Grammaticality judgments and linguistic methodology Carson T. Schütze language science press Carson T. Schütze. 2019. The empirical base of linguistics: Grammaticality judgments and linguistic methodology (Classics in Linguistics 2). Berlin: Language Science Press. This title can be downloaded at: http://langsci-press.org/catalog/book/89 © 2019, Carson T. Schütze Published under the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 Licence (CC BY 4.0): http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ ISBN: 978-3-946234-02-9 (Digital) 978-3-946234-03-6 (Hardcover) 978-3-946234-04-3 (Softcover) 978-1-523743-32-2
    [Show full text]
  • The Linguistics Wars Pdf, Epub, Ebook
    THE LINGUISTICS WARS PDF, EPUB, EBOOK Randy Allen Harris | 368 pages | 09 Mar 1995 | Oxford University Press Inc | 9780195098341 | English | New York, United States The Linguistics Wars PDF Book As a non-linguist, this book also served as a serviceable introduction to some of the field's basic ideas, and it was interesting to read about Chomsky in his original role. Javascript is not enabled in your browser. It has also been noted that the complex adaptive system view of language is highly compatible with those strands of language evolution research that focus on the cumulative cultural evolution of language see e. We can begin with very simple notions that depend on bodily orientation: front-back, before-after, left-right, etc. The book is certainly not suitable for people outside the field because it involves too much linguistic theory, so in a sense the book fails to do what it wants to do. Protolanguage and mechanisms of meaning construal in interaction. It''s just a matter of fact. Spivey, M. The major research project was aimed at overcoming this tension by showing that the apparent complexity and variety of language was only superficial, the result of minor changes in a fixed and invariant system. Since the mid-twentieth century, the field of linguistics has been a tumultuous discipline. Jul 30, Tom rated it it was ok. Leaving the myth behind: a reply to Adger The shape of the human language-ready brain. However, Christiansen and Chater , p. Oxford: OUP. Wang Taiwan: Pyramid Press , — It should be stressed that these matters are presented in an entirely different light by intellectual opinion, which has its own tasks and commitments.
    [Show full text]
  • Where Did Pragmatics Comme From
    n°19, Juin 2003, pp. 7-12 Where did pragmatics come from ? Abstract The present study is concerned with the early beginnings of pragmatics. It investigated the linguistic and philosophical backgrounds of this field. It was argued that pragmatics grew within philosophy and its emergence as an independent field Dr. A. HAMAD was, for some time, delayed by the influence of some linguistic Associate Prof. of Linguistics theories especially the generative-transformational theory. An-Najah Nat. University Finally, it was pointed out that this field was freed from the Nablus, Palestine influence of this theory. lthough many scholars, philosophers and A linguists, have been studying various types of pragmatic topics such as indexicality, implicatures, illocutionary force, speech acts, presuppositions, etc. For hundreds of years, pragmatics as a field has not emerged until recently. Not only that, but it has been denied the status of a component of grammar besides the phonological, syntactic, and semantic components which altogether constitute the core components of human language grammar. Critics have questioned the nature and the domain of this field; that is the theoretical as well as the practical status of the field in general. It seems that the scholars’ attitude toward pragmatics has been the result of radical theorizations in the main trend of theoretical linguistics motivated primarily by the structural and ملخص generative-transformational linguistic theories. The تهدف هذه الدراسة للتعرف على present study will attempt to explore briefly the البدايات المبكرة لعلم المقا مية. بحثت background of this field, its development, and the الدراسة في الخلفيات اللغوية والفلسفية reasons that stood behind the delay of its emergence التي تقف وراء هذا العلم.ثم حاولت .and institutionalization الدراسة التدليل على أن علم المقامية Philosophy and the Study of Language قد نشأ في حضن الفلسفة وأن بعض النضريات اللغوية عملت ولبعض In order to have a better understanding of the الوقت على تأخير ظهور هذا العلم.
