A Man of Little Faith

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

A Man of Little Faith A MAN OF LITTLE FAITH SUNY series in Contemporary French Thought —————— David Pettigrew and François Raffoul, editors A MAN OF LITTLE FAITH Memory Theaters in Contemporary Barcelona MICHEL DEGUY With Two Essays by JEAN-LUC NANCY Translated, edited, and with an Introduction by CHRISTOPHER ELSON State University of New York Press Frontispiece, illustration by Alain Lestié untitled acrostic for Michel Deguy’s 80th birthday, by Jean-Luc Nancy Un homme de peu de foi © Editions Bayard, 2003 Published by State University of New York Press, Albany © 2014 State University of New York All rights reserved Printed in the United States of America No part of this book may be used or reproduced in any manner whatsoever without written permission. No part of this book may be stored in a retrieval system or transmitted in any form or by any means including electronic, electrostatic, magnetic tape, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise without the prior permission in writing of the publisher. For information, contact State University of New York Press, Albany, NY www.sunypress.edu Production, Eileen Nizer Marketing, Kate Seburyamo Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Deguy, Michel. [Un homme de peu de foi. English] A man of little faith / Michel Deguy ; translated, edited, and with an introduction by Christopher Elson. pages cm. — (SUNY series in contemporary French thought) Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 978-1-4384-5359-0 (hardcover : alk. paper) ISBN 978-1-4384-5360-6 (ebook) 1. Faith—Philosophy. 2. Belief and doubt—Philosophy. 3. Religion— Philosophy. I. Title. BD215.D4413 2014 210—dc23 2013048559 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 Meteor tracing furious ellipses Impalpable bump of worlds in rebound Cast pebbles, coaldust, silex, micas and gypsums Humouristic reports, sobs and zounds Entrained by the pure avidity of saying Luxuriant all and one like the other Drawing on his lyre ingenious before us Enharmonic with cadences of reason Grave and gay in turn in the well-milled throat Ulcerous from the saps that its conjugation Yearning like a gluttonous muse there pours out —Jean-Luc Nancy, from Deguy le Grand 8 CONTENTS Translator’s Notes xi Introduction To Conserve While Leaving Behind: Michel Deguy’s Palinody xv A MAN OF LITTLE FAITH This text is of little faith . 3 I. Palinody I will not tell of how “I lost faith” . 11 There is no transcendent . 12 If I were a visual artist . 13 I will reverse a saying of Auguste Comte . 14 Confiteor 17 Love Story 19 Negligence 21 The fantasy of forgetting 22 Cuttings 23 Paul Valéry’s “to be awake . .” 24 Gift without Exchange 25 Case of Equality 28 Love has no why . 29 Of the Author 30 Escence 31 “Super Flumina” 32 Attached 34 Poetry is triple . 36 Man is the being who tramps his own transcendence . 37 “My fellow, my sister . .” [Mon semblable, ma soeur] 39 Natives of Eden . 40 “Everything is full of soul(s) . .” . 41 “Keine Rache mehr” . 42 “Ecce Homo” 43 I pause for a moment . 46 We are in the Fiji Islands . 47 We are in the Fiji Islands . 48 Of the Mortal Possessing Speech 50 II. Notebooks of Disbelief In Doubt 57 “Non credo in” 62 To Mothers 63 In the imagination . 64 “The patient breath of the bull” . 66 Who is God? . 67 Christ 68 The Incarnate 69 Why continue . 70 Nothing will be destroyed . 71 Since the body . 72 The Future of the Illusion 73 Relics 75 Of the Holy Family 76 My Guardian Angel 77 There are certainly other just men in the city . 78 The Infernal Machine 79 Metaphysical Meditation 81 Descartes and Socrates 82 Enough with the science! . 83 Literature And The Good 85 The Common Nothing 87 The Reproach Made to Kant 90 “Minima Moralia” 92 Logic of Double Negation or of Non-Mathematical, Paradoxical Apodicticity 93 III. Simone Weil From Memory Life and Death 99 Of Purity 101 Attention 103 Of Contrariety 104 And Today 106 viii Notes On Paradox 109 Of the Double-Bind 111 Digression on Analogy 114 Transcendence 116 An Aside 117 Revelation, continued . 118 Of Religion 119 Of the End 121 IV. Jewish Humanity Peace-With 125 “All Men Will Be Jewish” 128 Appendix A: Dublin Interview 147 Appendix B: Two Essays on Michel Deguy by Jean-Luc Nancy Deguy The New Year! 169 To Accompany Michel Deguy 189 Notes 201 Index 211 ix TRANSLATOR’S NOTES It is a privilege and an adventure to translate Michel Deguy, to attempt to bring his vigorous inventivity and erudition in the original French to life in an idiomatic, comparably layered, and still comprehensible English. This often seems like an impossible exercise, balancing inspiration and peril, one where difficult choices are necessary on every page. Deguy’s inventivity is that of the extreme contemporary, an already “future rigor” where the writer of vigilance works ceaselessly to safeguard the linguistic relics of our cultural past at the same time as he seeks to enliven today’s words, which are always at risk of falling behind today’s things and phenomena, keeping both sides open in a continuous retranslation for future uses and astonishments. 