Herder's Science of Man: the Origins of Anthropology in the Philosophy

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Herder's Science of Man: the Origins of Anthropology in the Philosophy Title Page Herder’s Science of Man: The Origins of Anthropology in the Philosophy of Language by William Eck BA in Philosophy, Harvard University, 2011 MA in Philosophy, University of Pittsburgh, 2015 Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Kenneth P. Dietrich School of Arts & Sciences in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Pittsburgh 2019 Committee Membershi p Page UNIVERSITY OF PITTSBURGH DIETRICH SCHOOL OF ARTS AND SCIENCES This dissertation was presented by William Eck It was defended on April 2, 2019 and approved by Robert Brandom, PhD, Distinguished Professor Stephen Engstrom, PhD, Professor Richard Moran, PhD, Professor John McDowell, Distinguished University Professor Mark Wilson, PhD, Distinguished Professor Dissertation Director: Robert Brandom, PhD, Distinguished Professor ii Copyright © by William Eck 2019 iii Abstract Herder’s Science of Man: The Origins of Anthropology in the Philosophy of Language William Alexander Eck, PhD University of Pittsburgh, 2019 Herder is one of the historical figures most responsible for the establishment of cultural anthropology as its own discipline. Before Herder, anthropology was conceived of as a science more closely related to biology and anatomy. Early anthropologists such as Ernst Platner proposed to answer philosophical questions by means of an examination of our physical bodies and nervous systems. Questions in logic, epistemology, and the theory of action were transformed by these anthropologists into questions concerning the workings of our nervous system and sensory organs. The central claim of this dissertation is that this transformation of anthropology from an empirical study of anatomy to an empirical study of culture and history was motivated by a new picture of the relationship between mind and language developed together by Hamann and Herder in the 18th century. The development of anthropology from a medical science into a study of culture in the work of Herder and Hamann was largely instigated by Kant’s critiques of Platner’s anthropology. Concepts central to philosophy, such as freedom and reason, are, on Kant’s view, fundamentally normative concepts, and therefore cannot be meaningfully investigated by means of an empirical study of the body. Hamann, however, develops a conception of reason as dependent on language, and therefore social and historical, and he comes to the thought that, just as languages are particular to a given community and a particular point in history, so must reason be. What this meant was that the study of reason not only could but must be made responsible to empirical evidence. Anthropology could then be rehabilitated into a study of reason and free action by means of the empirical study of language iv and culture. In Herder’s work, rehabilitating anthropology into an empirical discipline capable of drawing conclusions concerning reason, meanings, and values meant coming up with an understanding of normativity consistent with both empiricism and naturalism. I reconstruct Herder’s arguments for Einfühlung, a method of “feeling one’s way” into the culture under study, as providing an answer to the former problem, and his social conception of normativity, which provides an answer to the latter. v Table of Contents Preface ......................................................................................................................................... viii 1.0 Introduction.............................................................................................................................. 1 1.1 The Importance of Hamann ........................................................................................... 5 1.2 The Shape of the Project ............................................................................................... 11 2.0 Early Philosophical Anthropology and the Empirical ........................................................ 17 2.1 The State of Philosophical Psychology: Hume and Baumgarten ............................. 21 2.2 Platner’s Medical Anthropology ................................................................................... 25 2.3 Kant and the Limits of Medical Anthropology ........................................................... 31 2.4 Kant’s Pragmatic Anthropology ................................................................................... 36 3.0 Gnawing on the Bone: Language and Reason in Hamann ............................................... 42 3.1 Hamann’s Response to Enlightenment....................................................................... 46 3.2 Instruction, Imitation, and Reason .............................................................................. 56 3.3 Kant’s Purisms of Reason ............................................................................................. 64 3.4 Anthropology as an Edifying Discipline ..................................................................... 73 4.0 The Field, the King, and the Son: Hamann and Herder on Language ............................. 75 4.1 Herder’s Early Holism .................................................................................................. 78 4.2 The Young Herder’s Vision for Anthropology ............................................................ 82 4.3 Herder’s Early Picture of Language ............................................................................ 90 4.4 Hamann’s Critique: The King of the Field ................................................................. 97 4.5 “On the Cognition”: Herder on Normativity ............................................................ 101 vi 4.6 Herder’s Anthropological Holism: An Introduction ................................................ 