    [Show full text]
  • 1. Introduction
    A fox knows many things but a hedgehog one big thing Mark Aronoff Stony Brook University 1. Introduction Isaiah Berlin’s little book, The Hedgehog and the Fox (1953), takes its title from a line by the Greek poet Archilochus: πόλλ᾽ οἶδ᾽ ἀλωπηξ ἀλλ᾽ ἐχῖνος ἓν μέγα ‘many [things] knows [a] fox but [a] hedgehog one big [thing]’. Since it is impossible to do justice in a paraphrase to Berlin’s prose, I will quote the relevant passage in full: [T]aken figuratively, the words can be made to yield a sense in which they mark one of the deepest differences which divide writers and thinkers, and, it may be, human beings in general. For there exists a great chasm between those, on one side, who relate everything to a single central vision, one system less or more coherent or articulate, in terms of which they understand, think, and feel—a single, universal, organizing principle in terms of which alone all that they are and say has significance—and, on the other side, those who pursue many ends, often unrelated and even contradictory, connected, if at all, only in some de facto way, for some psychological or physiological cause, related by no moral or aesthetic principle; these last lead lives, perform acts, and entertain ideas that are centrifugal rather than centripetal, their thought is scattered or diffused, moving on many levels, seizing upon the essence of a vast variety of experiences and objects for what they are in themselves, without, consciously or unconsciously, seeking to fit them into, or exclude them from, any one unchanging, all-embracing, sometimes self-contradictory and incomplete, at times fanatical, unitary vision.
    [Show full text]
  • Download the Linguistics Wars Free Ebook
    THE LINGUISTICS WARS DOWNLOAD FREE BOOK Randy Allen Harris | 368 pages | 09 Mar 1995 | Oxford University Press Inc | 9780195098341 | English | New York, United States Language wars: the 19 greatest linguistic spats of all time While the entrenched linguists were not looking for a messiah, apparently many of their students were. Dave rated it liked it Jun 06, Trivia About The Linguistics Wars. Use this word at your own risk. This book chronicles both sides of the Generative Semantics vs. The debates followed the usual trajectory of most large-scale clashes, scientific or otherwise. To study this co-ordination of certain sounds with certain meanings is to study language. Albaugh and Kathryn M. Both positions changed dramatically in the course of the dispute--the triumphant Chomskyan position was very The Linguistics Wars from The Linguistics Wars initial one; the defeated generative semantics position was even more transformed. Particularly, it The Linguistics Wars, when you add gender to the mix. Jul 11, David rated it liked it Shelves: linguisticsdid-not-finish. PaperbackThe Linguistics Wars. That drives them to spend hours arguing with strangers on the internet, to go around correcting misspelt signs in the dead of night, or even to threaten acts of violence? Start your review of The Linguistics Wars. Betsy rated it really liked it Jun 10, What can I say about this book. There was a revolution, which colored the field of linguistics for the following decades. There was a revolution, which colored the field of linguistics for the following decades. The repercussions of the Linguistics Wars are still with us, not only in the bruised feelings and late-night war stories of the combatants, and in the contentious mood in many quarters, but in the way linguists currently look at language and the mind.
    [Show full text]
  • Ten Choices for Lexical Semantics
    1 Ten Choices for Lexical Semantics Sergei Nirenburg and Victor Raskin1 Computing Research Laboratory New Mexico State University Las Cruces, NM 88003 {sergei,raskin}@crl.nmsu.edu Abstract. The modern computational lexical semantics reached a point in its de- velopment when it has become necessary to define the premises and goals of each of its several current trends. This paper proposes ten choices in terms of which these premises and goals can be discussed. It argues that the central questions in- clude the use of lexical rules for generating word senses; the role of syntax, prag- matics, and formal semantics in the specification of lexical meaning; the use of a world model, or ontology, as the organizing principle for lexical-semantic descrip- tions; the use of rules with limited scope; the relation between static and dynamic resources; the commitment to descriptive coverage; the trade-off between general- ization and idiosyncracy; and, finally, the adherence to the “supply-side” (method- oriented) or “demand-side” (task-oriented) ideology of research. The discussion is inspired by, but not limited to, the comparison between the generative lexicon ap- proach and the ontological semantic approach to lexical semantics. It is fair to say that lexical semantics, the study of word meaning and of its representation in the lexicon, experienced a powerful resurgence within the last decade.2 Traditionally, linguistic se- mantics has concerned itself with two areas, word meaning and sentence meaning. After the ascen- dancy of logic in the 1930s and especially after “the Chomskian revolution” of the late 1950s-early 1960s, most semanticists, including those working in the transformational and post-transforma- tional paradigm, focused almost exclusively on sentence meaning.
