HYPERVENTILATING ABOUT INTRINSIC VALUE⋆ the Friends Of

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

HYPERVENTILATING ABOUT INTRINSIC VALUE⋆ the Friends Of FRED FELDMAN HYPERVENTILATING ABOUT INTRINSIC VALUE ? (Received 18 June 1998; accepted in revised form 10 July 1998) ABSTRACT. Plato, Aristotle, Kant, Brentano, Moore, and Chisholm have suggested “marks” or criteria of intrinsic goodness. I distinguish among eight of these. I focus in this paper on four: (a) unimprovability, (b) unqualifiedness, (c) dependence upon intrinsic natures, and (d) incorruptibility. I try to show that each of these is problematic in some way. I also try to show that they are not equivalent – they point toward distinct conceptions of intrinsic goodness. In the end it appears that none of them is fully satisfactory. Insofar as none of these succeeds, a fundamental problem remains for those who make use of the concept of intrinsic value. Precisely what do we have in mind when we say that some sort of value is “intrinsic”? KEY WORDS: Aristotle, axiology, Brentano, Chisholm, intrinsic value, Kant, Moore, Plato, The Good, theory of value 1. HYPERBOLIC REMARKS ABOUT INTRINSIC GOODNESS The friends of intrinsic value (and here I include myself) often lapse into poetry when they try to describe the object of their common interest. They speak in metaphor, analogy, and hyperbole. Plato, for example, gave analo- gies, saying that The Good is in some way like the sun.1 He suggested that each is a source of immense value. And just as the sun is too blinding to observe directly with the naked eye, so the form of The Good is too dazzling to contemplate directly with the naked mind. In a particularly high-flying passage, Plato compares a philosopher who has grasped the concept of goodness with a cave-dweller who has emerged from his subterranean cavern into the blinding light of the sun. He says: In the world of knowledge, the last thing to be perceived and only with great difficulty is the essential Form of Goodness. Once it is perceived, the conclusion must follow that, for all things, this is the cause of whatever is right and good; in the visible world it gives birth to light and to the lord of light, while it is itself sovereign in the intelligible world and the ? Paper presented at the 21st Annual Greensboro Symposium in Philosophy, April 5, 1998. I thank Alison McIntyre, Michael Zimmerman, Earl Conee, and Owen McLeod for helpful comments. 1 Plato, The Republic, translated and with an introduction and notes by Francis MacDonald Cornford (New York and London: Oxford University Press, 1958), p. 231. The Journal of Ethics 2: 339–354, 1998. © 1998 Kluwer Academic Publishers. Printed in the Netherlands. 340 FRED FELDMAN parent of intelligence and truth. Without having had a vision of this Form no one can act with wisdom, either in his own life or in matters of state.2 Those who perceive this blinding form of goodness will return to their cavern dazed and confused. Their former compatriots will think them ridiculous, and may even try to kill them. Immanuel Kant likewise drew comparisons. In describing a thing he took to be good in some outstandingly fundamental way, he tried to make clear that this thing does not have its value because of its capacity to produce good results. For even if “by the niggardly provision of a stepmotherly nature” it were to have no extrinsic value at all: ...itwouldstill sparkle like a jewel in its own right, as something that had its full worth initself....Itsusefulnesswouldbeonlyitssetting, as it were, so as to enable us to handle it more conveniently in commerce or to attract the attention of those who are not yet connoisseurs, but not to recommend it to those who are experts or to determine its worth.3 G. E. Moore himself seemed to have trouble finding clear, literal words to describe this object. In one place, while struggling to express himself, he said this: “If I am asked ‘what is good?’ my answer is that good is good, and that is the end of the matter. Or if I am asked ‘How is good to be defined?’ my answer is that it cannot be defined, and that is all I have to say about it.”4 It seems to me that we simply must do better than this. Metaphors and analogies and enforced silences will not help us to understand each other or the object of our common interest. I fear that by speaking in these confusing ways, we give aid and comfort to those who are no friends of intrinsic goodness. They are inclined to think that we don’t know what we are talking about (or maybe that we are talking about nothing at all). It also seems to me that insofar as there is confusion about intrinsic goodness, there is even greater confusion about the other concepts of axi- ology and perhaps also those of normative ethics. For it is reasonable to suppose that other value concepts (extrinsic goodness, signatory goodness, etc.) are to be defined by appeal to the concept of intrinsic goodness. It is also at least somewhat reasonable to suppose that the concept of intrinsic goodness plays some role in the explanation of such things as moral rightness of actions, and virtuosity of character. 