111 5.0 Herder’s Anthropology as Philosophy ............................................................................... 115 5.1 National Character and Language ............................................................................. 118 5.2 Empirical Data as the Basis of Anthropology ........................................................... 129 5.3 Interpretation as an Act of Empathy ......................................................................... 140 5.4 Herder’s Pluralism ...................................................................................................... 156 5.5 Anthropology as a Future for Philosophy .................................................................. 164 5.6 The Advantages of Herder’s Anthropology .............................................................. 167 6.0 Einfühlung Examined ......................................................................................................... 174 6.1 Davidson on Interpretation......................................................................................... 177 6.2 Einfühlung as Radical Interpretation ........................................................................ 183 6.3 On Scheme and Content ............................................................................................. 191 6.4 Einfühlung as a Methodology .................................................................................... 200 7.0 In Herder’s Wake ................................................................................................................. 204 7.1 The Influence of Herder on Humboldt ..................................................................... 207 7.2 The Neo-Kantian Struggle and Cassirer ................................................................... 215 7.3 Wittgenstein’s Ethnographic Methodology .............................................................. 223 7.4 Ordinary Language and Ordinary Ethics.................................................................. 229 Bibliography .............................................................................................................................. 237 vii Preface The work which has come together in this dissertation would not have been possible, first and foremost, without the continuous help and support of its director, Robert Brandom. I would also like to thank the members of my committee: Stephen Engstrom, Richard Moran, John McDowell, and Mark Wilson, for both their comments and assistance in getting this project off the ground and their constant contribution to my philosophical upbringing. I would also like to thank my parents, Bill and Maria Eck, for their enduring support as I pursued both this particular project and philosophy more broadly, and my partner, Harriet Provine, without whom I may not have had the strength and focus required by a project of this nature. Although a number of people have provided me with helpful feedback throughout this process, I would like to single out Sabina Bremner and Jake McNulty for their insightful commentary on my chapters as this dissertation came to bear the shape it has. viii 1.0 Introduction One of the most pressing issues facing Kant’s philosophy, and Post-Kantian philosophy in its wake, consists in the question of how to address the relationship between the normative dimension and the empirical world of experience, or, in Kant’s terminology, the noumenal and the phenomenal.1 On Kant’s view, our capacity for practical reason brings with it a set of responsibilities and obligations to act in certain ways, just as our capacity for theoretical reason brings with it a set of responsibilities and obligations to judge and believe in certain ways. The relationship between these responsibilities
Recommended publications
  • Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics CAMBRIDGE TEXTS in the HISTORY of PHILOSOPHY
    CAMBRIDGE TEXTS IN THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY IMMANUEL KANT Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics CAMBRIDGE TEXTS IN THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY Series editors KARL AMERIKS Professor of Philosophy at the University of Notre Dame DESMOND M. CLARKE Professor of Philosophy at University College Cork The main objective of Cambridge Textsin the History of Philosophy is to expand the range, variety and quality of texts in the history of philosophy which are available in English. The series includes texts by familiar names (such as Descartes and Kant) and also by less well-known authors. Wherever possible, texts are published in complete and unabridged form, and translations are specially commissioned for the series. Each volume contains a critical introduction together with a guide to further reading and any necessary glossaries and textual apparatus. The volumes are designed for student use at undergraduate and postgraduate level and will be of interest not only to students of philosophy, but also to a wider audience of readers in the history of science, the history of theology and the history of ideas. For a list of titles published in the series, please see end of book. IMMANUEL KANT Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics That Will Be Able to Come Forward as Science with Selections from the Critique of Pure Reason TRANSLATED AND EDITED BY GARY HATFIELD University of Pennsylvania Revised Edition cambridge university press Cambridge, New York, Melbourne, Madrid, Cape Town, Singapore, São Paulo Cambridge University Press The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge cb2 2ru, UK Published in the United States of America by Cambridge University Press, New York www.cambridge.org Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9780521828246 © Cambridge University Press 1997, 2004 This publication is in copyright.