    [Show full text]
  • Chomsky's Revolution and Behaviourist Psychology More Gener­ Neil Smith Ally
    BOOK REVIEWS cognitive scientists and resulted in the overthrow of Bloomfieldian linguistics Chomsky's revolution and behaviourist psychology more gener­ Neil Smith ally. He explains the elegance of 'deep structure' and the power of Chomsky's The Linguistics Wars. By Randy Allen Harris. Oxford University Press: 1993. Pp. 356. conception of language as expounded in £22, $30. the 'standard theory', and then shows how a disparate group of young scholars, the generative semanticists, effectively hi­ NOAM Chomsky's position in the history that constrain the development of lan­ jacked the fledgling theory and developed of ideas is comparable to that of Darwin or guage. That is, the putative hypothesis it in ways so radical that Chomsky soon Descartes. In this century his peers in space of the infant language-learner in­ came to be seen as a reactionary fighting a influence are the unlikely trio of Einstein, cludes so few possibilities that the task of rearguard action against the forces of Picasso and Freud, with each of whom he language acquisition is dramatically sim­ progress. has something in common. Like Darwin plified. For instance, the principle of The sequel to this apparent decline was and Descartes, Chomsky has redefined 'structure dependence' ensures that no remarkable. After a decade of academic our understanding of ourselves as hu­ child will ever entertain the hypothesis savagery in which the discipline was sev­ mans; like Freud- but with added intel­ that one way of relating sentences is to erely factionalized, it was Chomsky rather lectual rig our- he has revolutionized our reverse their word order, so that the than the young Turks who emerged victo­ view of the mind; like Einstein, he blends question (or negative, or future tense) of rious.
    [Show full text]
  • The Bloomsbury Companion to Cognitive Linguistics
    The Bloomsbury Companion to Cognitive Linguistics Bloomsbury Companions Bloomsbury Companion to Lexicography, edited by Howard Jackson Bloomsbury Companion to Phonetics, edited by Mark J. Jones and Rachael-Anne Knight Bloomsbury Companion to Syntax, edited by Silvia Luraghi and Claudia Parodi Continuum Companion to Discourse Analysis, edited by Ken Hyland and Brian Paltridge Available in Paperback as Bloomsbury Companion to Discourse Studies Continuum Companion to Historical Linguistics, edited by Silvia Luraghi and Vit Bubenik Available in Paperback as Bloomsbury Companion to Historical Linguistics Continuum Companion to the Philosophy of Language, edited by Manuel García-Carpintero and Max Köbel Available in Paperback as Bloomsbury Companion to the Philosophy of Language Continuum Companion to Phonology, edited by Nancy C. Kula, Bert Botma and Kuniya Nasukawa Available in Paperback as Bloomsbury Companion to Phonology Continuum Companion to Second Language Acquisition, edited by Ernesto Macaro Available in Paperback as Bloomsbury Companion to Second Language Acquisition Forthcoming: Bloomsbury Companion to M.A.K. Halliday, edited by Jonathan J. Webster Bloomsbury Companion to Stylistics, edited by Violeta Sotirova Bloomsbury Companion to TESOL, edited by Jun Liu and Cynthia Murphy The Bloomsbury Companion to Cognitive Linguistics Edited by Jeannette Littlemore and John R. Taylor LONDON • NEW DELHI • NEW YORK • SYDNEY Bloomsbury Academic An imprint of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc 50 Bedford Square 1385 Broadway London New York WC1B 3DP NY 10018 UK USA www.bloomsbury.com Bloomsbury is a registered trade mark of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc First published 2014 © Jeannette Littlemore, John R. Taylor and Contributors, 2014 Jeannette Littlemore and John R. Taylor have asserted their right under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act, 1988, to be identified as the Editors of this work.
