Xunzi in the Light of the Guodian Manuscripts

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Xunzi in the Light of the Guodian Manuscripts -2- Xunzi in the Light of the Guodian Manuscripts Newly excavated manuscripts, as discussed in the Introduction, offer op­ portunities fo r a richer understanding of classical Chinese philosophy than was available to previous generations, even in China. Mter the dis­ covery in 1993 of a cache of bamboo manuscripts in an elite tomb at Guo­ dian, near Jingmen ntiF�, Hubei province #9.J;:ft�,1 the scholarly world celebrated the so-called Guodian Laozi: the three texts in the collection that are composed of material with close parallels in the received Lao·t.i. Now that this initial period of excitement has begun to ebb, it has be­ come clear that the other manuscripts from Guodian are at least as inter­ esting as the Laozi texts from a philosophical point of view and probably even more important from a historical point of view. The Guodian tomb has yielded the earliest editions of two canonical Confucian texts: Jet-Black Robes ( Ziyt) and The Five Forms of Conduct ( Wu xing) . Furthermore, the ex­ cavation yielded several previously unknown Confucian texts that shed light on the early history of the Confucian tradition. This chapter will fo cus on several texts from this last category: Cheng zhi wen zhi RIGZIIFJZ;2 Honoring Virtue and Morality (Zun deyi -��); The Xing Emerges from the Endowment (Xingzi ming chu '� §iii!±!);The Six Forms of Virtue (Liude 1\tfD ;3 Failure and Success Depend on Time ( Qjongda yi shi j'lJ jl�)�); The Way of Tang and Yu (Tang Yu zhi dao Mf.l1tZ.l�J;4 The Way of Integrity and Trustworthiness (Zhongxin zhi dao J!!. ffl'ZJ:i); and some unti­ tled miscellanies known as Collections of Sayings (Yucong �Ji). I believe that these works should be understood as doctrinal material deriving from a single tradition of Confucianism and datable to around 300 B.c. Of the surviving literature from the same period, they are closer to the Xunzi than to any other text and indeed anticipate several significant 36 Xunzi in the Light of the Guodian Manuscripts 37 ideas in Xunzi's philosophy.5 It is especially important to take note of these connections with Xunzi, in view of the emerging trend to associate the Guodian manuscripts with Zisi rJ!!.,6 the grandson of Confucius, whom Xunzi bitterly criticized. These newfound Confucian texts contain a number of core ideas that distinguish them clearly from Mencian Confucianism and suggest the ex­ istence of a vibrant non-Mencian tradition of Confucianism that culmi­ nated in Xunzi's system of moral philosophy. Before the discovery of the Guodian tomb, there was very little evidence concerning Xunzi's intel­ lectual antecedents, but it is apparent now that the Guodian manuscripts anticipate several characteristic themes in Xunzi 's philosophy: (1) the notion of "human nature" (xing ·�), including the controversy over whether the source of morality is "internal" or "external"; (2) the role of "learning" (xue ¥) and "habitual practice" (xi �) in moral develop­ ment; (3) the content and origin of "ritual" (li1ft), by which human beings accord with the Way; (4) the conception of the ruler as the "mind" (xin 1i:.') of the state; (5) and the psychological utility of "music" (yue �) in inculcating proper values. Each of these subjects will be addressed below. One caveat before proceeding: for a number of reasons, the Guodian manuscripts are among the most difficult texts yet excavated. First, the writing of the Chinese characters presents more epigraphic problems than that of manuscripts recently excavated at sites such as Mawangdui. The manuscripts contain dozens of opaque graphs, including many that simply cannot be deciphered (so-called daikao zi ��*) .7 Second, while the bamboo strips are well preserved, there are several lacunae, some of which occur, frustratingly, at crucial junctures in the argument of the texts. Finally, and most important, the texts had to be reconstructed strip by strip (since they were fo und, in the words of one Chinese expert, "in a pile"),8 and determining the correct sequence is often a matter of edu­ cated guesswork. Consequently, the current arrangement of the material is often questionable. For these reasons, the analysis and translations presented below are necessarily tentative. We can only hope that with more intensive study, and with the ongoing publication of the early Confucian texts housed at the Shanghai Museum, our understanding of the Guodian manuscripts will improve. Famously, Xunzi believes that human nature is "evil" � (or, more liter­ ally, "detestable")-by which he means that human beings naturally 38 After Confucius wish only to satisfy their appetitive and concupiscent desires. He is also famous for his distinctive use of the