    [Show full text]
  • History of the Human Sciences
    History of the Human Sciences http://hhs.sagepub.com Herder: culture, anthropology and the Enlightenment David Denby History of the Human Sciences 2005; 18; 55 DOI: 10.1177/0952695105051126 The online version of this article can be found at: http://hhs.sagepub.com/cgi/content/abstract/18/1/55 Published by: http://www.sagepublications.com Additional services and information for History of the Human Sciences can be found at: Email Alerts: http://hhs.sagepub.com/cgi/alerts Subscriptions: http://hhs.sagepub.com/subscriptions Reprints: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.nav Permissions: http://www.sagepub.co.uk/journalsPermissions.nav Citations http://hhs.sagepub.com/cgi/content/refs/18/1/55 Downloaded from http://hhs.sagepub.com at CAPES on December 11, 2009 03HHS18-1 Denby (ds) 8/3/05 8:47 am Page 55 HISTORY OF THE HUMAN SCIENCES Vol. 18 No. 1 © 2005 SAGE Publications (London, Thousand Oaks, CA and New Delhi) pp. 55–76 [18:1;55–76; DOI: 10.1177/0952695105051126] Herder: culture, anthropology and the Enlightenment DAVID DENBY ABSTRACT The anthropological sensibility has often been seen as growing out of opposition to Enlightenment universalism. Johann Gottfried Herder (1744–1803) is often cited as an ancestor of modern cultural relativism, in which cultures exist in the plural. This article argues that Herder’s anthropology, and anthropology generally, are more closely related to Enlightenment thought than is generally considered. Herder certainly attacks Enlightenment abstraction, the arrogance of its Eurocentric historical teleology, and argues the case for a proto-hermeneutical approach which emphasizes embeddedness, horizon, the usefulness of prejudice. His suspicion of the ideology of progress and of associated theories of stadial development leads to a critique of cosmopolitanism and, particularly, of colonialism.
    [Show full text]
  • 3787324461 Lp.Pdf
    AUFKLÄRUNG Interdisziplinäres Jahrbuch zur Erforschung des 18. Jahrhunderts und seiner Wirkungsgeschichte In Verbindung mit der Deutschen Gesellschaft für die Erforschung des 18. Jahrhunderts herausgegeben von Lothar Kreimendahl, Monika Neugebauer-Wölk und Friedrich Vollhardt Redaktion: Marianne Willems Band 19 · Jg. 2007 Themenschwerpunkt: ERNST PLATNER (1744–1818) KONSTELLATIONEN DER AUFKLÄRUNG ZWISCHEN PHILOSOPHIE, MEDIZIN UND ANTHROPOLOGIE Herausgegeben von Guido Naschert und Gideon Stiening FELIX MEINER VERLAG 4 Inhalt ISSN 0178-7128 Aufklärung. Jahrbuch für die Erforschung des 18. Jahrhunderts und seiner Wirkungs- geschichte. – In Verbindung mit der Deutschen Gesellschaft für die Erforschung des 18. Jahrhunderts herausgegeben von Lothar Kreimendahl, Monika Neugebauer-Wölk und Friedrich Vollhardt. – Redaktion: Dr. Marianne Willems, Ludwig-Maximilians-Universität München, Institut für deutsche Philologie, Schellingstraße 3, 80799 München, E-mail: [email protected]. © Felix Meiner Verlag 2007. Das Jahrbuch und alle in ihm enthaltenen Beiträge sind ur- heberrechtlich geschützt. Jede Verwertung außerhalb der engen Grenzen des Urheber- rechtsgesetzes ist ohne Zustimmung des Verlages unzulässig und strafbar. Das gilt insbe- sondere für Vervielfältigungen, Übersetzungen, Mikroverfilmungen und die Einspeicherung und Verarbeitung in elektronischen Systemen. Textformatierung: Katja Mellmann. Druck und Bindung: Druckhaus „Thomas Müntzer“, Bad Langensalza. Printed in Germany. INHALT Guido Naschert, Gideon Stiening: Zur Einführung.