    [Show full text]
  • Cognitive Grammar in Literature Edited by Chloe Harrison, Louise
    Cognitive Grammar in Literature edited by Chloe Harrison, Louise Nuttall, Peter Stockwell and Wenjuan Yuan Contents Foreword Ronald W. Langacker 1. Introduction: Cognitive Grammar in literature Chloe Harrison, Louise Nuttall, Peter Stockwell and Wenjuan Yuan PART I Studies of Narrative Fiction 2. War, worlds and Cognitive Grammar Peter Stockwell 3. Construal and comics: the multimodal autobiography of Alison Bechdel’s Fun Home Michael Pleyer and Christian W. Schneider 4. Attentional windowing in David Foster Wallace’s ‘The Soul Is Not a Smithy’ Chloe Harrison 5. Resonant metaphor in Kazuo Ishiguro’s Never Let Me Go Sam Browse 6. Constructing a text world for The Handmaid’s Tale Louise Nuttall 7. Point of view in translation: Lewis Carroll's Alice in grammatical wonderlands Elzbieta Tabakowska PART II Studies of Poetry 8. Profiling the flight of ‘The Windhover’ Clara Neary 2 9. Foregrounding and literariness in Dylan Thomas's ‘After the funeral’ Anne Päivärinta 10. Conceptual proximity and the experience of war in Siegfried Sassoon’s ‘A working party’ Marcello Giovanelli 11. Most and now: tense and aspect in Bálint Balassi’s ‘Áldott szép pünkösdnek’ Mike Pincombe 12. Fictive motion in Wordsworthian nature Wenjuan Yuan 13. The cognitive poetics of ‘If’ Craig Hamilton 14. Representing the represented: verbal variations on Vincent’s Bedroom in Arles Alina Kwiatowska Afterword: From Cognitive Grammar to Systems Rhetoric Todd Oakley 3 List of Contributors Sam Browse is a researcher in the School of English at the University of Sheffield. His work focuses on developing a text-driven approach to metaphor in discourse, and his interests encompass literary, political, economic and journalistic forms of public discourse.
    [Show full text]
  • MODIFICATION? 9 Not Elsewhere
    DRAFT Modification Marcin Morzycki Michigan State University June 12, 2013 Latest revision: June 2014 This is a draft of a book in preparation for the Cambridge University Press series Key Topics in Semantics and Pragmatics. It’s something between a textbook for people with a basic background in semantics and an introduc- tory survey of work on the semantics of adjectives, adverbs, and degrees. For a fuller explanation, see section 1.2. Comments would be extremely helpful, so please don’t hesitate to contact me if you have any, even very minor ones. DRAFT Contents Acknowledgments vii 1 Preliminaries 1 1.1 Two problems .............................. 1 1.2 What this book is and isn’t ..................... 2 1.3 Background assumptions ...................... 3 1.3.1 Glossing logical notation ................. 3 1.3.2 Theoretical framework ................... 4 1.3.3 Notational and typographical conventions ....... 7 1.4 What, if anything, is modification? ................ 8 1.5 Roadmap ................................ 12 2 The Lexical Semantics of Adjectives: More Than Just Scales 13 2.1 Introduction .............................. 13 2.2 How adjectives and nouns combine: a typology . 14 2.2.1 Intersective interpretations . 14 2.2.2 Subsective interpretations . 16 2.2.3 Apparently subsective intersective interpretations . 20 2.2.4 Ordinary non-subsective adjectives . 22 2.2.5 Privative adjectives, which may not exist . 24 2.3 The type of adjectives and the nature of subsectivity . 26 2.3.1 How powerful are adjectives? . 26 2.3.2 Siegel: The Doublet Theory . 30 2.3.3 Larson: events inside the nominal extended projection 34 2.3.4 The implicit argument approach .