1. Neologisms. I have an absolute respect for Deguyan neology and a commitment to rendering it each and every time, even at the cost of occa- sional awkwardness. “Things change more quickly than words” and culture has been “vampirized” (CPAC, 195 and back cover). Neologisms are sharp wooden stakes in the toolbox of Michel Deguy, Vampire Hunter. 2. Something that may not be immediately apparent to the reader of only the English text is the degree to which I have respected but not absolutely the expansive, exigent syntax of Deguy’s phraseology. Sometimes the precise preciousness of his sentences has been attenuated here, sinuos- ity abandoned in favor of a straightened-out stretch, his prosody’s rhythmic elongation across the bar lines given more limited measures. 3. The quantity and cumulative, signifying density of allusions in this as in any other of Deguy’s works adds a further dimension to its translation, as well as posing basic editorial challenges. How not to overload the text with parenthetical references or footnotes? I have attempted to find the right balance between useful information and excessive disruption of the text’s flow and appearance. On the same heading, the French poetic tradition is massively present here as elsewhere in Deguy’s corpus and I have aimed for a balance between compactly indicating author names or/and the titles of works cited by Deguy and the inclusion of a few recapitulative notes gathering together a brief account of the place of Apollinaire, Baudelaire, Mallarmé, Rimbaud, and others in A Man of Little Faith and Deguy’s other works. xi 4. A Man of Little Faith is a multilingual book before any translat- ing takes place. There are many citations and expressions in Latin and in Greek, along with a few quotations left in their original English, German, or other languages. Like his late friend, Jacques Derrida, Deguy proceeds from the conviction that any language is always already more than one, always relating to itself diachronically and relating to its others geopoetically in full consciousness of the necessity of translation and a lucid reflection on its conditions of possibility. His 1978 text “The Compass Rose of Languages” (JMUSA, 88–98) is a fine illustration, in a kind of textualist mode, of the poet-thinker’s acute awareness of the necessity of relating one European language to its others. 5. Wherever Deguy has played with a biblical or philosophical cita- tion in Greek or Latin, I immediately give a rendering in square brackets to help the reader avoid mistaking a more or less significant alteration for a familiar reference. Explanation or translation of unaltered quotations in the original languages is treated less systematically, sometimes given paren- thetically, sometimes incorporated into endnotes found on the same page, sometimes not provided, if the context is sufficiently rich. 6. The comme of comparison. One of the most important challenges for a translator of Deguy is to find ways to convey the density of his thought of comparison, a reflection that is both poetic and ontological in its implica- tions. The French comme condenses the senses of English “like” and “as” or German wie and als. Deguy has worked on and with its ambivalent two- sidedness virtually since the beginning of his career. The cumulative richness of these years of poetic and philosophical reflection on comme is present in the translator’s mind at each occasion of choice. In the subsection “Escence” (infra 30–31), Deguy makes it clear that he privileges the like over the as but cannot escape from the undividedness of the comparative and the definitive, the proximity in comme of the open multivalence of like and the identitary risks of as. “The work of reason, which always still awaits, is to scrutinize the obscurity of a difference which is reducible to that of ‘as’ and ‘like,’ [en tant que/ pareil à] which in French comes down to the homogeneity of the comme where this difference cannot be heard” (infra 118). A crucial decision must be made with respect to Deguy’s tendency to substantify the adverb or conjunction “comme” in order to treat comparison theoretically: Le comme, when it is used analytically as a conceptual operator, will be treated in English translation as a compound common noun, “the like-or-as,” despite the possible awkwardness of that expansive choice—I think the reader needs this occasional reminder; this will not be the case in expressions like l’ontologie du comme, which is translated as “the ontol- ogy of like,” suppressing the implicit definite article and condensing the two-sidedness of like-or-as for the sake of elegance.