    [Show full text]
  • Herder. Physiology and Philosophical Anthropology Stefanie Buchenau
    Herder. Physiology and philosophical anthropology Stefanie Buchenau To cite this version: Stefanie Buchenau. Herder. Physiology and philosophical anthropology. Herder. Philosophy and Anthropology., 2017, 9780198779650. 10.1093/oso/9780198779650.003.0005. hal-02286197 HAL Id: hal-02286197 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-02286197 Submitted on 13 Sep 2019 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. 1 Stefanie BUCHENAU, “Herder. Physiology and Anthropology” in : Herder. Philosophy and Anthropology. éd. par Nigel de Souza et Anik Waldow, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2017. Herder. Physiology and philosophical anthropology1 Stefanie BUCHENAU, Paris2 Abstract: In eighteenth-century Germany, a new field of philosophical anthropology emerged, signaling a profound reconfiguration of what, originally, in the Renaissance, was primarily a medical and anatomical discipline. This paper focuses on Herder’s contribution to this development and investigates its medical and physiological context. Set in the context of the long history of anthropology, Herder’s philosophy can be seen as a response to recent discoveries in medicine and physiology. The major impulse came from Albrecht von Haller’s new distinction between the irritability of muscle and the sensibility of nerves, that he first presented in the 1740s and 1750s.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction
    Introduction Stefanie Buchenau & Roberto Lo Presti This volume focuses on medical and philosophical debates about human and animal cognition in the early modern age. At first sight, early modern dualism seems to imply the dismissal of most of the earlier medical and philosophical research perspectives on human cognition. If thought and cognition need to be viewed as properties characterizing those substances that are not part of the physical world, as the Cartesians assert, then it is necessary to establish a radical dichotomy between the mind and the body and between humans and animals; the view that considers mental func- tions as depending on and, possibly, developing from physical functions, seems to set out from the wrong premise. However, a closer glance reveals that this perspective on the modern age is somehow distorted. It is clear that the moderns never ceased to approach cognition—the brain and its functions—from both a medical and a philo - sophical perspective. They never lost interest in the anatomical structures and the physiological conditions underlying the rise, differentiation, and articulation of human and animal forms of cognition. On the contrary, they expanded the earlier practice of comparative anatomy and physiology to give it a new experimental and scientific basis, and they deepened their investigations of the human brain and the nervous system. Doing so, they drew on traditions from both antiquity and the Renaissance more than 1 ©2017 University of Pittsburgh Press. All rights reserved. 2 | STEFANIE BUCHENAU & ROBERTO LO PRESTI any other branch of science. Their field of inquiry had been largely estab- lished by Aristotle, whose zoological and psychological works attest to his intention to create a comprehensive “scientific” discourse on the soul as the informing principle of animal life.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant on Mental Disorder. Part 2: Philosophical Implications of Kant's
    History of Psychiatry, 20(3): 000–000 Copyright © 2009 SAGE Publications (Los Angeles, London, New Delhi, Singapore and Washington DC) www.sagepublications.com [200906] DOI: 10.1177/0957154X08337644 Kant on mental disorder. Part 2: Philosophical implications of Kant’s account PATRICK FRIERSON* Whitman College, USA This paper considers various philosophical problems arising from Kant’s account of mental disorder. Starting with the reasons why Kant considered his theory of mental disorder important, I then turn to the implications of this theory of Kant’s metaphysics, epistemology and ethics. Given Kant’s account of insanity as ‘a totally different standpoint . from which one sees all objects differently’ (7: 216), the Critique of Pure Reason should be read as offering a more social epistemology than typically recognized. Also, mental disorders that seem to undermine human freedom and rationality raise problems for Kant’s moral philosophy that his pragmatic anthropology helps to mitigate. Finally, I propose some implications of Kant’s account of mental disorder for contemporary work on mental illness. Keywords: epistemology; ethics; freedom; Kant; mental illness; superstition In a discussion of the possibility of a priori knowledge, Bertrand Russell critiques Kant’s account of such knowledge on the grounds that, among other things, Kant’s account depends upon contingent facts about human nature. As Russell (1912/1998: 87) explains: The thing to be accounted for is our certainty that the facts must always conform to logic and arithmetic. To say that logic and arithmetic are contributed by us does not account for this. Our nature is as much a fact of the existing world as anything, and there can be no certainly that it will remain constant.
