An Essay on the First-Person Plural A

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

An Essay on the First-Person Plural A BEING-TOGETHER: AN ESSAY ON THE FIRST-PERSON PLURAL A Dissertation submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate School of Arts and Sciences of Georgetown University In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy By Quentin A. Fisher, M.A. Washington, DC November 14, 2019 Copyright 2019 by Quentin A. Fisher All Rights Reserved ii BEING-TOGETHER: AN ESSAY ON THE FIRST-PERSON PLURAL Quentin A. Fisher, M.A. Thesis Advisor: Mark N. Lance, Ph.D. ABSTRACT This dissertation concerns the philosophy of the first-person. It consists of three principal philosophical studies, each concerning a set of concepts that, when taken together, form a skeletal though unified account of the first-person. The first part concerns the various uses of the first-person singular (‘I’) as well as first-person immunity to error through misidentification. The second part concerns the various uses of the first-person plural (‘we’). I argue that (i) there are several distinct uses of the first-person plural pronoun, (ii) that each of these uses can be articulated inferentially, and (iii) that one use of the first-person plural—what I call the “generic use”—is conceptually basic. In the third part, I argue that the first-person plural pronoun is, at least on some of its uses, the grammatical mark of a certain form of self-conscious understanding, and it is this kind of self-conscious understanding that underwrites the possibility of speaking a language. I end by outlining some structural relations between the various uses of the first-person singular and the first-person plural. According to the account offered here, the first-person singular and the first-person plural form a non-additive unitary structure. Correctly understood, an account of the first-person must include both the first-person singular and the first-person plural. iii The essays in this dissertation are the fruit of several longstanding conversations: with my committee, Mark Lance, Terry Pinkard, and David Bronstein; with my teachers, Bill Blattner, Yuri Corrigan, Wayne Davis, Bryce Huebner, Rebecca Kukla, Huaping Lu-Adler, Mark Murphy, Evan Riley, and Kate Withy; and with my friends, Daniel Baker, Gaurav Bagwe, Gabe Broughton, Clark Donley, Jason Farr, Rose Ryan Flynn, Jonathan Gombin, Oren Magid, Jake McNulty, Thomas Pendlebury, Kyle Scott, Ryan Simonelli, Omar Talhouk, Gerald Taylor, and Wim Vanrie. I would like to single out four philosophers for special thanks. For the past five years I have been in nearly continuous conversation with Terry Pinkard. These conversations have had a transformative effect on my conception of philosophy, and this document everywhere bears the marks of his influence. Mark Lance, my chair, made himself available at the drop of a dime anytime I had something to say or discuss this past year. He has been a relentless critic and supporter of my work, and I am very grateful for the seriousness with which he brought to this project. In my third year of graduate school I met weekly with Kate Withy to discuss Heidegger’s Being and Time. Unlike anyone I’ve met, Kate shows how reading a philosophical text can be as much an ethical activity as it is an intellectual one. Her commitment to the activity of philosophy has been a constant source of inspiration. Lastly, my gratitude to Jason Farr extends far beyond anything I can or want say here. For the past four years, hardly a day has gone by without his companionship. Much of this dissertation has been hammered out on our walks together, and his friendship has been a great joy in my life. I would like to thank Ella Taranto for her unabating enthusiasm for this project over the past year. I save my deepest gratitude for my family: my mother, Steffie; my father, Stewart; and my sister, Kameron. Questions that approach the philosophical are everywhere threatened by unintelligibility, and no experience is more familiar to me than the illusion of having meant something. Those listed above have saved me from the worst of my mistakes. Washington, DC October 2019 iv TABLE OF CONTENTS INTRODUCTION .......................................................................................................................................... 