Recommended publications
  • Aeschynē in Aristotle's Conception of Human Nature Melissa Marie Coakley University of South Florida, [email protected]
    University of South Florida Scholar Commons Graduate Theses and Dissertations Graduate School 3-20-2014 Aeschynē in Aristotle's Conception of Human Nature Melissa Marie Coakley University of South Florida, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd Part of the Philosophy Commons Scholar Commons Citation Coakley, Melissa Marie, "Aeschynē in Aristotle's Conception of Human Nature" (2014). Graduate Theses and Dissertations. https://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd/4999 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at Scholar Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Graduate Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Scholar Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Aeschynē in Aristotle’s Conception of Human Nature by Melissa M. Coakley A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy College of Arts and Science University of South Florida Major Professor: Joanne Waugh, Ph.D. Bruce Silver, Ph.D. Roger Ariew, Ph.D. Thomas Williams, Ph.D. Date of Approval: March 20, 2014 Keywords: Shame, Anaeschyntia, Aidōs, Aischynē, Ancient Greek Passions Copyright © 2014, Melissa M. Coakley DEDICATION This manuscript is dedicated to my husband Bill Murray and to my parents: Joan and Richard Coakley. Thank you for your endless support, encouragement, and friendship. To Dr. John P. Anton, I have learned from you the importance of having a “ton of virtue and a shield of nine layers for protection from the abysmal depths of vice.” Thank you for believing in me, my dear friend.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle's Theory of Practical Wisdom
    ¥ ARISTOTLE'S THEORY OF PRACTICAL WISDOM By YoSHlo FUJII Professor of Philosophy Aristotelian philosophy has been studied assiduously by scholars of the world for the last two thousand years. It seems that no Aristotelian stone has been left unturned and that nothing new can be said about the Stagirite in the sphere of philosophy and philology. But one can always expect to find a new angle, from which to study his outstanding works on philosophical problems. In any new undertaking, however, we should not follow the Scholastic formulae or the well-beaten path of Aristotelian study. What we are called upon to do today is to throw a new light on the incarnate system of Aristotelian philosophy evolved through following' its development rather than on his pre-harmonized system. This problem has been successfully dealt with by Prof. Werner Jaeger in his work, Aristoteles, Grueedlegueeg eil~er Geschich,te seileer L;fatwicklu,~g (Berlin, 1923). A. E. Taylor was quite right when he said, "If any of us henceforth ventures to make assertions about Aristotle without having taken Mr. Jaeger's fascinating work into account, he will at least be speaking very terribly at his own peril." I That development of Aristotelian philo- sophy seen in the studies effected on the Jaeger method has been followed and furthered largely by F. Solmsen and R. Walzer in both logical and ethical ficlds.2 1 myself have traced by this same method the history of Aristotle's metaphysical and epistemological developments in my work, Aristotelione Studies (in Japanese, Tokyo, 1940). Again in another treatise, The ~thics of Aristotle (in Japanese, Tokyo, 1951), I have endeavoured to survey and analyse the development and structure of the practical wisdom (~)Pb!)~alS) of Aristotle which constitutes the most fundamental concept of all the intellectual virtues.