2 Ibid. 3 Immanuel Kant, Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals, translated, with an Intro- duction, by Lewis White Beck (Indianapolis and New York: Bobbs-Merrill Company, Inc., 1959), p. 10. 4 G. E. Moore, Principia Ethica, edited and with an introduction by Thomas Baldwin (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), p. 58. HYPERVENTILATING ABOUT INTRINSIC VALUE 341 Thus, there is reason for us to insist upon clarity and precision in our statements about the nature of intrinsic goodness. 2. SEARCHING FOR A CRITERION OF INTRINSIC GOODNESS Here’s one way to tackle the question. We can assume that there are several sorts of goodness. First and foremost, of course, there is intrinsic goodness – the “Chief good” (in Aristotle’s phrase).5 In addition, there are several lesser sorts of goodness. These include goodness as a means, goodness as a sign, goodness as a part, overall goodness, logical goodness (as in “that’s a good argument, but the conclusion is false”), monetary goodness, aesthetic goodness, functional goodness and perhaps others. We can then try to determine what’s distinctive about intrinsic goodness. We can, that is, seek a “criterion” or “mark” of intrinsic goodness – something that will enable us to distinguish this most important sort of goodness from all the others. Several of the great moral philosophers of the past seem to have given some thought to this question, and some of them apparently have pro- vided suggestions of answers. Each of the suggestions embodies a sort of “guiding intuition” about intrinsic goodness. Each suggests one way to distinguish this value concept from others. I am aware of at least eight main guiding intuitions about intrinsic good- ness (Perhaps it would be better to say that I am aware of some passages in writings of great moral philosophers; if in these passages the philosophers were talking about intrinsic goodness, then these passages seem to contain hints of at least eight distinct guiding intuitions about intrinsic goodness). I here briefly list the guiding intuitions, give some references, and suggest some sketchy interpretations: 1. The intrinsically good as the unimprovably good. Hints of this intuition can be found in Plato in the Philebus, and in Aristotle in the Nicomachean Ethics I,7. Aristotle indicates that he is searching for something that is so good that if you have it, your life cannot be improved by the addition of anything else. Happiness (which he takes to be this marvelous thing) is alleged to be “not a thing counted as one good thing among others – if it were so counted it would clearly be made more desirable by the addition of even the least of goods; ...”Onthecontrary,happinessisunimprovably 5 Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, translated by W. D. Ross, in The Basic Works of Aris- totle edited and with an introduction by Richard McKeon (New York: Random House, 1941), p. 941 (Bk I, Ch 7. 1097a27). 342 FRED FELDMAN good – it is “...thatwhichwhenisolatedmakeslife desirable and lacking in nothing (NE I,7).” 2. The intrinsically good as the most final good. Again, this idea can be found in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. He says, “The chief good is something final. [it is] always desirable in itself and never for the sake of something else.” (NE I,7) 3. The intrinsically good as the unqualifiedly good. Immanuel Kant sug- gests this idea in the Groundwork, where he discusses the good will, which according to him shines like a jewel (Section One, first sentence): Nothing in the world – indeeed nothing even beyond the world – can possibly be conceived which could be called good without qualification except a good will....6 The good will is not good because of what it effects or accomplishes or because of its adequacy to achieve some proposed end; it is good only because of its willing, i.e., it is good of itself.7 (The first quoted sentence suggests that intrinsically good things are good without qualification; the second sentence assures us that he is talking about intrinsic goodness.) 4. The intrinsically good as the object of correct intrinsic love. This is Franz Brentano’s idea. In The Origin of our Knowledge of Right and Wrong,8 Brentano says: “We call a thing good when the love relating to it is correct. In the broadest sense of the term, the good is that which is worthy of love, that which can be loved with the love that is correct.” 5. The intrinsically good as that which is good in virtue of its intrinsic nature.
