Fermat, Leibniz, Euler, and the Gang: the True History of the Concepts of Limit and Shadow

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Fermat, Leibniz, Euler, and the Gang: the True History of the Concepts of Limit and Shadow Fermat, Leibniz, Euler, and the Gang: The True History of the Concepts of Limit and Shadow Tiziana Bascelli, Emanuele Bottazzi, Frederik Herzberg, Vladimir Kanovei, Karin U. Katz, Mikhail G. Katz, Tahl Nowik, David Sherry, and Steven Shnider he theories as developed by European Fermat determined the optimal value by impos- mathematicians prior to 1870 differed ing a condition using his adequality of quantities. from the modern ones in that none of But he did not really think of quantities as func- them used the modern theory of limits. tions, nor did he realize that his method produced Fermat develops what is sometimes only a necessary condition for his optimization Tcalled a “precalculus” theory, where the optimal condition. For a more detailed general introduc- value is determined by some special condition such tion, see chapters 1 and 2 of the volume edited by as equality of roots of some equation. The same Grattan-Guinness (Bos et al. 1980 [19]). can be said for his contemporaries like Descartes, The doctrine of limits is sometimes claimed to Huygens, and Roberval. have replaced that of infinitesimals when analysis Leibniz’s calculus advanced beyond them in was rigorized in the nineteenth century. While working on the derivative function of the variable x. it is true that Cantor, Dedekind and Weierstrass He had the indefinite integral whereas his prede- attempted (not altogether successfully; see Ehrlich cessors only had concepts more or less equivalent 2006 [32], Mormann & Katz 2013 [79]) to eliminate to it. Euler, following Leibniz, also worked with infinitesimals from analysis, the history of the limit such functions, but distinguished the variable (or concept is more complex. Newton had explicitly variables) with constant differentials dx, a status written that his ultimate ratios were not actually that corresponds to the modern assignment that x ratios but, rather, limits of prime ratios (see Russell is the independent variable, the other variables of 1903 [89, item 316, pp. 338-339]; Pourciau 2001 [84]). In fact, the sources of a rigorous notion of the problem being dependent upon it (or them) limit are considerably older than the nineteenthth functionally. century. Tiziana Bascelli is an independent researcher in history In the context of Leibnizian mathematics, the and philosophy of science. Her email address is tiziana. limit of f (x) as x tends to x0 can be viewed as [email protected]. the “assignable part” (as Leibniz may have put Emanuele Bottazzi is a Ph.D. student at the Università di it) of f (x0 + dx) where dx is an “inassignable” Trento, Italy. His email address is Emanuele.Bottazzi@ infinitesimal increment (whenever the answer is unitn.it. independent of the infinitesimal chosen). A modern Frederik Herzberg is an assistant professor of mathemati- formalization of this idea exploits the standard cal economics at Bielefeld University, Germany, as well as part principle (see Keisler 2012 [67, p. 36]). an external member of the Munich Center for Mathematical Philosophy, Germany. His email address is fherzberg@uni- Mikhail G. Katz is professor of mathematics at Bar Ilan Uni- bielefeld.de. versity, Israel. His email is [email protected]. Vladimir Kanovei is professor of mathematics at IPPI, Tahl Nowik is professor of mathematics at Bar Ilan Univer- Moscow, and MIIT, Moscow, Russia. His email address is sity, Israel. His email is [email protected]. [email protected]. David Sherry is professor of philosophy at Northern Arizona Karin U. Katz teaches mathematics at Bar Ilan University, University. His email address is [email protected]. Israel. Her email address is [email protected]. Steven Shnider is professor of mathematics at Bar Ilan DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1090/noti1149 University, Israel. His email is [email protected]. 848 Notices of the AMS Volume 61, Number 8 In the context of ordered fields E, the standard −1 0 1 2 3 4 part principle is the idea that, if E is a proper extension of the real numbers R, then every finite (or limited) element x 2 E is infinitely close to a suitable x0 2 R. Such a real number is called the standard part (sometimes called the shadow) of x, or in formulas, st(x) = x . Denoting by E the 0 f r collection of finite elements of E, we obtain a map r + α r + β r + γ st : Ef ! R: Here x is called finite if it is smaller (in absolute value) than some real number (the term finite is immediately comprehensible to a wide mathemati- cal public, whereas limited corresponds to correct st technical usage); an infinitesimal is smaller (in absolute value) than every positive real; and x is −1 0 1 r 2 3 4 infinitely close to x0 in the sense that x − x0 is infinitesimal. Figure 1. The standard part function, st, “rounds Briefly, the standard part