    [Show full text]
  • Educational Thoughts of Aristotle and Confucius
    Educational Thoughts of Aristotle and Confucius JEONG-KYU LEE Korean Educational Development Institute Hongik University, Seoul ABSTRACT: This study examines the educational principles and aims of Aristotle and Confucius. Through a descriptive analysis, the research questions of the study are assessed . Both philosophers subscribed to the common educational principles that emphasize ethical education for building individual cultivation, social harmony, and the ideal state. The individual and social aims of education are: (a) to provide the proper m ethod of training the virtuous persons who have ideal characters through self-cultivation, and (b) to build the harmonious community and the good state through development of a gentleman or a noble man. On the other hand, differences include: Confucius emphasized his ethical and political principles without supporting the metaphysical and epistemological theories, which was unlike Aristotle's approach; he did not use a set of tools like Aristotle's Organon to justify his ethical a nd political thought. Finally, the article claims that Confucius generally stressed self­ cultivation through humanity and ritual, while Aristotle primarily emphasized self-actualization through habit and reason. RESUME: Cette etude examine de s principes d'education et des objectifs d'Aristotle et de Confucius. Les questions de la recherche sont evaluees a travers une analyse descriptive. Les deux philosophes souscrivent aux principes communs d'education qui mettent en valeur l'e ducation ethique dont le but primordial est de co nstruire la culture individuelle, l'harmonie sociale et l'etat ideal. Confucius soulignait des notions ethiques et politiques et n e supportait pas les theories metaphysiques et episte mologiques ce qui e tait different de l'approche d'Aristotle.
    [Show full text]
  • Nova Magna Moralia ------PHYSICS-ETHICS-POLITICS: NEOCLASSIC CONCEPTS for POSTMODERN TIMES
    Nova Magna Moralia ------------------ PHYSICS-ETHICS-POLITICS: NEOCLASSIC CONCEPTS FOR POSTMODERN TIMES By Paris Arnopoulos Published in SKEPSIS: A Journal of Philosophy & Interdisciplinary Research Volume XIII-XIV, Athens, 2002-3 ABSTRACT At the dawn of the third millennium, humanity is increasingly aware that its traditional ethnocentric ethic is inadequate for the task of global sustainability. It is by now apparent that the contradictory requirements of physical nature, modern culture and human nurture, demand an evolving and dynamic homeostasis among all three existential realms. Under the circumstances, traditional morality may seem too restricted in time and place to suffice in the interdependent and interacting world of the present and future. Yet, it is the fundamental axiom of this paper that updating, enlarging and readapting the classic cannon of ethics as a Modern Macro-Morality (M3) is the best way of resolving some of our planetary problems. In the Emerging Global Order (EGO) of the new millennium, renewed ethics will have to be applied in an ecumenical scale in order to harmonize both the potentiality and responsibility of humanity towards itself and its environment. Building a holistic ethic can only be done by transcending local particularities and emphasizing global similarities, found in all great philosophies, ideologies and religions. A distillation of the essence of these ideas indicates the shared deontology of our species. These human universals are firmly rooted in the implicate order of things from which they draw their common heritage and to which they eventually return. The primordial origin of this particular study is classic natural law as the eternal foundation of a renewed cosmopolitan ethic.