Recommended publications
  • Anthropocentrism
    Lecture 11: Anthropocentrism • Anthropocentrism and intrinsic value • Is anthropocentrism a good environmental philosophy? • Transformative power of nature • Problems with transformative power Friday, October 18, 2013 Topics • Anthropocentrism and intrinsic value • Is anthropocentrism a good environmental philosophy? • Transformative power of nature • Problems with transformative power Friday, October 18, 2013 Anthropocentrism • Human-centered • We only have direct moral obligations towards people • Animals only have instrumental value (that is, insofar as they are useful for our purposes). They don’t have intrinsic value (that is, in their own right). Friday, October 18, 2013 Anthropocentrism • The idea of intrinsic value is mysterious. (“the value it has all by itself”) • Usually, to say that something has value is to say that someone values it. Value presupposes a valuer (‘eye of the beholder’) • Value is typically not intrinsic to a thing, but “projected on it” by another (relative not absolute) Friday, October 18, 2013 Anthropocentrism • One reason that biocentrism and ecocentrism seem strange is that they entail that living things or ecosystems have intrinsic value - that is, it has value even if nobody values it. Friday, October 18, 2013 Kantianism • Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) • Kant believed that human beings possess intrinsic value. I value I value myself! food • This is because, unlike non- and sex humans, I can value myself. Consequently, I do not derive my value externally, but intrinsically. Friday, October 18, 2013 Kantianism • He also believed that only human beings have intrinsic value. That’s because only human beings have the self- awareness and reasoning capacity to value themselves. • This placed them in a unique moral category Friday, October 18, 2013 Direct and Indirect Obligations • Our direct moral obligations to others stems from a recognition of their intrinsic value.
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Philosophy
    An Introduction to Philosophy W. Russ Payne Bellevue College Copyright (cc by nc 4.0) 2015 W. Russ Payne Permission is granted to copy, distribute and/or modify this document with attribution under the terms of Creative Commons: Attribution Noncommercial 4.0 International or any later version of this license. A copy of the license is found at http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0/ 1 Contents Introduction ………………………………………………. 3 Chapter 1: What Philosophy Is ………………………….. 5 Chapter 2: How to do Philosophy ………………….……. 11 Chapter 3: Ancient Philosophy ………………….………. 23 Chapter 4: Rationalism ………….………………….……. 38 Chapter 5: Empiricism …………………………………… 50 Chapter 6: Philosophy of Science ………………….…..… 58 Chapter 7: Philosophy of Mind …………………….……. 72 Chapter 8: Love and Happiness …………………….……. 79 Chapter 9: Meta Ethics …………………………………… 94 Chapter 10: Right Action ……………………...…………. 108 Chapter 11: Social Justice …………………………...…… 120 2 Introduction The goal of this text is to present philosophy to newcomers as a living discipline with historical roots. While a few early chapters are historically organized, my goal in the historical chapters is to trace a developmental progression of thought that introduces basic philosophical methods and frames issues that remain relevant today. Later chapters are topically organized. These include philosophy of science and philosophy of mind, areas where philosophy has shown dramatic recent progress. This text concludes with four chapters on ethics, broadly construed. I cover traditional theories of right action in the third of these. Students are first invited first to think about what is good for themselves and their relationships in a chapter of love and happiness. Next a few meta-ethical issues are considered; namely, whether they are moral truths and if so what makes them so.
    [Show full text]
  • A Confusion in Goodness
    Forthcoming in Philosophical Studies The Pen, the Dress, and the Coat: A Confusion in Goodness Miles Tucker Abstract: Conditionalists say that the value something has as an end—its final value—may be conditional on its extrinsic features. They support this claim by appealing to examples: Kagan points to Abraham Lincoln’s pen, Rabinowicz and Rønnow-Rasmussen to Lady Diana’s dress, and Korsgaard to a mink coat. They contend that these things may have final value in virtue of their historical or societal roles. These three examples have become familiar: many now merely mention them to establish the conditionalist position. But the widespread faith in such cases is, I believe, unjustified. This is because, surprisingly, the pen, the dress, and the coat cannot have final value. I argue that the problem is internal: these cases are ruled out by every conditionalist account of final value. Further, the problem with these well-known cases applies to most other supposed examples of extrinsic, final goods. Thus nearly all cases given to support the conditionalist view cannot succeed. I suggest a kind of diagnosis: I claim that these examples are best seen as instances of sentimental value, rather than final value. I close by providing a brief account of sentimental value and explain how it relates to instrumental, intrinsic, and final goodness. Keywords: axiology, final value, intrinsic value, sentimental value The final value of a thing is the value it has for its own sake, or as an end. The intrinsic value of a thing is the value it has in itself or in virtue of its intrinsic features.1 Conditionalists hope to separate these two kinds of value.