tenn xing, which is unlike that en­ countered, for example, in the Mencius. For Xunzi, xing means "what is so by birth" �Z..PJTPJ �1\i,9 or everything that we possess without hav­ ing exerted any effort to obtain it. For Mencius, in contrast, xing repre­ sents the natural course of development that an organism may be ex­ pected to undergo given nourishing conditions, as has been persuasively demonstrated in a classic study by A. C. Graham.10 This is no trivial point, because Xunzi's attempted refutation of Mencius is based on an under­ standing of the keyword xing that Mencius would not have accepted. The consequence of this difference in usage, as Dai Zhen M!l (1724-1777) pointed out, is that Xunzi uses xing to denote the characteristic that all members of a species have in common, whereas Mencius uses the term to denote the characteristic that distinguishes a species from all others.U (For example, all human beings have brains, but having brains does not distinguish human beings from all other species.) The Guodian manuscripts consistently use xing in the same sense as Xunzi:12 Within the four seas, [everyone's] xing is the same. That they use their minds differentlyis caused by teaching. 14 :!m.A.z.:[g:W$.A.z·rg: • ��ffii*fl";!FZW�� iP. • JW��i!?. • · • • • • JltPJ �Wfl"·rg: ffii :!m.A./F1l.T� iP. • 15 The xing of a sage and the xing of a mediocre person are without exception regulated by Heaven at birth; thus they are as they are.... Therefore the people allhave xing, and a sage cannot be without16 one. None of the Guodian manuscripts state explicitly that xing is evil, but it is evident that they regularly understand it to be naturally deficient of "morality" �. which must be attained from "outsid e" ��. In this respect, the conception of xing in the Guodian manuscripts could hardly come closer to that of Xunzi. TheXing Emerges fromEnd the owment explains that our inborn nature is revealed spontaneously in our responses to the stim­ uli around us and that it is not naturally moral. We must strive to "bring morality inside ourselves": Xunzi in the Light of the Guodian Manuscripts 39 JLA!ii!Efl"·� {,,t:JE� «f�rm�{'F «fmrm�rr · �'&'rm�JE · • · · w, �, tt · tt§$ili tfrf§x!J¥ ill , �z� · -tl!. • lUtJi��� JIU4t!&Z • · · U!Ml� ·!'if · -m1::�·� · • M�1lfm-m • �1lfm� � [m1lfijg] mz . ��1lftmf.l'1z •17 Although everyone has a xing, the mind has no fixed will. It becomes operative only after [it encounters] objects; it becomes active only after [it encounters] pleasure; it becomes fixed only after habitual practice. The qi of happiness, anger, grief, and sorrow is the xing. Once it is apparent externally, objects take hold of it. The xingemerges from the endowment; the endowment is sent down from Heaven. The Way begins in the one's responses toreality ;18 one's responses to reality are hom of one's xing. At first, one stays close to one's responses to reality; in the end, one stays close to morality. Those who know their responses to reality know how to express them; those who know morality know how to bring it inside themselves. In other words, when presented with external stimuli, we exhibit our qing •JW, our "responses to reality," which are simply a manifestation of our unsettled internal state. "Knowing one's qing" is identified here as a crucial first step toward moral development (and elsewhere, as described below, TheXing Emergesfrom the Endowrrumt emphasizes the importance of speaking in accord with one's genuine qing) . But the qing is only the be­ ginning of the Way; specifically, it lacks morality, for morality can come about only after "habitual practice," the conscious and habitual reforma­ tion of the xing. Other manuscripts in the corpus advance the same idea, affirming more explicitly that morality is not inborn. Humanity is hom in human beings; morality is hom of the Way. Some things are hom inside [us]; some things are hom outside [us] . ,20 e. ' f1'1-tP. ••• ��-tl!. Humanity is intemal. Morality is extemal. This last statement must be astonishing to any student of Chinese phi­ losophy, because it isattributed to the philosopher Gaozi 1!fr in a debate recorded in the received Mencius. The consequences of this association will be discussed later. For now, let us observe that this idea, namely, that 40 After Confucius morality must be obtained from outside the self, is common to Gaozi, Xunzi, and the Guodian manuscripts-and to virtually no other known members of the Confucian school. Xunzi postulates that, despite our natural evil, we can improve ourselves, namely, by what he calls "learning," which includes studying the canoni­ cal texts handed down by the ancient sages.21 These texts are the Rites, the Music, the Odes, the Documents, and the Spri ngs and Autumns, which in­ corporate the principles of the entire universe. <:m>z�x-tl?. <�>ztf1�-tl?.