1 CHAPTER 1: FIRST-PERSON IMMUNITY TO ERROR THROUGH MISIDENTIFICATION ..................................................................................................... 21 CHAPTER 2: ARTICULATING THE FIRST-PERSON PLURAL ................................................... 53 CHAPTER 3: ON THE FIRST-PERSON PLURAL CHARACTER OF LINGUISTIC PRACTICE ............................................................................................................................. 82 CONCLUSION ............................................................................................................................................ 111 REFERENCES........................................................................................................................................... 116 v LIST OF TABLES TABLE 1. FORMS OF THE FIRST-PERSON PLURAL ....................................................................... 9 TABLE 2. FORMS OF THE FIRST-PERSON SINGULAR ............................................................... 36 TABLE 3. IMMUNITY AND ITS GROUNDS ....................................................................................... 48 TABLE 4. COMPLETE FORMS OF THE FIRST-PERSON PLURAL ............................................ 75 TABLE 5. DESCRIPTIONS BY EXEMPLIFICATION ...................................................................... 85 TABLE 6. LEFT-HAND SIDE OF DESCRIPTIONS BY EXEMPLIFICATION ......................... 96 TABLE 7. ACTIVE AND PASSIVE DIATHESES .............................................................................. 100 vi Introduction Here again we see language as the existence of spirit. Language is self-consciousness existing for others. It is self-consciousness which as such is immediately present , and as this self-consciousness, it is universal. —G.W.F. Hegel 1 This dissertation (or “essay,” as I’ve called it) concerns the philosophy of the first-person. It consists of three principal philosophical studies, each concerning a set of concepts that, when taken together, form a skeletal though unified account of the first-person. The first part concerns the various uses of the first-person singular (‘I’) as well as first-person immunity to error through misidentification (hereafter, first-person IEM). The second part concerns the various uses of the first-person plural (‘we’). I argue that (i) there are several distinct uses of the first-person plural pronoun, (ii) that each of these uses can be articulated inferentially, and (iii) that one use of the first-person plural—what I call the “generic use”—is conceptually basic. In the third part, I argue that the first-person plural pronoun is, at least on some of its uses, the grammatical mark of a certain form of self-conscious understanding, 1 Hegel, G.W.F. (2018). The Phenomenology of Spirit. Edited and Translated by Terry Pinkard. Cambridge University Press, §652. 1 and it is this kind of self-conscious understanding that underwrites the possibility of speaking a language. I end by outlining some structural relations between the various uses of the first-person singular and the first-person plural. According to the account offered here, the first-person singular and the first-person plural form a non-additive unitary structure. Correctly understood, an account of the first-person must include both the first-person singular and the first-person plural. These studies cover a wide swath of conceptual space, and from the perspective of contemporary philosophy of the first-person, it is not clear that they all fit under a common heading. In this introduction, I bring out some of the substantive interrelations between these studies. They build one upon the others, and the concepts elucidated in the initial parts are then put to work and further elaborated in the subsequent parts. By showing the conceptual interrelations between the topics listed above, I hope to begin to exfoliate the term ‘the first-person’ to find a place for these topics under one heading: the first-person. 