    [Show full text]
  • Die Zeitgenössischen Rezensionen Der Elementarphilosophie K
    © 2008 AGI-Information Management Consultants May be used for personal purporses only or by libraries associated to dandelon.com network. DIE ZEITGENÖSSISCHEN REZENSIONEN DER ELEMENTARPHILOSOPHIE K. L. REINHOLDS Herausgegeben und eingeleitet von Faustino Fabbianelli o 2003 GEORG OLMS VERLAG HILDESHEIM • ZÜRICH • NEW YORK Inhaltsverzeichnis Abkürzungen IX-XI Einleitung XIII-LXXVIII Die zeitgenössischen Rezensionen der „Elementarphilosophie" XV Die Reaktionen auf die „Theorie des Vorstellungsvermögens" und die „Elementarphilosophie" - Eine kurze Geschichte (1789-1796) I. Antikantianer XXIX a) Das Philosophische Magazin und das Philosophische Archiv von Johann August Eberhard XXIX b) Aenesidemus-Schulze XXXVI c) Ernst Platner XLI d) Johann August Heinrich Ulrich XLIV II. Immanuel Kant XLVI III. Kantianer XLVIII IV. Die „Reinhold-Schule" LIV V. Salomon Maimon LVII VI. Johann Gottlieb Fichte LXV VII. Johann Heinrich Abicht LXVII1 VIII. Jakob Sigismund Beck LXXII Editorische Hinweise LXXVII Texte 1-262 Versuch einer neuen Theorie des menschlichen Vorstellungsvermögens, Prag und Jena 1789 1. Allgemeine Literatur-Zeitung, Nr. 357-358, Jena, Leipzig und Wien, 19.-20. November 1789. - Rezensent: August Wilhelm Rehberg 1 2. Gothaische gelehrte Zeitungen, 100. St., Gotha, 16. Dezember 1789 11 3. Göttingische Anzeigen von gelehrten Sachen, 14. St., Göttingen, 23. Januar 1790. - Rezensent: Johann Georg Heinrich Feder 18 VI Inhaltsverzeichnis 4. Annalen der neuesten Theologischen Litteratur und Kirchengeschichte, 2. Jg., Rinteln 1790, 6.-7. Woche. - Rezensent: Carl Gottfried Fürstenau 25 5. Erlangische gelehrte Zeitung, VIII.-IX. St., Erlangen, 17. u. 24. Februar 1790 31 6. Oberdeutsche allgemeine Litteraturzeitung, XXVIII. St., Salzburg, 5. März 1790 38 7. Tübingische gelehrte Anzeigen, 39. St., Tübingen, 17. Mai 1790. - Rezensent: Johann Friedrich Flatt 50 8.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 1.Pdf
    VU Research Portal The Usefulness of the Kantian Philosophy Marx, K.J. 2010 document version Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Link to publication in VU Research Portal citation for published version (APA) Marx, K. J. (2010). The Usefulness of the Kantian Philosophy: How Karl Leonhard Reinhold's Commitment to Enlightenment Influenced His Reception of Kant. General rights Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. • Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the public portal for the purpose of private study or research. • You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain • You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the public portal ? Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. E-mail address: [email protected] Download date: 27. Sep. 2021 chapter 1 Reinhold’s life and works The present study aims to shed light on Reinhold’s appropriation of the Kantian philoso- phy from his personal and philosophical background. Therefore, this chapter is devoted to introducing the man and his work in such a way as to contribute to the understanding of the relevant writings. It does not aim to be a full biographical account,1 since it only considers Reinhold’s life up to his departure from Jena to Kiel.