function “rounds off” off” a finite hyperreal to the nearest real number. a finite element of E to the nearest real number The function st is here represented by a vertical (see Figure 1). projection. An “infinitesimal microscope” is used The proof of the principle is easy. A finite to view an infinitesimal neighborhood of a standard real number r , where α, β, and γ element x 2 E defines a Dedekind cut on the represent typical infinitesimals. Courtesy of subfield R ⊂ E (alternatively, on Q ⊂ R), and Wikipedia. the cut in turn defines the real x0 via the usual correspondence between cuts and real numbers. One sometimes writes down the relation Methodological Remarks x ≈ x0 To comment on the historical subtleties of judging to express infinite closeness. or interpreting past mathematics by present-day We argue that the sources of such a relation, standards,1 note that neither Fermat, Leibniz, Euler, and of the standard part principle, go back to nor Cauchy had access to the semantic founda- Fermat, Leibniz, Euler, and Cauchy. Leibniz would tional frameworks as developed in mathematics + discard the inassignable part of 2x dx to arrive at the end of the nineteenthth and first half of at the expected answer, 2x, relying on his law of the twentieth centuries. What we argue is that homogeneity (see the section entitled “Leibniz’s their syntactic inferential moves ultimately found Transcendental Law of Homogeneity”). Such an modern proxies in Robinson’s framework, thus inferential move is mirrored by a suitable proxy in placing a firm (relative to ZFC)2 semantic foun- the hyperreal approach, namely the standard part dation underneath the classical procedures of function. these masters. Benacerraf (1965 [10]) formulated Fermat, Leibniz, Euler, and Cauchy all used a related dichotomy in terms of mathematical one or another form of approximate equality, or the idea of discarding “negligible” terms. Their practice vs. mathematical ontology. inferential moves find suitable proxies in the For example, the Leibnizian laws of continuity context of modern theories of infinitesimals, and (see Knobloch 2002 [69, p. 67]) and homogene- specifically the concept of shadow. ity can be recast in terms of modern concepts The last two sections present an application of such as the transfer principle and the standard the standard part to decreasing rearrangements part principle over the hyperreals, without ever of real functions and to a problem on divergent appealing to the semantic content of the technical integrals due to S. Konyagin. development of the hyperreals as a punctiform con- This article continues efforts in revisiting the tinuum; similarly, Leibniz’s proof of the product history and foundations of infinitesimal calculus rule for differentiation is essentially identical, at and modern nonstandard analysis. Previous efforts the syntactic level, to a modern infinitesimal proof in this direction include Bair et al. (2013 [6]), (see, again, the section “Leibniz’s Transcendental Bascelli (2014 [7]), Błaszczyk et al. (2013 [15]), Law of Homogeneity”). Borovik et al. (2012 [16], [17]), Kanovei et al. (2013 [55]), Katz, Katz & Kudryk (2014 [61]), Mormann 1Some reflections on this can be found in Lewis (1975 [76]). et al. (2013 [79]), Sherry et al. (2014 [92]), Tall et 2The Zermelo–Fraenkel Set Theory with the Axiom of al. (2014 [97]). Choice. September 2014 Notices of the AMS 849 A-track and B-track formulated a condition, in terms of the mean value 5 The crucial distinction between syntactic and se- theorem, for what would qualify as a successful mantic aspects of the work involving mathematical theory of infinitesimals, and concluded: continua appears to have been overlooked by I will not say that progress in this direction R. Arthur who finds fault with the hyperreal proxy is impossible, but it is true that none of of the Leibnizian continuum, by arguing that the the investigators have achieved anything latter was non-punctiform (see Arthur 2013 [5]). positive (Klein 1908 [68, p. 219]). Yet this makes little difference at the syntactic Klein was referring to the current work on level, as explained above. Arthur’s brand of the syn- infinitesimal-enriched systems by Levi-Civita, Bet- categorematic approach following Ishiguro (1990 tazzi, Stolz, and others. In Klein’s mind, the [52]) involves a reductive reading of Leibnizian infinitesimal track was very much a current re- infinitesimals as logical (as opposed to pure) fic- search topic; see Ehrlich (2006 [32]) for a detailed tions involving a hidden quantifier à la Weierstrass, coverage of the work on infinitesimals around 1900. ranging over “ordinary” values. This approach was critically analyzed in (Katz & Sherry 2013 [65]), Formal Epistemology: Easwaran on Hyperreals (Sherry & Katz 2013 [92]), and (Tho 2012 [101]). Some recent articles are more encouraging in that Robinson’s framework poses a challenge to they attempt a more technically sophisticated ap- traditional historiography of mathematical analysis.