    [Show full text]
  • Phil. 173: Metaethics Oct. 1, 2019 Lecture 9: Can Nihilists Live Their Nihilism?
    Phil. 173: Metaethics Oct. 1, 2019 Lecture 9: Can Nihilists Live Their Nihilism? I. If Nihilism Is True, Then What Should We Do? Whether this question is even coherent depends on what sort of nihilism one adheres to. A few varieties: moral nihilism: There is no such thing as rightness, wrongness, duty, obligation, or any other moral notion. practical nihilism: There is no such thing as practical normativity of any type (i.e. no such thing as any sort of normative notion that applies to action), including the following: what one ought morally to do; what one ought prudentially to do; and what one ought all-things-considered to do. normative nihilism: There is no such thing as any normative notion. If the type of nihilism in question is practical or normative nihilism, then the above question makes no sense. If the type of nihilism in question is moral nihilism, and if the only sort of practical consideration that one is not a nihilist about are prudential ones (as in Joyce’s case), then the question makes sense and is equivalent to: “If moral nihilism is true, then what is it in my best interests to do?” Note that in this case, in addition to being a moral nihilist, one is also a practical egoist. Note, also, that if one is a moral nihilist, it is not entirely clear that one is entitled to talk about what we should do as opposed to what I (or you, or she, or he, or they) should do—the move from what it’s in each of our individual interests to do, to what it’s in our collective interest to do, is precisely the sort of thing in which morality consists.
    [Show full text]
  • The Welfare-Nihilist Arguments Against Judgment Subjectivism
    Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy https://doi.org/10.26556/jesp.v19i3.886 Vol. 19, No. 3 · March 2021 © 2021 Author THE WELFARE-NIHILIST ARGUMENTS AGAINST JUDGMENT SUBJECTIVISM Anthony Kelley ne way to construe subjectivism about well-being is as the view that x is basically good for S if and only if, because, and to the extent that x is Ovalued, under the proper conditions, by S.1 Dale Dorsey argues for an idealized, judgment-based theory of valuing, one according to which a person values a thing if and only if, because, and to the extent that she would believe, under the proper conditions, that it is basically good for herself.2 Call subjectiv- ism about well-being coupled with a judgment-based theory of valuing judgment subjectivism.3 Judgment subjectivism is a remarkable theory, and Dorsey’s case for it is compelling. If the theory is true, then what is good for you is wholly determined by what you believe is good for you. It is somewhat surprising that it has not been the subject of much scrutiny.4 In this paper, I offer three related arguments against the theory. The arguments are about what judgment subjectivism im- plies about the well-being of welfare nihilists, people who believe that there are no welfare properties or at least that none are instantiated. I maintain that wel- 1 This construal is Dale Dorsey’s; see Dorsey, “Subjectivism without Desire,” 407. One con- troversial feature of Dorsey’s statement of subjectivism is that it requires that a theory link a person’s good to her values in order for it to count as subjectivist.
    [Show full text]
  • JÖRG LÖSCHKE/ Harmony and Intrinsic Value
    HARMONY AND INTRINSIC VALUE Jörg Löschke∗ Abstract: The concept of harmony does not play a very important role in contemporary analytic philosophy. In this paper, I argue that this peripheral status of the concept of harmony in analytic philosophy is not warranted. In fact, harmony might be the central normative concept: some philosophers think that complex unity is the metaphysical grounds of intrinsic value: whenever something is intrinsically valuable, it is so in virtue of the fact that disparate elements are brought into complex wholes. In this paper I discuss the possibility that harmony, rather than complex unity, plays this pivotal role. I conclude that, while there are some considerations in favour of this view, there are also considerations that speak against it; nevertheless, analytic philosophers should be more concerned with the concept of harmony than they have been so far. Introduction The concept of harmony has traditionally played an important role in the ethical outlooks of many cultures. It is an important concept in Confucianism; it plays an important role in the philosophy of Native Americans and other indigenous cultures (Miller 2019); and it has been an important concept in the thought of many classical Greek thinkers. However, this interest in harmony as an ethical concept has hardly carried over into contemporary analytical philosophy. Harmony is sometimes mentioned in passing when philosophers talk about another concept that has gained quite some attention, namely the concept of organic unity.1 The principle of organic unity says that the value of a whole need not equal the sum of the value of its individual parts2: for example, the individual brushstrokes of a painting have little or no value at all, but in combination, they can constitute great aesthetic value.