    [Show full text]
  • Seminar on Aristotle's Ethics
    Aristotle’s Ethics Philosophy 207z Fall 2013 Chris Korsgaard 205 Emerson Hall 495-3916 [email protected] Office Hours: Thursdays, 2:00-4:00, and by appointment I. Required Texts Aristotle. The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translation. Volumes 1 and 2. ed. Jonathan Barnes. Princeton, 1984. (ordered at the Coop) Korsgaard, Christine M. “Two Kinds of Matter in Aristotle’s Metaphysics” (1982) “Aristotle on Function and Virtue” (1986) “Aristotle and Kant on the Source of Value” (1986) “From Duty and for the Sake of the Noble: Kant and Aristotle on Morally Good Action” (1996) “Acting for a Reason” (2004) “The Origin of the Good and Our Animal Nature” (2007) “Aristotle’s Function Argument” (2008) Selections from The Natural History of the Good, the Pufendorf Lectures, 2013 (on the course web site) II. Recommended Books Books containing Recommended Readings on the syllabus: Broadie, Sarah. Ethics with Aristotle. Oxford, 1995. Kraut, Richard (ed). The Blackwell Guide to Aristotle’s Ethics. Blackwell, 2006. Plato. Complete Works. ed. John M. Cooper and D. S. Hutchinson. Hackett, 1997. Rorty, Amélie. Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics. University of California, 1981. Other Recommended Books ordered at the Coop: Aquinas, St. Thomas. Commentary on Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. Trans. C. I. Litzinger. Dumb Ox Books, 1993. Engstrom, Stephen, and Whiting, Jennifer. Aristotle, Kant, and the Stoics: Rethinking Happiness and Virtue. Cambridge, 1998. Korsgaard, Christine M. The Constitution of Agency. Oxford, 2008. Miller, Jon (ed). Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics: A Critical Guide. Cambridge, 2011. Pakaluk, Michael, and Pearson, Giles (eds.) Moral Psychology and Human Action in Aristotle.
    [Show full text]
  • Rhizai. a Journal for Ancient Philosophy and Science (Rhizai
    Contemplation and Self–awareness in the Nicomachean Ethics «Contemplation and Self–awareness in the Nicomachean Ethics» by Matthew D. Walker Source: Rhizai. A Journal for Ancient Philosophy and Science (Rhizai. A Journal for Ancient Philosophy and Science), issue: VII.2 / 2010, pages: 221­238, on www.ceeol.com. CONTEMPLATION AND SELF–AWARENESS IN THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS Matthew D. Walker In this paper, I explore Aristotle’s account in the Nicomachean Ethics (NE) of how agents attain self-awareness through contemplation. In Part I, I examine Aristotle’s views from Book IX on how contemplating friends elicits self-awareness, and point out two limitations that friends have in this respect. I argue, however, that on Aristotle’s view, theoretical contemplation of the divine provides agents another source of self-awareness free from these limitations, and that Aristotle’s account of contemplation’s role in self-awareness concludes in Book X, not in Book IX. In Part II, I offer an account of how theoretical contemplation of the divine elicits self-awareness. I argue that Aristotle’s remarks on how agents attain self-awareness through contemplating friends provides a model for how agents attain self-awareness in contemplating the divine. I. In NE IX.9, Aristotle defends the view that since the blessedly happy agent has limited powers to contemplate his own virtuous actions directly, ‘the blessed [agent] will be in need of friends, if indeed he chooses to contemplate actions [that are] decent and his own’ (1170a2–3).1 After presenting an initial argument for this conclusion at 1169b28–1170a4, Aristotle offers a more detailed (and more metaphysical) argument for the same general view at 1170a14–b10.