    [Show full text]
  • The Empirical Base of Linguistics Grammaticality Judgments and Linguistic Methodology
    The empirical base of linguistics Grammaticality judgments and linguistic methodology Carson T. Schütze language Classics in Linguistics 2 science press Classics in Linguistics Chief Editors: Martin Haspelmath, Stefan Müller In this series: 1. Lehmann, Christian. Thoughts on grammaticalization 2. Schütze, Carson T. The empirical base of linguistics: Grammaticality judgments and linguistic methodology 3. Bickerton, Derek. Roots of language ISSN: 2366-374X The empirical base of linguistics Grammaticality judgments and linguistic methodology Carson T. Schütze language science press Carson T. Schütze. 2016. The empirical base of linguistics: Grammaticality judgments and linguistic methodology (Classics in Linguistics 2). Berlin: Language Science Press. This title can be downloaded at: http://langsci-press.org/catalog/book/89 © 2016, Carson T. Schütze Published under the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 Licence (CC BY 4.0): http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ ISBN: 978-3-946234-02-9 (Digital) 978-3-946234-03-6 (Hardcover) 978-3-946234-04-3 (Softcover) 978-1-523743-32-2 (Softcover US) ISSN: 2366-374X DOI:10.17169/langsci.b89.100 Cover and concept of design: Ulrike Harbort Typesetting: Felix Kopecky, Sebastian Nordhoff, Carson T. Schütze Fonts: Linux Libertine, Arimo, DejaVu Sans Mono Typesetting software:Ǝ X LATEX Language Science Press Habelschwerdter Allee 45 14195 Berlin, Germany langsci-press.org Storage and cataloguing done by FU Berlin Language Science Press has no responsibility for the persistence or accuracy of URLs for external or third-party Internet websites referred to in this publication, and does not guarantee that any content on such websites is, or will remain, accurate or appropriate. For my mother, Dorly Schütze, and the memory of my father, Ted Schütze It is simultaneously the greatest virtue and failing of linguistic theory that sequence acceptability judgments are used as the basic data.
    [Show full text]
  • ACL Lifetime Achievement Award
    ACL Lifetime Achievement Award Word Play Lauri Karttunen∗ Palo Alto Research Center Stanford University This article is a perspective on some important developments in semantics and in computational linguistics over the past forty years. It reviews two lines of research that lie at the opposite ends on the field: semantics and morphology. The semantic part deals with issues from the 1970s such as discourse referents, implicative verbs, presuppositions, and questions. The second part presents a brief history of the application of finite-state transducers to linguistic analysis starting with the advent of two-level morphology in the early 1980s and culminating in successful commercial applications in the 1990s. It offers some commentary on the relationship, or the lack thereof, between computational and paper-and-pencil linguistics. The final section returns to the semantic issues and their application to currently popular tasks such as textual inference and question answering. 1. Prologue Thirty-eight years ago, in the summer of 1969 at the second meeting of COLING in Sånga-Säby in Sweden, I stood for the first time in front of a computational audience and started my talk on Discourse Referents by reading the following passage (Karttunen 1969a, 1976): Consider a device designed to read a text in some natural language, interpret it, and store the content in some manner, say, for the purpose of being able to answer questions about it. To accomplish this task, the machine will have to fulfill at least the following basic requirement. It has to be able to build a file that consists of records of all individuals, that is, events, objects, etc., mentioned in the text and, for each individual, record whatever is said about it.
    [Show full text]