Recommended publications
  • Cauchy, Infinitesimals and Ghosts of Departed Quantifiers 3
    CAUCHY, INFINITESIMALS AND GHOSTS OF DEPARTED QUANTIFIERS JACQUES BAIR, PIOTR BLASZCZYK, ROBERT ELY, VALERIE´ HENRY, VLADIMIR KANOVEI, KARIN U. KATZ, MIKHAIL G. KATZ, TARAS KUDRYK, SEMEN S. KUTATELADZE, THOMAS MCGAFFEY, THOMAS MORMANN, DAVID M. SCHAPS, AND DAVID SHERRY Abstract. Procedures relying on infinitesimals in Leibniz, Euler and Cauchy have been interpreted in both a Weierstrassian and Robinson’s frameworks. The latter provides closer proxies for the procedures of the classical masters. Thus, Leibniz’s distinction be- tween assignable and inassignable numbers finds a proxy in the distinction between standard and nonstandard numbers in Robin- son’s framework, while Leibniz’s law of homogeneity with the im- plied notion of equality up to negligible terms finds a mathematical formalisation in terms of standard part. It is hard to provide paral- lel formalisations in a Weierstrassian framework but scholars since Ishiguro have engaged in a quest for ghosts of departed quantifiers to provide a Weierstrassian account for Leibniz’s infinitesimals. Euler similarly had notions of equality up to negligible terms, of which he distinguished two types: geometric and arithmetic. Eu- ler routinely used product decompositions into a specific infinite number of factors, and used the binomial formula with an infi- nite exponent. Such procedures have immediate hyperfinite ana- logues in Robinson’s framework, while in a Weierstrassian frame- work they can only be reinterpreted by means of paraphrases de- parting significantly from Euler’s own presentation. Cauchy gives lucid definitions of continuity in terms of infinitesimals that find ready formalisations in Robinson’s framework but scholars working in a Weierstrassian framework bend over backwards either to claim that Cauchy was vague or to engage in a quest for ghosts of de- arXiv:1712.00226v1 [math.HO] 1 Dec 2017 parted quantifiers in his work.
    [Show full text]
  • Fermat, Leibniz, Euler, and the Gang: the True History of the Concepts Of
    FERMAT, LEIBNIZ, EULER, AND THE GANG: THE TRUE HISTORY OF THE CONCEPTS OF LIMIT AND SHADOW TIZIANA BASCELLI, EMANUELE BOTTAZZI, FREDERIK HERZBERG, VLADIMIR KANOVEI, KARIN U. KATZ, MIKHAIL G. KATZ, TAHL NOWIK, DAVID SHERRY, AND STEVEN SHNIDER Abstract. Fermat, Leibniz, Euler, and Cauchy all used one or another form of approximate equality, or the idea of discarding “negligible” terms, so as to obtain a correct analytic answer. Their inferential moves find suitable proxies in the context of modern the- ories of infinitesimals, and specifically the concept of shadow. We give an application to decreasing rearrangements of real functions. Contents 1. Introduction 2 2. Methodological remarks 4 2.1. A-track and B-track 5 2.2. Formal epistemology: Easwaran on hyperreals 6 2.3. Zermelo–Fraenkel axioms and the Feferman–Levy model 8 2.4. Skolem integers and Robinson integers 9 2.5. Williamson, complexity, and other arguments 10 2.6. Infinity and infinitesimal: let both pretty severely alone 13 3. Fermat’s adequality 13 3.1. Summary of Fermat’s algorithm 14 arXiv:1407.0233v1 [math.HO] 1 Jul 2014 3.2. Tangent line and convexity of parabola 15 3.3. Fermat, Galileo, and Wallis 17 4. Leibniz’s Transcendental law of homogeneity 18 4.1. When are quantities equal? 19 4.2. Product rule 20 5. Euler’s Principle of Cancellation 20 6. What did Cauchy mean by “limit”? 22 6.1. Cauchy on Leibniz 23 6.2. Cauchy on continuity 23 7. Modern formalisations: a case study 25 8. A combinatorial approach to decreasing rearrangements 26 9.