2 This essay begins where many studies of the first-person begin: the source of first-person singular immunity to error through misidentification (first-person IEM). Abstractly, some statement or assertion ϕa has the property of first-person IEM if and only if any context that constitutes this assertion as knowledge that something is ϕ constitutes as well knowledge that one oneself is ϕ. But why is first-person IEM the standard starting point for work on the first-person? It is largely accepted (and I do accept) that first-person IEM is one of the principal marks of self-consciousness. When my use of ‘I’ is immune to error through misidentification, I know myself to be in some way or another, 2 Throughout this essay I use small capitals to denote concepts. I use italics for emphasis and to denote propositions, e.g., p. I use single quotes to mention terms or sentences—though see Chapter 3 §2 for some complications regarding the use/mention distinction—and I use double-quotes for quoting sources as well as intratextual indirect speech. I also use double-quotes to introduce terms-of-art. I use minuscule xs, ys, and ϕs as variables to range over various sorts of entities at issue in propositional schemas. (Though see Chapter 2 §2.2.1 for complications concerning syncategorematic verbal nexuses.) I use
Recommended publications
  • Sign Language Typology Series
    SIGN LANGUAGE TYPOLOGY SERIES The Sign Language Typology Series is dedicated to the comparative study of sign languages around the world. Individual or collective works that systematically explore typological variation across sign languages are the focus of this series, with particular emphasis on undocumented, underdescribed and endangered sign languages. The scope of the series primarily includes cross-linguistic studies of grammatical domains across a larger or smaller sample of sign languages, but also encompasses the study of individual sign languages from a typological perspective and comparison between signed and spoken languages in terms of language modality, as well as theoretical and methodological contributions to sign language typology. Interrogative and Negative Constructions in Sign Languages Edited by Ulrike Zeshan Sign Language Typology Series No. 1 / Interrogative and negative constructions in sign languages / Ulrike Zeshan (ed.) / Nijmegen: Ishara Press 2006. ISBN-10: 90-8656-001-6 ISBN-13: 978-90-8656-001-1 © Ishara Press Stichting DEF Wundtlaan 1 6525XD Nijmegen The Netherlands Fax: +31-24-3521213 email: [email protected] http://ishara.def-intl.org Cover design: Sibaji Panda Printed in the Netherlands First published 2006 Catalogue copy of this book available at Depot van Nederlandse Publicaties, Koninklijke Bibliotheek, Den Haag (www.kb.nl/depot) To the deaf pioneers in developing countries who have inspired all my work Contents Preface........................................................................................................10
    [Show full text]
  • Plural Noun Verb Agreement
    Plural Noun Verb Agreement Domenico usually syndicated days or casseroles recollectively when aphelian Jonah gelatinated finest and municipally. wittinglyTubular Nedwhen usually Roderic outsteps slavers some his culmination. cripplers or niggardising jingoistically. Burning and chronic Pate never supervening The individual actions of this case, trousers are replacing and verb and the sat are likely to match within noun with which verb agreement mistakes Subject-Verb all Across Prepositional Phrases AJE. That is that singular subject belongs with a singular verb form when a plural. For example topic sentence anyone has incorrect subject-verb agreement. Subject their Agreement TIP Sheets Butte College. Do collective nouns need the plural verb involve The Editor. We can help singular though plural verbs with many collective nouns Pamela and government is she of these. What verb agreement and improve your device. It's easy actually shine a bitter subject contains both a vast and its plural verb or pronoun joined by or the hero just agrees with lean part off the subject. If that noun is plural then the bound is now Take a look at them following two sentences Neither the players nor a coach wants to lose the motto Neither a coach. A random noun at the non-essential clause placed right degree to learn verb in. AWE Grammar Subject-Verb Agreement. It is a poor subject worth the presence of the only noun participants. Subject-Verb Agreement Educationcom. Subject-Verb Agreement schedule and verbs must living in. SUBJECT AND powerful AGREEMENT. Subject-Verb Agreement Examples Singular nor plural subjects are nouns and the rules for those are usually straightforward with most cases you can telling the.