Recommended publications
  • “Daoism and Confucianism” In: Liu X. (Eds) Dao Companion to Daoist Philosophy
    Lai Karyn. (2015) “Daoism and Confucianism” In: Liu X. (eds) Dao Companion to Daoist Philosophy. Dao Companions to Chinese Philosophy, vol 6. Springer, Dordrecht, pp. 489-511. This is the post-print version. The definitive version is to be found at: https://link-springer- com.wwwproxy1.library.unsw.edu.au/chapter/10.1007/978-90- 481-2927-0_21 This chapter relies on a distinction between Confucianism and Daoism made during the Han dynasty (漢朝: 206 BCE–220 CE) and further perpetuated in Chinese intellectual history. It examines the connections between pre-Qin (秦朝: 221– 206 BCE) Daoist and Confucian philosophies, focusing on their differences as well as similarities. While it has been traditionally accepted that there are many tensions, and even antagonism, between concepts and approaches in Daoist and Confucian thought, the discussion here also focuses on the historical linkages and philosophical continuities that at times blur the distinction between the two. The primary comparison here will be conducted at three levels: the individual within its environment, the socio-political world, and the cultivation of the self. These three levels of analysis are organized in three sections, from the more inclusive to the more specific. However, the sections are only theoretical divisions, since both Daoist and Confucian philosophies emphasize a concept of selfhood that focuses on an individual’s relationships with others, within a larger natural and cosmic environment. To more fully understand these comparisons, it is important also to examine the intellectual climate within which interactions between so- called Daoism and Confucianism took place. These details, including information gleaned from relatively recently discovered texts, are not merely tangential to our understanding of both philosophies.
    [Show full text]
  • The Old Master
    INTRODUCTION Four main characteristics distinguish this book from other translations of Laozi. First, the base of my translation is the oldest existing edition of Laozi. It was excavated in 1973 from a tomb located in Mawangdui, the city of Changsha, Hunan Province of China, and is usually referred to as Text A of the Mawangdui Laozi because it is the older of the two texts of Laozi unearthed from it.1 Two facts prove that the text was written before 202 bce, when the first emperor of the Han dynasty began to rule over the entire China: it does not follow the naming taboo of the Han dynasty;2 its handwriting style is close to the seal script that was prevalent in the Qin dynasty (221–206 bce). Second, I have incorporated the recent archaeological discovery of Laozi-related documents, disentombed in 1993 in Jishan District’s tomb complex in the village of Guodian, near the city of Jingmen, Hubei Province of China. These documents include three bundles of bamboo slips written in the Chu script and contain passages related to the extant Laozi.3 Third, I have made extensive use of old commentaries on Laozi to provide the most comprehensive interpretations possible of each passage. Finally, I have examined myriad Chinese classic texts that are closely associated with the formation of Laozi, such as Zhuangzi, Lüshi Chunqiu (Spring and Autumn Annals of Mr. Lü), Han Feizi, and Huainanzi, to understand the intellectual and historical context of Laozi’s ideas. In addition to these characteristics, this book introduces several new interpretations of Laozi.