    [Show full text]
  • Connes on the Role of Hyperreals in Mathematics
    Found Sci DOI 10.1007/s10699-012-9316-5 Tools, Objects, and Chimeras: Connes on the Role of Hyperreals in Mathematics Vladimir Kanovei · Mikhail G. Katz · Thomas Mormann © Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2012 Abstract We examine some of Connes’ criticisms of Robinson’s infinitesimals starting in 1995. Connes sought to exploit the Solovay model S as ammunition against non-standard analysis, but the model tends to boomerang, undercutting Connes’ own earlier work in func- tional analysis. Connes described the hyperreals as both a “virtual theory” and a “chimera”, yet acknowledged that his argument relies on the transfer principle. We analyze Connes’ “dart-throwing” thought experiment, but reach an opposite conclusion. In S, all definable sets of reals are Lebesgue measurable, suggesting that Connes views a theory as being “vir- tual” if it is not definable in a suitable model of ZFC. If so, Connes’ claim that a theory of the hyperreals is “virtual” is refuted by the existence of a definable model of the hyperreal field due to Kanovei and Shelah. Free ultrafilters aren’t definable, yet Connes exploited such ultrafilters both in his own earlier work on the classification of factors in the 1970s and 80s, and in Noncommutative Geometry, raising the question whether the latter may not be vulnera- ble to Connes’ criticism of virtuality. We analyze the philosophical underpinnings of Connes’ argument based on Gödel’s incompleteness theorem, and detect an apparent circularity in Connes’ logic. We document the reliance on non-constructive foundational material, and specifically on the Dixmier trace − (featured on the front cover of Connes’ magnum opus) V.
    [Show full text]
  • Lecture 25: Ultraproducts
    LECTURE 25: ULTRAPRODUCTS CALEB STANFORD First, recall that given a collection of sets and an ultrafilter on the index set, we formed an ultraproduct of those sets. It is important to think of the ultraproduct as a set-theoretic construction rather than a model- theoretic construction, in the sense that it is a product of sets rather than a product of structures. I.e., if Xi Q are sets for i = 1; 2; 3;:::, then Xi=U is another set. The set we use does not depend on what constant, function, and relation symbols may exist and have interpretations in Xi. (There are of course profound model-theoretic consequences of this, but the underlying construction is a way of turning a collection of sets into a new set, and doesn't make use of any notions from model theory!) We are interested in the particular case where the index set is N and where there is a set X such that Q Xi = X for all i. Then Xi=U is written XN=U, and is called the ultrapower of X by U. From now on, we will consider the ultrafilter to be a fixed nonprincipal ultrafilter, and will just consider the ultrapower of X to be the ultrapower by this fixed ultrafilter. It doesn't matter which one we pick, in the sense that none of our results will require anything from U beyond its nonprincipality. The ultrapower has two important properties. The first of these is the Transfer Principle. The second is @0-saturation. 1. The Transfer Principle Let L be a language, X a set, and XL an L-structure on X.