    [Show full text]
  • Will Oxford Curriculum Vitae May 30, 2019
    Will Oxford Curriculum vitae May 30, 2019 CONTACT INFORMATION Address Department of Linguistics University of Manitoba 545 Fletcher Argue Building 15 Chancellor’s Circle Winnipeg, MB R3T 5V5 Phone 204-474-9623 Email [email protected] Website http://home.cc.umanitoba.ca/∼oxfordwr EDUCATION 2014 PhD, University of Toronto (Linguistics) Thesis: Microparameters of agreement: A diachronic perspective on Algonquian verb inflection 2007 MA, Memorial University of Newfoundland (Linguistics) Thesis: Towards a grammar of Innu-aimun particles 2005 BA, Memorial University of Newfoundland (Linguistics and French) 2005 Linguistic Society of America Summer Institute, MIT/Harvard PROFESSIONAL APPOINTMENTS 2019– Associate Professor, Department of Linguistics, University of Manitoba 2014–19 Assistant Professor, Department of Linguistics, University of Manitoba 2013–14 Lecturer, Department of Linguistics, University of Manitoba PUBLICATIONS Journal articles 2018 Oxford, Will. 2018. Inverse marking and Multiple Agree in Algonquin: Complementar- ity and variability. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory. (Published online; volume number to follow.) 2017 Oxford, Will. 2017. The Activity Condition as a microparameter. Linguistic Inquiry 48: 711–722. Will Oxford • 2 of 18 2017 Oxford, Will. 2017. Variation and change in the Degree Phrase. Linguistic Variation 17: 98–110. 2015 Oxford, Will. 2015. Patterns of contrast in phonological change: Evidence from Algo- nquian vowel systems. Language 91: 308–357. under Lochbihler, Bethany, Will Oxford, and Nicholas Welch. The person-animacy connection: revision Evidence from Algonquian and Dene. Revisions requested by Linguistic Inquiry. Books and edited volumes in prep Ghomeshi, Jila, and Will Oxford, eds. Special double issue of Canadian Journal of Lin- guistics on grammatical person. 2008 Oxford, Will.
    [Show full text]
  • Person and Number Agreement in American Sign Language
    Person and Number Agreement in American Sign Language Hyun-Jong Hahm The University of Texas at Austin Proceedings of the HPSG06 Conference Linguistic Modelling Laboratory Institute for Parallel Processing Bulgarian Academy of Sciences Sofia Held in Varna Stefan Müller (Editor) 2006 CSLI Publications http://csli-publications.stanford.edu/ Abstract American Sign Language (ASL) has a group of verbs showing agreement with the subject or/and object argument. There has not been analysis on especially number agreement. This paper analyzes person and number agreement within the HPSG framework. I discuss person and number hierarchy in ASL. The argument of agreement verbs can be omitted as in languages like Italian. The constraints on the type agreement-verb have the information on argument optionality. 1 Introduction1 During the past fifty years sign languages have been recognized as genuine languages with their own distinctive structure. Signed languages and spoken languages have many similarities, but also differ due to the different modalities: visual-gestural modality vs. auditory-vocal modality. This paper examines a common natural language phenomenon, verb agreement in American Sign Language (ASL, hereafter) through the recordings of a native signer within the framework of Head-Driven Phrase Structure Grammar (HPSG).2 Most analyses of signed languages have been based largely on transformational grammar. Cormier et al. (1999) discusses locus agreement in ASL, which is the first work in the HPSG framework. However, their work is limited to locus agreement with singular arguments. This paper examines person and number verb agreement. One type of verb shows agreement with object or/and subject arguments. Main focus in this paper is to show what constraints agreement verbs have, to explain the subject/object-verb agreement.
    [Show full text]
  • Pragmatic Person Features in Pronominal and Clausal Speech Act Phrases Hailey Hyekyeong Ceong* Abstract. This Paper Proposes
    2021. Proc Ling Soc Amer 6(1). 484–498. https://doi.org/10.3765/plsa.v6i1.4984. Pragmatic person features in pronominal and clausal speech act phrases Hailey Hyekyeong Ceong* Abstract. This paper proposes the necessity of pragmatic person features (Ritter and Wiltschko 2018) in pronominal and clausal speech act phrases in Korean, giving three main arguments for such necessity: (i) pragmatic person [ADDRESSEE] is needed for hearsay mye which expresses the meaning of you told me without the lexical verb of saying, (ii) pragmatic person [SPEAKER] is needed for the unequal distribution of first-person plural pronouns with exhortative ca ‘let us’, and (iii) pragmatic persons [SPEAKER], and [ADDRESSEE] are needed for the asymmetric distribution of a dative goal argument in secondhand exhortatives. Based on the compatibility and incompatibility of exhortative ca- and secondhand exhortative ca- mye clauses with a first-person pronoun (e.g., na ‘I’, ce ‘I’, wuli ‘we’, and cehuy ‘we’), I argue that pragmatic person features are needed in syntax to account for their distribution. Keywords. person; formality; clusivity; speech act phrases; hearsay; Korean 1. Introduction. This paper investigates pragmatic person features in pronominal and clausal speech act phrases focusing on the properties of first-and secondhand exhortatives in Korean. Based largely on evidence from a survey of variable pronominal paradigms across languages, Ritter and Wiltschko (2018) state that some languages lexicalize the distinction between prag- matic and grammatical person features. In this paper, I argue, on the basis of the distribution and interpretation of first-and secondhand exhortative markers, first-person pronouns, and the (dis-) agreement with the head of exhortatives and a first-person pronoun, that the distinction is lexical- ized in Korean as well.