    [Show full text]
  • Baker Metaphysics of Goodness in Ethics of Aristotle Oct 15
    The Metaphysics of Goodness in the Ethics of Aristotle Samuel Baker [email protected] Penultimate Draft. Please cite version published in Philosophical Studies (2017) 174:1839-1856 Abstract: Kraut (2011) and other neo-Aristotelians have argued that there is no such thing as absolute goodness. They admit only good in a kind, e.g. a good sculptor, and good for something, e.g. good for fish. What is the view of Aristotle? Mostly limiting myself to the Nicomachean Ethics [NE], I argue that Aristotle is committed to things being absolutely good and also to a metaphysics of absolute goodness where there is a maximally best good that is the cause of the goodness of all other things in virtue of being their end. I begin (in Section 2) by suggesting that the notion of good as an end, which is present in the first lines of the NE, is not obviously accounted for by good in a kind or good for something. I then give evidence that good in a kind (in Section 3) and good for something (in Section 4) can explain neither certain distinctions drawn between virtues nor the determinacy ascribed to what is good “in itself.” I argue (in Section 5) contra Gotthelf (2012) that because several important arguments in the Nicomachean Ethics rely on comparative judgments of absolute value—e.g. “Man is the best of all animals”— Aristotle is committed to the existence of both absolute goodness and an absolutely best being. I focus (in Section 6) on one passage, Aristotle’s division of goods in NE I 12, which presupposes this metaphysical picture.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle on Natural Law Max Salomon Shellens
    Notre Dame Law School NDLScholarship Natural Law Forum 1-1-1959 Aristotle on Natural Law Max Salomon Shellens Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.nd.edu/nd_naturallaw_forum Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Shellens, Max Salomon, "Aristotle on Natural Law" (1959). Natural Law Forum. Paper 40. http://scholarship.law.nd.edu/nd_naturallaw_forum/40 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by NDLScholarship. It has been accepted for inclusion in Natural Law Forum by an authorized administrator of NDLScholarship. For more information, please contact [email protected]. ARISTOTLE ON NATURAL LAW Max Salomon Shellens WHEN DISCUSSING LAW AND JUSTICE philosophers and historians almost in- variably claim that Aristotle' is the father of natural law. The truth of this claim will not be contested here. However, without a clear understanding of what Aristotle meant by the expression "natural law," the claim that he was the father of natural law has little significance. 1. Aristotle did not coin the term 81Kauov cvo0-K'V, nor was he the first per- son to relate 'justice' to 'nature.' It is important to stress this in order to ap- preciate fully the way he approaches the problem of natural law in its various aspects. Largely through the teachings of the Sophists the expression SKatov 2 4vov had become quite popular by the time of Aristotle. Despite con- siderable doctrinal differences in various dicta of the Sophists concerning the 8tKatov cVCtKoV they all share a polemical character. Aristotle's treatment of this subject is polemical too; but what distinguishes him from his predeces- sors is the fact that he endeavors to overcome a purely negative attitude, thereby turning a slogan into a serious problem.
    [Show full text]
  • Energeia in the Magna Moralia
    Energeia i n the Magna Moralia A New Case for Late Authorship Daniel Wolt Bilkent University, Dept. of Philosophy [email protected] Abstract There is no clear consensus among scholars about the authenticity of the M agna Moralia (MM). Here I present a new case for thinking that the work was composed by a later Peripatetic, and is not, either directly or indirectly, the work of Aristotle. My argument rests on an analysis of the author’s usage of energeia. The usage of e nergeia is a fruitful way to investigate the date of the work because the term was apparently coined by Aristotle but in later antiquity came to be used in ways inconsistent with Aristotle’s own usage. I argue that in several passages from the M M t he term is used in this distinctively late sense and that it is not plausible to think that this innovation could have occured in Aristotle’s own lifetime or shortly thereafter. Keywords Aristotle – Magna Moralia – energeia – Hellenistic philosophy – Peripatetic ethics 1 Introduction The authorship of the Magna Moralia (MM) is one of the great unsolved mysteries of the Aristotelian Corpus. There is a variety of views about where the work came from, but these can be roughly divided into two camps. The first camp, which I shall call the early authorship view, holds either that the work was written by Aristotle or one of his students, perhaps as 1 notes from a lecture course. On this view the MM is at least a fairly reliable source for Aristotle’s own thought.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle on Science
    Aristotle on Science Science (episteme): an axiomatic system, where necessary first principles lead by deductive inference to all the truths of the discipline (Posterior Analytics, I.6) Logic: the study of “verbal reasoning.” Logic itself is not a science, but precedes the sciences, and consists of six works of Aristotle’s that came to be called the Organon: Categories (discusses the different kinds of predicates [kategoria]). On Interpretation, (discusses the nature and structure of simple propositions, truth, and modality). Prior Analytics (discusses the syllogism). Posterior Analytics (discusses the nature of axioms, and of axiomatized science in general). Topics (discusses predicables, as well as rules for effective arguments and debate). On Sophistical Refutations (discusses various forms of arguments and fallacies) — this was often given as an appendix to the Topics. Also, Aristotle’s Rhetoric makes explicit use of the Topics. Whether logic counted as part of philosophy (or the sciences) was disputed The Stoics viewed it as the first of three parts of science, while the Peripatetics viewed it as a tool of science. THEORETICAL SCIENCES: CONCERNED WITH TRUTH ALONE Theology: the study of “changeless objects” (which are therefore divine). As such it is the “first science” or primary philosophy. (Book 8 of the Physics argues for an “unmoved mover”.) Metaphysics: the study of being qua being. [Metaphysics] Mathematics: Arithmetic [Metaphysics, Bks. 13-14]. Geometry Astronomy (this is most akin to philosophy because it deals with a substance which is sensible yet eternal, while arithmetic and geometry do not deal with any substance [Metaphysics, Bk. 12; De caelo: on the structure of the heavens, the earth, the elements].