    [Show full text]
  • Communications Programming Concepts
    AIX Version 7.1 Communications Programming Concepts IBM Note Before using this information and the product it supports, read the information in “Notices” on page 323 . This edition applies to AIX Version 7.1 and to all subsequent releases and modifications until otherwise indicated in new editions. © Copyright International Business Machines Corporation 2010, 2014. US Government Users Restricted Rights – Use, duplication or disclosure restricted by GSA ADP Schedule Contract with IBM Corp. Contents About this document............................................................................................vii How to use this document..........................................................................................................................vii Highlighting.................................................................................................................................................vii Case-sensitivity in AIX................................................................................................................................vii ISO 9000.....................................................................................................................................................vii Communication Programming Concepts................................................................. 1 Data Link Control..........................................................................................................................................1 Generic Data Link Control Environment Overview...............................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • From Pythagoreans and Weierstrassians to True Infinitesimal Calculus
    CORE Metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk Provided by Keck Graduate Institute Journal of Humanistic Mathematics Volume 7 | Issue 1 January 2017 From Pythagoreans and Weierstrassians to True Infinitesimal Calculus Mikhail Katz Bar-Ilan University Luie Polev Bar Ilan University Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.claremont.edu/jhm Part of the Analysis Commons, and the Logic and Foundations Commons Recommended Citation Katz, M. and Polev, L. "From Pythagoreans and Weierstrassians to True Infinitesimal Calculus," Journal of Humanistic Mathematics, Volume 7 Issue 1 (January 2017), pages 87-104. DOI: 10.5642/ jhummath.201701.07 . Available at: https://scholarship.claremont.edu/jhm/vol7/iss1/7 ©2017 by the authors. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons License. JHM is an open access bi-annual journal sponsored by the Claremont Center for the Mathematical Sciences and published by the Claremont Colleges Library | ISSN 2159-8118 | http://scholarship.claremont.edu/jhm/ The editorial staff of JHM works hard to make sure the scholarship disseminated in JHM is accurate and upholds professional ethical guidelines. However the views and opinions expressed in each published manuscript belong exclusively to the individual contributor(s). The publisher and the editors do not endorse or accept responsibility for them. See https://scholarship.claremont.edu/jhm/policies.html for more information. From Pythagoreans and Weierstrassians to True Infinitesimal Calculus Cover Page Footnote Israel Science Foundation grant 1517/12 (acknowledged also in the body of the paper). This article is available in Journal of Humanistic Mathematics: https://scholarship.claremont.edu/jhm/vol7/iss1/7 From Pythagoreans and Weierstrassians to True Infinitesimal Calculus Mikhail G.
    [Show full text]
  • TME Volume 5, Numbers 2 and 3
    The Mathematics Enthusiast Volume 5 Number 2 Numbers 2 & 3 Article 27 7-2008 TME Volume 5, Numbers 2 and 3 Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.umt.edu/tme Part of the Mathematics Commons Let us know how access to this document benefits ou.y Recommended Citation (2008) "TME Volume 5, Numbers 2 and 3," The Mathematics Enthusiast: Vol. 5 : No. 2 , Article 27. Available at: https://scholarworks.umt.edu/tme/vol5/iss2/27 This Full Volume is brought to you for free and open access by ScholarWorks at University of Montana. It has been accepted for inclusion in The Mathematics Enthusiast by an authorized editor of ScholarWorks at University of Montana. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Montana Mathematics Enthusiast ISSN 1551-3440 VOL. 5, NOS.2&3, JULY 2008, pp.167-462 Editor-in-Chief Bharath Sriraman, The University of Montana Associate Editors: Lyn D. English, Queensland University of Technology, Australia Claus Michelsen, University of Southern Denmark, Denmark Brian Greer, Portland State University, USA Luis Moreno-Armella, University of Massachusetts-Dartmouth International Editorial Advisory Board Miriam Amit, Ben-Gurion University of the Negev, Israel. Ziya Argun, Gazi University, Turkey. Ahmet Arikan, Gazi University, Turkey. Astrid Beckmann, University of Education, Schwäbisch Gmünd, Germany. John Berry, University of Plymouth,UK. Morten Blomhøj, Roskilde University, Denmark. Robert Carson, Montana State University- Bozeman, USA. Mohan Chinnappan, University of Wollongong, Australia. Constantinos Christou, University of Cyprus, Cyprus. Bettina Dahl Søndergaard, University of Aarhus, Denmark. Helen Doerr, Syracuse University, USA. Ted Eisenberg, Ben-Gurion University of the Negev, Israel.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:1404.5658V1 [Math.LO] 22 Apr 2014 03F55