    [Show full text]
  • The Analects of Confucius
    The analecTs of confucius An Online Teaching Translation 2015 (Version 2.21) R. Eno © 2003, 2012, 2015 Robert Eno This online translation is made freely available for use in not for profit educational settings and for personal use. For other purposes, apart from fair use, copyright is not waived. Open access to this translation is provided, without charge, at http://hdl.handle.net/2022/23420 Also available as open access translations of the Four Books Mencius: An Online Teaching Translation http://hdl.handle.net/2022/23421 Mencius: Translation, Notes, and Commentary http://hdl.handle.net/2022/23423 The Great Learning and The Doctrine of the Mean: An Online Teaching Translation http://hdl.handle.net/2022/23422 The Great Learning and The Doctrine of the Mean: Translation, Notes, and Commentary http://hdl.handle.net/2022/23424 CONTENTS INTRODUCTION i MAPS x BOOK I 1 BOOK II 5 BOOK III 9 BOOK IV 14 BOOK V 18 BOOK VI 24 BOOK VII 30 BOOK VIII 36 BOOK IX 40 BOOK X 46 BOOK XI 52 BOOK XII 59 BOOK XIII 66 BOOK XIV 73 BOOK XV 82 BOOK XVI 89 BOOK XVII 94 BOOK XVIII 100 BOOK XIX 104 BOOK XX 109 Appendix 1: Major Disciples 112 Appendix 2: Glossary 116 Appendix 3: Analysis of Book VIII 122 Appendix 4: Manuscript Evidence 131 About the title page The title page illustration reproduces a leaf from a medieval hand copy of the Analects, dated 890 CE, recovered from an archaeological dig at Dunhuang, in the Western desert regions of China. The manuscript has been determined to be a school boy’s hand copy, complete with errors, and it reproduces not only the text (which appears in large characters), but also an early commentary (small, double-column characters).
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Xunzi Versus Zhuangzi: Two Approaches to Death in Classical
    1 Xunzi versus Zhuangzi: Two Approaches to Death in Classical Chinese Thought Chris Fraser University of Hong Kong Abstract The contrasting approaches to death and bereavement in classical Confucianism and Daoism epitomize the different orientations of the two ethical traditions. Confucianism, here represented by Xunzi, interprets and manages death and bereavement through distinctive cultural practices, specifically rituals and associated norms of propriety, which are intended to bring order, harmony, and beauty to human events and conduct. Daoism, here represented by the Zhuangzi, contextualizes and copes with death and loss through an understanding of and identification with natural processes. Both approaches address death and bereavement through a systematic, naturalistic philosophy of life that makes no appeal to a conception of divinity or a personal afterlife. For Xunzi, the heart of this system is ritual propriety, through which all human affairs—including inevitable, natural events such as death—must be mediated. For the Zhuangzi, by contrast, rigid, ritualized cultural forms are an obstacle to coping efficiently with natural processes such as death. Rather than constructing a sphere of “the human” as distinct from “the natural,” the Zhuangzi urges us to situate the human within nature in a way that removes the opposition between the two. This essay contrasts and critiques the two approaches, contending that although Xunzi’s theory of ritual presents a plausible account of the relation between humanity, culture, and nature, it fails to address death appropriately as an inexorable, natural event. By contrast, the Zhuangzi presents an attractive way of relating human life and death to nature and thus perhaps offers a means of finding solace concerning death.