    [Show full text]
  • Person Vs Spatial Agreement Final Revision
    Person vs. locative agreement: Evidence from late learners and language emergence Lily Kwok, Stephanie Berk, Diane Lillo-Martin University of Connecticut Abstract Sign languages are frequently described as having three verb classes. One, ‘agreeing’ verbs, indicates the person/number of its subject and object by modification of the beginning and ending locations of the verb. The second, ‘spatial’ verbs, makes a similar appearing modification of verb movement to represent the source and goal locations of the theme of a verb of motion. The third class, ‘plain’ verbs, is characterized as having neither of these types of modulations. A number of researchers have proposed accounts that collapse all of these types, or the person-agreeing and spatial verbs. Here we present evidence from late learners of American Sign Language and from the emergence of new sign languages that person agreement and locative agreement have a different status in these conditions and we claim their analysis should be kept distinct, at least in certain ways. Keywords Verb agreement Language development Delayed first language Language emergence Sign languages 1 1 Introduction: Verb classes in sign languages In very many sign languages, a subset of verbs can be modified in ways that some researchers have analyzed as a kind of verb agreement. Verbs that allow for this kind of modification use locations in the signing space (‘loci’) in a particular way, as described below. First, the loci have to be associated with a referent, either because the referent is physically present in the signing situation (present referents) or because the signer has indicated that a particular locus will be used to stand for a referent (non-present referents).
    [Show full text]
  • Noun Inflection and Pronouns
    Chapter 3 Noun inflection and pronouns The starting point for an investigation of Meskwaki morphology and syntax is agreement and case marking, the morphological expressions of syntactic relations. Meskwaki verbs are inflected for subject and object, nouns are inflected for possessors, and case marking is required on some oblique arguments and objects of adpositions. The present chapter describes the inflectional categories and their realization on NPs; verb inflection is covered in chapters 4 and 5.1 The categories of number and person are discussed in 3.1, gender in 3.2, and obviation, the discourse- based opposition of proximate and obviative third persons, in 3.3. Gender and obviation are treated at length since each has been the subject of controversy. Gender in Algonquian is usually described by linguists as an arbitrary system, but this perspective has been criticized by some anthropologists, who claim instead that the division of nouns into animate and inanimate gender is culturally significant. The position taken here is that gender is to some degree semantically motivated, but it is not predictable. As for obviation, Algonquianists disagree over the extent to which obviation is a syntactic phenomenon. It is shown in 3.3. that the domain within which obviation is obligatory may be defined in syntactic terms, but within that domain, the choice of which third person is proximate and which obviative depends almost entirely upon discourse factors, not upon syntactic factors. The categories of number, person, and obviation also play a role in the inflection of nouns for possessor, which is described in 3.4.