    TOWARD A CLARITY OF THE EXTREME VALUE THEOREM KARIN U. KATZ, MIKHAIL G. KATZ, AND TARAS KUDRYK Abstract. We apply a framework developed by C. S. Peirce to analyze the concept of clarity, so as to examine a pair of rival mathematical approaches to a typical result in analysis. Namely, we compare an intuitionist and an infinitesimal approaches to the extreme value theorem. We argue that a given pre-mathematical phenomenon may have several aspects that are not necessarily captured by a single formalisation, pointing to a complementar- ity rather than a rivalry of the approaches. Contents 1. Introduction 2 1.1. A historical re-appraisal 2 1.2. Practice and ontology 3 2. Grades of clarity according to Peirce 4 3. Perceptual continuity 5 4. Constructive clarity 7 5. Counterexample to the existence of a maximum 9 6. Reuniting the antipodes 10 7. Kronecker and constructivism 11 8. Infinitesimal clarity 13 8.1. Nominalistic reconstructions 13 8.2. Klein on rivalry of continua 14 arXiv:1404.5658v1 [math.LO] 22 Apr 2014 8.3. Formalizing Leibniz 15 8.4. Ultrapower 16 9. Hyperreal extreme value theorem 16 10. Approaches and invitations 18 11. Conclusion 19 References 19 2000 Mathematics Subject Classification. Primary 26E35; 00A30, 01A85, 03F55. Key words and phrases. Benacerraf, Bishop, Cauchy, constructive analysis, con- tinuity, extreme value theorem, grades of clarity, hyperreal, infinitesimal, Kaestner, Kronecker, law of excluded middle, ontology, Peirce, principle of unique choice, procedure, trichotomy, uniqueness paradigm. 1 2 KARINU. KATZ, MIKHAILG. KATZ, ANDTARASKUDRYK 1. Introduction German physicist G. Lichtenberg (1742 - 1799) was born less than a decade after the publication of the cleric George Berkeley’s tract The Analyst, and would have certainly been influenced by it or at least aware of it.
    [Show full text]
  • The Hyperreals
    THE HYPERREALS LARRY SUSANKA Abstract. In this article we define the hyperreal numbers, an ordered field containing the real numbers as well as infinitesimal numbers. These infinites- imals have magnitude smaller than that of any nonzero real number and have intuitively appealing properties, harkening back to the thoughts of the inven- tors of analysis. We use the ultrafilter construction of the hyperreal numbers which employs common properties of sets, rather than the original approach (see A. Robinson Non-Standard Analysis [5]) which used model theory. A few of the properties of the hyperreals are explored and proofs of some results from real topology and calculus are created using hyperreal arithmetic in place of the standard limit techniques. Contents The Hyperreal Numbers 1. Historical Remarks and Overview 2 2. The Construction 3 3. Vocabulary 6 4. A Collection of Exercises 7 5. Transfer 10 6. The Rearrangement and Hypertail Lemmas 14 Applications 7. Open, Closed and Boundary For Subsets of R 15 8. The Hyperreal Approach to Real Convergent Sequences 16 9. Series 18 10. More on Limits 20 11. Continuity and Uniform Continuity 22 12. Derivatives 26 13. Results Related to the Mean Value Theorem 28 14. Riemann Integral Preliminaries 32 15. The Infinitesimal Approach to Integration 36 16. An Example of Euler, Revisited 37 References 40 Index 41 Date: June 27, 2018. 1 2 LARRY SUSANKA 1. Historical Remarks and Overview The historical Euclid-derived conception of a line was as an object possessing \the quality of length without breadth" and which satisfies the various axioms of Euclid's geometric structure.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:1204.2193V2 [Math.GM] 13 Jun 2012
    Alternative Mathematics without Actual Infinity ∗ Toru Tsujishita 2012.6.12 Abstract An alternative mathematics based on qualitative plurality of finite- ness is developed to make non-standard mathematics independent of infinite set theory. The vague concept \accessibility" is used coherently within finite set theory whose separation axiom is restricted to defi- nite objective conditions. The weak equivalence relations are defined as binary relations with sorites phenomena. Continua are collection with weak equivalence relations called indistinguishability. The points of continua are the proper classes of mutually indistinguishable ele- ments and have identities with sorites paradox. Four continua formed by huge binary words are examined as a new type of continua. Ascoli- Arzela type theorem is given as an example indicating the feasibility of treating function spaces. The real numbers are defined to be points on linear continuum and have indefiniteness. Exponentiation is introduced by the Euler style and basic properties are established. Basic calculus is developed and the differentiability is captured by the behavior on a point. Main tools of Lebesgue measure theory is obtained in a similar way as Loeb measure. Differences from the current mathematics are examined, such as the indefiniteness of natural numbers, qualitative plurality of finiteness, mathematical usage of vague concepts, the continuum as a primary inexhaustible entity and the hitherto disregarded aspect of \internal measurement" in mathematics. arXiv:1204.2193v2 [math.GM] 13 Jun 2012 ∗Thanks to Ritsumeikan University for the sabbathical leave which allowed the author to concentrate on doing research on this theme. 1 2 Contents Abstract 1 Contents 2 0 Introdution 6 0.1 Nonstandard Approach as a Genuine Alternative .