    [Show full text]
  • Pragmatism, Environmental Philosophy and the Ghost of William James
    Contemporary Pragmatism Editions Rodopi Vol. 9, No. 1 (June 2012), 25–52 ©2012 The Turn of the Skew: Pragmatism, Environmental Philosophy and the Ghost of William James Piers H.G. Stephens This paper addresses two issues: the controversy over pragmatism in environmental philosophy, and the habitual exclusion of William James’s work from serious examination. Addressing critiques of pragmatic naturalism from Max Horkheimer, Eugene Hargrove and Holmes Rolston, I argue that their criticisms misfire, primarily due to skewed perception derived from mis-interpretative projections of views to which pragmatism is not committed. I conclude that the critics’ major concerns are largely groundless, but that greater emphasis on pragmatism’s experiential aspect would clarify this. 1. Introduction The possibility that pragmatism might offer a new, better direction for environmental ethics was first raised by Anthony Weston in a path-breaking paper in 1985,1 since which time a significant debate between pragmatists and anti-pragmatists has affected the whole field. Arguments on the pragmatist side have tended to criticize the high level of abstraction found within environmental ethics, often arguing against the practical helpfulness of the habitual stress on theoretical axiology, especially intrinsic value theory. In place of these axiological emphases, pragmatists have urged a greater and more pluralist attendance to specifics of particular environmental problems, and aimed at a greater emphasis on practical policy convergence in political terms. Thus
    [Show full text]
  • Intrinsic Value: Analysing Moore's Aristotelian Approach
    INTRINSIC VALUE: Analysing Moore’s Aristotelian approach1 Prof. Dr. Darlei Dall´Agnol (Universidade Federal de Santa Catarina) [email protected] Introduction The aim of this article is to analyse a tension in Moore’s ethics between two conceptions of intrinsic value. Taking Moore’s own review of his work (RC: 555)2,I shall refer to them as ‘good in Moore’s “own usage”’ and ‘goodness in Aristotle’s sense.’ In the first section, I shall scrutinise the texts where Moore states his own view pointing out the difficulties of his approach. In the second, I shall discuss Moore’s commitment to the Aristotelian approach, maintaining that it provides a more adequate account of intrinsic value and that it occupies a central place in his ethics. In the third section, I shall try to develop this Aristotelian account avoiding Moore’s misinterpretations and exploring features that he seems to neglect. In the concluding part, I shall point out that, if this interpretation of Moore’s ethics is correct, it requires a re-assessment of some of the common interpretations of his meta-ethical commitments and it also leads to a different understanding of his normative ethics and some of its practical implications. First of all, it is necessary to mark clearly the texts where Moore holds his own view and where he uses an Aristotelian approach. We can take, for this purpose, his own testimony: ‘...in my paper on “Is Goodness a Quality?” I said that I thought that the particular sense of “good” with which I had been concerned, was one in which “is good” meant “is an experience which is worth having for its own sake.” This was a sheer mistake as to my own usage,’ (RC: 555).
    [Show full text]
  • An Examination of Thomas Hurka's Virtue Consequentialism by Crystal Rose Submitted to the Graduate Degree Program in Philosoph
    An Examination of Thomas Hurka’s Virtue Consequentialism by Crystal Rose Submitted to the graduate degree program in Philosophy and the Graduate Faculty of the University of Kansas in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. __________________________ Chair: Erin Frykholm __________________________ Ben Eggleston __________________________ Tom Tuozzo __________________________ Brad Cokelet __________________________ Pamela Gordon Date Defended: August 23, 2017 The Dissertation Committee for Crystal Rose certifies that this is the approved version of the following dissertation: An Examination of Thomas Hurka’s Virtue Consequentialism _________________________ Chairperson Erin Frykholm Date Approved: August 23, 2017 ii Abstract In this dissertation, I examine three separate issues pertaining to Thomas Hurka’s virtue consequentialism. Hurka’s account describes virtue as a positive orientation towards a good, and a vice as a negative orientation towards a good. The three goods that Hurka assigns to his theory are: pleasure, achievement, and knowledge. In my first paper I argue that an indirect approach to virtue development is more effective than a direct approach. I propose that an individual will have an easier time becoming virtuous if he works on cultivating his empathy, and being guided by a rational commitment to promoting the goods, rather than depending strictly on his willpower, and a rational commitment to promoting the goods. In the second paper I criticize Hurka’s definition of humility, and argue for my own account. Hurka characterizes humility as an asymmetrical recognition of goods. We might inflate the goods of others even though they are equal to our own, or we might deflate our own compared to the equal goods of others.