    [Show full text]
  • Xunzi and Early Han Philosophy Author(S): Paul R
    Harvard-Yenching Institute Xunzi and Early Han Philosophy Author(s): Paul R. Goldin Source: Harvard Journal of Asiatic Studies, Vol. 67, No. 1 (Jun., 2007), pp. 135-166 Published by: Harvard-Yenching Institute Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/25066840 . Accessed: 06/01/2014 01:27 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Harvard-Yenching Institute is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Harvard Journal of Asiatic Studies. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Mon, 6 Jan 2014 01:27:31 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Xunzi and Early Han Philosophy PAUL R. GOLDIN University ofPennsylvania cultural prestige of the philosopher Xunzi (third century b.c.) The has reached extreme highs and lows over the centuries. In his own day, he was revered as "the most senior of the masters" (zui wei some lao shi ?SUii?fl?)1 and numbered among his students of themost influential men in the Chinese world, including Han Fei (d. 233 b.c.) and Li Si $|ft (d. 208 b.c.). He was stillwidely celebrated in theWest ern Han dynasty, when Dong Zhongshu ?#af (fl.
    [Show full text]
  • Han Feizi's Criticism of Confucianism and Its Implications for Virtue Ethics
    JOURNAL OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY Journal of Moral Philosophy 5 (2008) 423–453 www.brill.nl/jmp Han Feizi’s Criticism of Confucianism and its Implications for Virtue Ethics * Eric L. Hutton Department of Philosophy, University of Utah, 215 S. Central Campus Drive, CTIHB, 4th fl oor, Salt Lake City, UT 84112, USA [email protected] Abstract Several scholars have recently proposed that Confucianism should be regarded as a form of virtue ethics. Th is view off ers new approaches to understanding not only Confucian thinkers, but also their critics within the Chinese tradition. For if Confucianism is a form of virtue ethics, we can then ask to what extent Chinese criticisms of it parallel criticisms launched against contemporary virtue ethics, and what lessons for virtue ethics in general might be gleaned from the challenges to Confucianism in particular. Th is paper undertakes such an exercise in examining Han Feizi, an early critic of Confucianism. Th e essay off ers a careful interpretation of the debate between Han Feizi and the Confucians and suggests that thinking through Han Feizi’s criticisms and the possible Confucian responses to them has a broader philosophical payoff , namely by highlighting a problem for current defenders of virtue ethics that has not been widely noticed, but deserves attention. Keywords Bernard Williams, Chinese philosophy, Confucianism, Han Feizi, Rosalind Hursthouse, virtue ethics Although Confucianism is now almost synonymous with Chinese culture, over the course of history it has also attracted many critics from among the Chinese themselves. Of these critics, one of the most interesting is Han Feizi (ca.
    [Show full text]
  • Zhuangzi, Perspectives, and Greater Knowledge*
    Zhuangzi, perspectives, and greater knowledge* Donald Sturgeon PhD candidate, University of Hong Kong Although the text of the Zhuangzi1 seems to present many prima facie skeptical arguments, there has been much debate as to the nature of its skeptical stance, and even whether or not its stance is substantively skeptical at all.2 Chad Hansen and Chris Fraser have argued that the Zhuangzi does take a substantively skeptical position, but that this position is more nuanced than simply holding skepticism about the possibility of all knowledge.3 This paper will attempt to build upon Chris Fraser’s proposal that the Zhuangzi is skeptical about our ability to know a privileged class of ultimately correct ways of drawing distinctions (果是 guo shi and 果非 guo fei), but does not question our ability to know how to distinguish things in an ordinary, provisional and commonsense sense. I will attempt to engage with both sides of the debate, by firstly accepting that the Zhuangzi takes a substantive skeptical stance, but also arguing that in doing so the text also provides a positive account of how to improve our epistemic position – an account which * Forthcoming in Philosophy East and West 65:3. 1 This paper will focus on knowledge and skepticism in the anthology known as the Zhuangzi, beginning with ideas presented most clearly in the Qiwulun chapter, but will also consider how these ideas cohere with those presented elsewhere in the anthology – including in passages that may be later additions to the text by one or more distinct authors or editors. Even where this is so, it still seems useful to ask how – if at all – these ideas fit together, and why they might have been collected together in such an anthology.