    [Show full text]
  • General Introduction
    Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-45250-2 - Immanuel Kant: Anthropology, History, and Education Edited by Gunter Zoller and Robert B. Louden Excerpt More information General introduction The present volume in The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant in Translation differs from all of the other volumes in the series in that it is not devoted solely to one major work of Kant (e.g., Critique of Pure Reason, Critique of the Power of Judgment), does not focus on writings from a specific period of his writing career (e.g., Theoretical Philosophy, 1755– 70; Opus postumum), is not confined to one specific subfield or area of his philosophy (e.g., Practical Philosophy, Religion and Rational Theology), and does not focus on a distinct genre of writing or mode of presentation (e.g., Correspondence, Lectures on Metaphysics, Lectures on Ethics). At the same time, Anthropology, History, and Education is no mere miscellany of occa- sional pieces that stands awkwardly outside of Kant’s central philosoph- ical concerns. Rather, these writings (whose original publication dates span thirty-nine years of Kant’s life) are linked together by their central focus on human nature – the most pervasive and persistent theme in all of Kant’s writings. Kant repeatedly claimed that the question “What is the human being?” should be philosophy’smost fundamental concern (J¨asche Logic 9: 25; cf. letter to Staudlin¨ of May 4, 1793, 11: 429, Metaphysik P¨olitz 28: 533–4),1 and over the years he approached the question from a va- riety of different perspectives. In addition to addressing this question indirectly under the guises of metaphysics, moral philosophy, and phi- losophy of religion, Kant broached the question directly in his extensive work on anthropology, history, and education gathered in the present volume.
    [Show full text]
  • Naturphilosophie, 1775-1799
    RICE UNIVERSITY The Creativity of Nature: The Genesis of Schelling's Naturphilosophie, 1775-1799 by Ryan J. Foster A THESIS SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE Doctor of Philosophy APPROVED, THESIS COMMITTEE Peter C. Caldwell, Professor of History and German & Slavic Studies Marlf Kulstad, Professor "of Philosophy Robert J. Richards,- Morris Fishbein Professor of the History of Science and Medicine, The University of Chicago HOUSTON, TEXAS DECEMBER 2008 UMI Number: 3362224 Copyright 2009 by Foster, Ryan J. INFORMATION TO USERS The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted. Broken or indistinct print, colored or poor quality illustrations and photographs, print bleed-through, substandard margins, and improper alignment can adversely affect reproduction. In the unlikely event that the author did not send a complete manuscript and there are missing pages, these will be noted. Also, if unauthorized copyright material had to be removed, a note will indicate the deletion. UMI® UMI Microform 3362224 Copyright 2009 by ProQuest LLC All rights reserved. This microform edition is protected against unauthorized copying under Title 17, United States Code. ProQuest LLC 789 East Eisenhower Parkway P.O. Box 1346 Ann Arbor, Ml 48106-1346 ABSTRACT The Creativity of Nature: The Genesis of Schelling's Naturphilosophie 1115-1199 by Ryan J. Foster The Naturphilosophie of Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Schelling (1775-1854) has been neglected in the Anglophone world for over 200 years, but his detractors are wrong in insisting that his system represented a disguised mysticism and a rejection of empirical science. Although Schelling studied theology at the famous Tubingen seminary, he dedicated his life to philosophy by 1794, eventually turning to an intensive study of the natural sciences.