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle on Self-Knowledge and Friendship
    volume 11, no. 12 In memory of Ian Mueller. august 2011 an’s nature is political, Aristotle tells us; he needs others to live and to live well.1 The gods, on the other hand, are M perfect, self-contained, self-sufficient beings.2 And yet, he also tells us, we ought to become like gods as much as possible, fol- lowing the divine part of our nature. As Ross puts it in his memorable Aristotle on translation: We must not follow those who advise us, being men, to think of human things, and, being mortal, of mortal things, but must, so far as we can, make ourselves im- Self-Knowledge and mortal, and strain every nerve to live in accordance with the best thing in us; for even if it be small in bulk, much more does it in power and worth surpass everything. Friendship [Nicomachean Ethics 1177b31–1178a2]3 The good life for humans imitates divine life by its self-sufficiency, its provision on its own of what is worthwhile, its relative lack of depen- dence on external goods and matters of chance. In this way, our call to imitate divine self-sufficiency seems to conflict with our political nature, our need for other people. In the Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle addresses this possible conflict between our political nature and our divine nature in ways that are not obviously consistent with one another. In Book 9, Chapter 9, he argues that the happy man, although he is self-sufficient, will still need Zena Hitz 1. Nicomachean Ethics 1.7, 1097b8–11; 8.12, 1162a16–19; 9.9, 1169b16–22; Eudemi- an Ethics 7.10, 1242a19–28; Politics 1.2, 1253a7–18; 3.6, 1278b15–30; History of University of Maryland, Baltimore County Animals 1.1, 487b33–488a14.
    [Show full text]
  • The Aristotelian Beginnings
    Cambridge University Press 0521828651 - Aristotle East and West: Metaphysics and the Division of Christendom David Bradshaw Excerpt More information chapter 1 The Aristotelian beginnings Although Aristotle never takes credit for coining the word energeia, there can be little doubt that it was his own invention. It appears nowhere in extant Greek literature prior to Aristotle, and even for some decades after his death it is restricted mainly to philosophical writers, particularly those of Aristotle’s own school. By contrast, it occurs 671 times in Aristotle’s works, about once for every other page of the Berlin edition. Unfortunately Aristotle discusses its etymology only once, remarking briefly that energeia is derived from “deed” or “thing done” (t¼ rgon)(Met. ix.8 1050a22). Although this gives us the ultimate source of the term, the combination of en with ergon already had precedents in Greek, and it is likely that one of these was the more proximate source. The two available candidates are energos, an adjective meaning “active, effective,” and energein,averb meaning “to be active or effective, to operate.” In either case the root sense of energeia is something like “activity, operation, or effectiveness.” To say more than this based on etymology would be rash. One way to proceed at this point would be to list its various meanings in dictionary fashion, illustrating each by representative texts.1 Such a pro- cedure would not explain what united the various meanings in Aristotle’s mind and why he believed it appropriate to use the same term for them all. It would thus risk missing the term’s more subtle nuances.
    [Show full text]