    [Show full text]
  • A Distinction in Value: Intrinsic and for Its Own Sake*
    A Distinction in Value: Intrinsic and For Its Own Sake* Wlodek Rabinowicz and Toni R¿nnow-Rasmussen Department of Philosophy, Lund University Several philosophers have recently argued for a distinction between intrinsic and final value. Following G. E. Moore (1903, 1922, 1993), an object is thought to be intrinsically valuable insofar as its value depends on (Ósupervenes onÓ) its internal properties. It has final value if it is valuable Ôas an endÕ, Ôfor its own sakeÕ, rather than for the sake of something else.1 From a traditional point of view in moral philosophy, this seems to be a distinction without a difference: To value something for its own sake is to value it for the properties it has in itself, i.e., to value it intrinsically, on the basis of its internal properties. This traditional view, however, has come under attack under recent years, notably by such philosophers as Christine Korsgaard (1983), Shelly Kagan (1992) and John OÕNeill (1992). All of them argue for the following claim: (C) There are final values that are not intrinsic. Entailment in the other direction has nearly never been questioned, as far as we know: It seems to be a general if not a universal view that all intrinsic values are final.2 In this paper we do *This paper is dedicated to Peter Gärdenfors on the occasion of his 50th birthday. The early drafts were presented in February 1999, at a Lund-Copenhagen symposium on intrinsic value, and then in March and May 1999, at the Departments of Philosophy in Stockholm and St Andrews.
    [Show full text]
  • 1. Introduction
    Analytic Metaphysics versus Naturalized Metaphysics: The Relevance of Applied Ontology Baptiste Le Bihan and Adrien Barton forthcoming in Erkenntnis Abstract: The relevance of analytic metaphysics has come under criticism: Ladyman & Ross, for instance, have suggested do discontinue the field. French & McKenzie have argued in defense of analytic metaphysics that it develops tools that could turn out to be useful for philosophy of physics. In this article, we show first that this heuristic defense of metaphysics can be extended to the scientific field of applied ontology, which uses constructs from analytic metaphysics. Second, we elaborate on a parallel by French & McKenzie between mathematics and metaphysics to show that the whole field of analytic metaphysics, being useful not only for philosophy but also for science, should continue to exist as a largely autonomous field. Keywords: analytic metaphysics, naturalized metaphysics, applied ontology, philosophy of physics, biomedical ontology. 1. Introduction According to Ladyman & Ross (2007) (“L&R” hereafter) analytic metaphysics should be discontinued because of its lack of emphasis on scientific knowledge that makes it a waste of intellectual resources. Although most analytic metaphysicians1 would 1 Here, we do not take stock on the nature of the relation between analytic metaphysics and naturalized metaphysics (e.g. the question of whether the latter is actually a part of the former according to some definitions of the fields), although we will argue at the end that analytic metaphysics should not be discontinued and can evolve largely independently from metaphysics of science. 1 presumably believe that their discipline has intrinsic value insofar as it describes the actual world or the field of possibilities, L&R deny this.
    [Show full text]
  • Rethinking Intrinsic Value Author(S): Shelly Kagan Source: the Journal of Ethics, Vol
    Rethinking Intrinsic Value Author(s): Shelly Kagan Source: The Journal of Ethics, Vol. 2, No. 4, Intrinsic Value (1998), pp. 277-297 Published by: Springer Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/25115588 Accessed: 13-08-2014 16:51 UTC Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Springer is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal of Ethics. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 130.132.173.11 on Wed, 13 Aug 2014 16:51:18 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions SHELLY KAGAN RETHINKING EXTRINSIC VALUE (Received 18 June 1998; accepted in revised form 11 July 1998) ABSTRACT. According to the dominant philosophical tradition, intrinsic value must depend solely upon intrinsic properties. By appealing to various examples, however, I argue that we should at least leave open the possibility that in some cases intrinsic value may be based in part on relational properties. Indeed, I argue that we should even be open to the possibility that an object's intrinsic value may sometimes depend (in part) on its instrumental value. If this is right, of course, then the traditional contrast between intrinsic value and instrumental value is mistaken.
    [Show full text]