    [Show full text]
  • Chinese Religions, Fall 2010-11 CRN 16006
    Religious Studies 302 Chinese Religions, Fall 2010-11 CRN 16006 Instructor: Mark T. Unno, Office: PLC 812, Tel. 346-4973, Email: [email protected] Office hours: Mondays and Wednesdays 1:00-2:00 p.m. Lectures: 12:00-12:50 p.m. MWF 16 PAC; Home Page: http://www.uoregon.edu/~munno/ Selected strands of religious thought in China. This course will examine various Chinese religious traditions, in particular Confucianism, Daoism, and Buddhism. Rather than provide a comprehensive survey of all of the strands of Chinese religion (which is impractical in a ten-week quarter), this course emphasizes in-depth understanding through the study of primary religious texts supported by secondary readings in the relevant scholarly literature. The focus of our examination will be on the philosophical understanding of religious ideas in critical historical context. We will study key ideas within the context of various cultural and historical issues such as gender, class, and ritual. Requirements 1. Attendance: Required. Students can have one unexcused absence without penalty. Each class missed thereafter without prior permission will result in 1/2 grade penalty for the course grade. 2. Short exams: There will be two short, in-class exams, based on materials from the readings, lectures, and course web site. 3. Short papers: Students will write three short papers based on topics that will be provided by the instructor. 4. Final paper: Each student will hand in a medium length final paper of 4-6 pages double-spaced. Suggested topics will be provided. Students may choose to create their own topics with the consent of the instructor.
    [Show full text]
  • The Human and the Inhuman: Ethics and Religion in the Zhuangzi
    bs_bs_banner ERIC S. NELSON THE HUMAN AND THE INHUMAN: ETHICS AND RELIGION IN THE ZHUANGZI Abstract One critique of the early Daoist texts associated with Laozi and Zhuangzi is that they neglect the human and lack a proper sense of ethical personhood in maintaining the primacy of an impersonal dehumanizing “way.” This article offers a reconsideration of the appropriateness of such negative evaluations by exploring whether and to what extent the ethical sensibility unfolded in the Zhuangzi is aporetic, naturalistic, and/or religious. As an ethos of cultivating life and free and easy wandering by performatively enacting openness and responsiveness to things in an immanent this-worldly context, the Zhuangzi is oriented toward the relational attunement of disposition and practice rather than toward metaphysics or religion in a transcendent sense. It consequently suggests an immanent anarchic ethics without principles while neither forgetting nor reifying the sacred and the mundane in its playful illumination of the biospiritual dynamics of cultivating life. I. INTRODUCTION One reading of the texts associated with the names Laozi 老子 and Zhuangzi 莊子 is that they ignore the properly human and ethical in upholding the supremacy of an indifferent,1 impersonal, and fatalis- tic dao.2 Such concerns are formulated in the “Confucian” (ru 儒) tradition, for example by Xunzi 荀子, and remain prominent among both contemporary religious and secular personalist critics of early Daoism who argue that it lacks an appropriate conception of ethical personhood and moral agency. Early Daoist language appears paradoxically both impersonal and individualistic in how it depicts the sage as differentiated from ERIC S.
    [Show full text]
  • Egoism in Chinese Ethics
    E Egoism in Chinese Ethics Kim-Chong CHONG The term “egoism,” wei wo, in Chinese ethics is usu- universalization and the maximization of self-interest. ally associated with Yang Zhu, but it encompasses is- Ethical egoism is therefore largely a heuristic device sues much wider than the narrow and overriding con- of the twentieth century, although the two criteria just ception of self-interest attributed to him by Mencius mentioned had precursors in Hobbes and Kant. (Mengzi): “Even if he could benefit the Empire by A. C. Graham (1989) recounts a dialogue in the pulling one hair he would not do it (Mencius 7A26).” Mozi between Wumazi and Mozi, which can illustrate These include questions about the possibility of uni- the issue of universalization, although we shall have versal love, the extension of benevolence, human na- to qualify this later. Wumazi claims to be incapable ture, the ultimate motivation for behavior, self-cultiva- of concern for everyone; he says that although he is tion, the value of spontaneity, and the conflict between concerned for the people of his own neighborhood, he particularistic concern—i.e., concern for one’s is by degrees more concerned for his family than for kin—and nonparticularistic concern. These related is- his neighbors, for his parents than for other members sues surround classical figures like Mozi, Yang Zhu, of his family, and ultimately for himself than for his Gaozi, Mencius, and, beyond them, the neo-Confu- parents. The issue for Mozi is whether this is a morality cians. that can be prescribed: “Are you going to hide your Before describing these issues, we should first mention egoism in western ethics, where it has often morality, or tell others about it?” To Wumazi’s re- been discussed in terms of ethical egoism and psycho- sponse that he will tell others, Mozi argues that Wu- logical egoism.