    [Show full text]
  • S Morphemes in L2 English an Investigation Into Student Essays in Grades 6, 9, and 12 in Sweden
    -S morphemes in L2 English An investigation into student essays in grades 6, 9, and 12 in Sweden Essay in English studies, HEN301 Klara Joelsson Supervisor: Olcay Sert Examiner: Thorsten Schröter Term: Autumn 2017 Abstract Swedish students’ morpheme acquisition order in English, including the acquisition of -s morphemes, is a relatively unstudied topic. Given the morphological differences between the English and Swedish languages, students learning English in Sweden may encounter difficulties in the use of the third person singular present tense -s morpheme. Research also shows that Swedish students use the plural -s morpheme rather accurately at 9-10 years old. Mapping out the usage of the -s morphemes may pave the way for understanding the difficulties learners encounter in the use of such morphemes. Furthermore, looking into the usage of morphemes that have the same form but different grammatical functions (e.g.,-s morphemes) may help us understand the relationship between different proficiency levels and the accuracy rate of morpheme usage in L2 English. To this end, this study investigates a corpus of texts produced by students learning English in Sweden in grades 6, 9 and 12. The focus is particularly on the frequency and accuracy of the use of -s morphemes, aiming at revealing which type of -s morphemes has a higher accuracy rate. The results show that the accuracy rate with the plural -s morpheme is relatively higher, whereas the possessive -‘s morpheme is the most problematic one across all levels. Additionally, the largest issue with the contracted verb form of be -‘s was that the students did not add an apostrophe between the word and the -s, rather than not using the form at all.
    [Show full text]
  • Passive Voice
    Passive Voice Strictly speaking, Passive Voice (PV) isn’t grammatically wrong (though we all know Microsoft Word loves to underline PV sentences with a wiggly green line). In most academic disciplines (and according to the APA manual), however, PV is considered stylistically inferior to active voice. What is the actual difference between PV and active sentences? A basic definition (using as few confusing grammar terms as possible) is that PV sentences emphasize who or what receives the action of the verb, and de‐emphasize the subject (the person/thing actually doing the action). *One method that often works to identify a PV sentence is to locate the word by in a sentence. Active Passive Monica doesn’t like low‐fat mayonnaise. Low‐fat mayonnaise isn’t liked (by Monica) Sylvia is writing crazy, fratricidal poems. Crazy, fratricidal poems are being written. Joey likes jam. Jam is liked (by Joey). Thomas will work on the light bulb. The light bulb will be worked on (by Thomas). On page 77 of the APA Publication Manual, Sixth Edition, (the first page of the ʺStyle & Usageʺ section) you will see this: Preferred Active Voice Preferred: ʺWe conducted the survey in a controlled setting.ʺ Nonpreferred: ʺThe survey was conducted in a controlled setting.ʺ Passive voice is formed by a conjugation of “to be” (is, am, are, was, were, been, be, being) + a past participle (basically a past tense verb). e.g. is liked; are being written; will be worked on Occasionally, passive voice can help to avoid “blaming” someone for a failure: Mistakes were made.
    [Show full text]
  • UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Previously Published Works
    UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Previously Published Works Title Person as an inflectional category Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/3w33c23j Journal Linguistic Typology, 21(3) ISSN 1430-0532 Author Nichols, J Publication Date 2017-12-20 DOI 10.1515/lingty-2017-0010 License https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/ 4.0 Peer reviewed eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California Author's final version. A number of errors and omissions were corrected by the editors and in the proofs, so do not quote this version; refer to the publication and quote from there: Nichols, Johanna. 2017. Person as an inflectional category. Linguistic Typology 21:3.387- 456. Person as an inflectional category Abstract The category of person has both inflectional and lexical aspects, and the distinction provides a finely graduated grammatical trait, relatively stable in both families and areas, and revealing for both typology and linguistic geography. Inflectional behavior includes reference to speech-act roles, indexation of arguments, discreteness from other categories such as number or gender, assignment and/or placement in syntax, arrangement in paradigms, and general resemblance to closed-class items. Lexical behavior includes sharing categories and/or forms and/or syntactic behavior with major lexical classes (usually nouns) and generally resembling open-class items. Criteria are given here for typologizing person as more vs. less inflectional, some basic typological correlations are tested, and the worldwide linguistic-geographical distribution is mapped. Keywords: person, inflection, morphology, linguistic geography, typology 2 Person as an inflectional category 1. Introduction Person, probably more than any other inflectional category, originates in arguments but is strongly prone to end up as indexation on predicates and other phrase heads.