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 6 Introduction to Calculus
    RS - Ch 6 - Intro to Calculus Chapter 6 Introduction to Calculus 1 Archimedes of Syracuse (c. 287 BC – c. 212 BC ) Bhaskara II (1114 – 1185) 6.0 Calculus • Calculus is the mathematics of change. •Two major branches: Differential calculus and Integral calculus, which are related by the Fundamental Theorem of Calculus. • Differential calculus determines varying rates of change. It is applied to problems involving acceleration of moving objects (from a flywheel to the space shuttle), rates of growth and decay, optimal values, etc. • Integration is the "inverse" (or opposite) of differentiation. It measures accumulations over periods of change. Integration can find volumes and lengths of curves, measure forces and work, etc. Older branch: Archimedes (c. 287−212 BC) worked on it. • Applications in science, economics, finance, engineering, etc. 2 1 RS - Ch 6 - Intro to Calculus 6.0 Calculus: Early History • The foundations of calculus are generally attributed to Newton and Leibniz, though Bhaskara II is believed to have also laid the basis of it. The Western roots go back to Wallis, Fermat, Descartes and Barrow. • Q: How close can two numbers be without being the same number? Or, equivalent question, by considering the difference of two numbers: How small can a number be without being zero? • Fermat’s and Newton’s answer: The infinitessimal, a positive quantity, smaller than any non-zero real number. • With this concept differential calculus developed, by studying ratios in which both numerator and denominator go to zero simultaneously. 3 6.1 Comparative Statics Comparative statics: It is the study of different equilibrium states associated with different sets of values of parameters and exogenous variables.
    [Show full text]
  • Math 3010 § 1. Treibergs Final Exam Name: Practice Problems March 30
    Math 3010 x 1. Final Exam Name: Practice Problems Treibergs March 30, 2018 Here are some problems soluble by methods encountered in the course. I have tried to select problems ranging over the topics we've encountered. Admittedly, they were chosen because they're fascinating to me. As such, they may have solutions that are longer than the questions you might expect on an exam. But some of them are samples of homework problems. Here are a few of my references. References. • Carl Boyer, A History of the Calculus and its Conceptual Development, Dover Publ. Inc., New York, 1959; orig. publ. The Concepts of the Calculus, A Critical and Historical Discussion of the Derivative and the Integral, Hafner Publ. Co. Inc., 1949. • Carl Boyer, A History of Mathematics, Princeton University Press, Princeton 1985 • Lucas Bunt, Phillip Jones, Jack Bedient, The Historical Roots of Elementary mathematics, Dover, Mineola 1988; orig. publ. Prentice- Hall, Englewood Cliffs 1976 • David Burton, The History of Mathmatics, An Introduction, 7th ed., McGraw Hill, New York 2011 • Ronald Calinger, Classics of Mathematics, Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs 1995; orig. publ. Moore Publ. Co. Inc., 1982 • Victor Katz, A History of Mathematics An introduction, 3rd. ed., Addison-Wesley, Boston 2009 • Morris Kline, Mathematical Thought from Ancient to Modern Times, Oxford University Press, New York 1972 • John Stillwell, Mathematics and its History, 3rd ed., Springer, New York, 2010. • Dirk Struik, A Concise History of Mathematics, Dover, New York 1967 • Harry N. Wright, First Course in Theory of Numbers, Dover, New York, 1971; orig. publ. John Wiley & Sons, Inc., New York, 1939.
    [Show full text]