    [Show full text]
  • Dao Companion to the Philosophy of Xunzi, Dao Companions to Chinese Philosophy 7, DOI 10.1007/978-94-017-7745-2 1 2 M
    Eric L. Hutton Editor Dao Companion to the Philosophy of Xunzi Editor Eric L. Hutton Department of Philosophy University of Utah Salt Lake City , UT, USA Dao Companions to Chinese Philosophy ISBN 978-94-017-7743-8 ISBN 978-94-017-7745-2 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-94-017-7745-2 Library of Congress Control Number: 2016953488 © Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2016 This work is subject to copyright. All rights are reserved by the Publisher, whether the whole or part of the material is concerned, specifi cally the rights of translation, reprinting, reuse of illustrations, recitation, broadcasting, reproduction on microfi lms or in any other physical way, and transmission or information storage and retrieval, electronic adaptation, computer software, or by similar or dissimilar methodology now known or hereafter developed. The use of general descriptive names, registered names, trademarks, service marks, etc. in this publication does not imply, even in the absence of a specifi c statement, that such names are exempt from the relevant protective laws and regulations and therefore free for general use. The publisher, the authors and the editors are safe to assume that the advice and information in this book are believed to be true and accurate at the date of publication. Neither the publisher nor the authors or the editors give a warranty, express or implied, with respect to the material contained herein or for any errors or omissions that may have been made. Printed on acid-free paper This Springer imprint is published by Springer Nature The registered company is Springer Science+Business Media B.V.
    [Show full text]
  • Xunzi and Han Fei on Human Nature
    Xunzi and Han Fei on Human Nature Alejandro Bárcenas ABSTRACT: It is commonly accepted that Han Fei studied under Xunzi sometime during the late third century BCE. However, there is surprisingly little dedicated to the in-depth study of the relationship between Xunzi’s ideas and one of his best-known followers. In this essay I argue that Han Fei’s notion of xing, commonly translated as human nature, was not only influenced by Xunzi but also that it is an important feature of his political philosophy. “Aus so krummem Holze, als woraus der Mensch gemacht ist, kann nichts ganz Gerades gezimmert werden.” —Immanuel Kant, Idee zu einer allgemeinen Geschichte in weltbürgerlicher Absicht. T FIRST SIGHT, IT DOES not seem far-fetched to suggest that a thorough Astudy of Han Fei’s notion of xing (性)—commonly translated as human na- ture—should include an analysis of the role played by his teacher Xunzi. However, suggesting the existence of such influence has proven to be a quite controversial topic. For the most part recent interpreters of the history of Chinese philosophy tend to briefly mention the existence of some sort of philosophical relationship between Xunzi and Han Fei.1 What scholars generally acknowledge is that a master-student relationship existed between the two, which typically indicates some kind of influ- ence (or rejection) of one by the other. However, there is surprisingly little dedicated to the in-depth study of the relationship between Xunzi’s ideas and one of his best- known followers. This absence of detailed analysis is even more puzzling when it is contrasted with the profuse amount of research during recent years, dedicated to comparing Xunzi with Mencius, his most famous counterpart.2 In the following 1See, Geng Wu, Die Staatslehre des Han Fei: ein Beitrag zur chinesischen Idee der Staatsräson (Vienna: Springer, 1978) p.
    [Show full text]