    [Show full text]
  • This Textbook Investigates Definiteness Both from a Comparative and a The
    DEFA01 11/09/1998 5:23 PM Page i This textbook investigates definiteness both from a comparative and a the- oretical point of view, showing how languages express definiteness and what definiteness is. It surveys a large number of languages to discover the range of variation in relation to definiteness and related grammatical phenomena: demonstratives, possessives, personal pronouns. It outlines work done on the nature of definiteness in semantics, pragmatics and syn- tax, and develops an account on which definiteness is a grammatical cat- egory represented in syntax as a functional head (the widely discussed D). Consideration is also given to the origins and evolution of definite articles in the light of the comparative and theoretical findings. Among the claims advanced are that definiteness does not occur in all languages though the pragmatic concept which it grammaticalizes probably does, that many languages have definiteness in their pronoun system but not elsewhere, that definiteness is not inherent in possessives, and that definiteness is to be assimilated to the grammatical category of person. DEFA01 11/09/1998 5:23 PM Page ii DEFA01 11/09/1998 5:23 PM Page iii CAMBRIDGE TEXTBOOKS IN LINGUISTICS General editors: s. r. anderson, j. bresnan, b. comrie, w. dressler, c. ewen, r. huddleston, r. lass, d. lightfoot, j. lyons, p. h. matthews, r. posner, s. romaine, n. v. smith, n. vincent DEFINITENESS DEFA01 11/09/1998 5:23 PM Page iv In this series p. h. matthews Morphology Second edition b. comrie Aspect r. m. kempson Semantic Theory t. bynon Historical Linguistics j. allwood, l.-g.
    [Show full text]
  • Obligation Markers in Mexican Spanish: Competing Forms in a Changing System Katherine Honea Austin Peay State University
    Obligation markers in Mexican Spanish: competing forms in a changing system Katherine Honea Austin Peay State University Abstract Research on diachronic change and modality posit that modal verbs follow certain universal paths of devel- opment (e.g. Cornillie, 2007; Bybee & Fleischman, 1995; Bybee, Perkins & Pagliuca, 1994). This study examines the development of Spanish modality in Mexican Spanish using multivariate analyses, relative frequencies, and the comparative method as a means to uncover if and where linguistic changes are taking place and also to expose the subtle differences in patterns of use between two obligation markers – haber de ‘have to’ and tener que ‘have to’ - commonly used between the 16th and 20th centuries. Using the statistical program GoldVarb, 3,950 tokens were extracted from three corpora, the Corpus Diacrónico del Español (CORDE), the Corpus de Referencia del Español Actual (CREA) and the Internet Archive (archive. org), and analyzed and compared across centuries. Results indicated an overall shift in preference from haber de to tener que, suggesting that the system is undergoing longitudinal renewal. A statistical examination of this shift indicated that changes are reflected within tense, verb type, and grammatical person. This study provides evidence from Spanish that corroborates the claim that deontic modals tend to follow a universal path of change. In recent years research in linguistics has highlighted some of the changes that occur to modal systems across languages (e.g. Coates, 1983; Bybee & Pagliuca, 1984; Brinton, 1991; Bybee & Fleischman, 1995; Bybee, Pagliuca, & Perkins, 1991; Bybee, Perkins & Pagliuca, 1994; Narrog, 2005a; Blas Arroyo & González Martínez, 2014; Blas Arroyo & Vellón Lahoz, 2015).
    [Show full text]