    [Show full text]
  • Of the Early Enlightenment
    empiricismEarly Science and and the Medicine ‘reasonable 18-4-5 (2013) physicians’ 453-470 [131] ISSN 1383-7427 (print version) ISSN 1573-3823 (online version) ESM Experiment, Observation, Self-observation. Empiricism and the ‘Reasonable Physicians’ of the Early Enlightenment Carsten Zelle Ruhr-Universität Bochum* Abstract This article aims to analyze the mechanisms of empirical data collection in medicine and psychology in the early Enlightenment by means of experiment, observation and self-observation, while associating them with their discursive forms of representation; namely, the case narrative. The combination of empirical and discursive anthropo- techniques leads to explanations on the anthropoietics of the Enlightenment; i.e., the question of how the habitus of man was shaped around 1750. Texts of four German ‘reasonable physicians’ will be considered: Friedrich Hoffmann (1660–1742), Johann Gottlieb Krüger (1715–1759), Andreas Elias Büchner (1701–1769) and Johann August Unzer (1727–1799). Keywords Andreas Elias Büchner, Christian Wolff, Friedrich Hoffmann, Johann Gottlieb Krüger, Johann August Unzer, anthropology, casus, empirical psychology, empirico-rationalism, experientia, experiment, historia morbi, observation, poetics of knowledge, ratio, self- observation Introduction The theme of this article arose in the context of research into literary anthropology in the eighteenth century, which initially focused on a group of ‘reasonable physicians’ at the Prussian reform university of Halle/Saale. Having overcome Cartesian dualism of substance, philo- * Ruhr-Universität Bochum, Germanistisches Institut, Universitätsstraße 150, 44780 Bochum, Germany ([email protected]). This article has been translated from the German by Julia Lippmann (Bochum). [132] 454 carsten zelle sophically educated medical scientists such as Johann Gottlob Krüger (1715–1759) or Johann August Unzer (1727–1799) expanded their perspec- tive to focus on the ‘whole man’.
    [Show full text]
  • Was Behind the Newtonian Rejection of Hypotheses?
    This is a repository copy of What (else) was behind the Newtonian Rejection of Hypotheses?. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/156485/ Version: Accepted Version Book Section: Wilson, Catherine orcid.org/0000-0002-0760-4072 (2019) What (else) was behind the Newtonian Rejection of Hypotheses? In: Vanzo, Alberto and Anstey, Peter R., (eds.) Experiment, Speculation and Religion in Early Modern Philosophy. Routledge , New York . https://doi.org/10.4324/9780429022463 Reuse Items deposited in White Rose Research Online are protected by copyright, with all rights reserved unless indicated otherwise. They may be downloaded and/or printed for private study, or other acts as permitted by national copyright laws. The publisher or other rights holders may allow further reproduction and re-use of the full text version. This is indicated by the licence information on the White Rose Research Online record for the item. Takedown If you consider content in White Rose Research Online to be in breach of UK law, please notify us by emailing [email protected] including the URL of the record and the reason for the withdrawal request. [email protected] https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ ‘What (Else) was Behind the Newtonian Rejection of ‘Hypotheses’? Catherine Wilson To appear in a volume on Experiment, Speculation, and Religion in Early Modern Europe ed. By Peter Anstey and Alberto Vanzo. [I]t is proper to acquaint you that his great application in his inquirys into Nature did not make him unmindfull of the great Author of Nature; they were little acquainted with him, who imagine that he was so intent upon his studys of Geometry & Philosophy as to neglect that of Religion & other things subservient to it.
    [Show full text]