Midwestern Baptist Theological Seminary

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Midwestern Baptist Theological Seminary MIDWESTERN BAPTIST THEOLOGICAL SEMINARY UNCHANGING BEAUTY: FAITH AS THE APPREHENSION OF THE IMMUTABLE GOD’S GLORY REVEALED IN THE SON A PAPER SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE COURSE DR 01-37395 ADVANCED SYSTEMATIC THEOLOGY BY SAMUEL G. PARKISON KANSAS CITY, MISSOURI AUGUST, 19 2018 Introduction Two topics that have generated considerable attention in the field of systematic theology as of late are aesthetics1 and classical theism.2 Though neither topic is new to the Church’s life, each have experienced relative neglect and resurgence. However, notwithstanding how much attention both these theological loci have received, they are not often discussed in relation to one another. This paper seeks to explore their convergence in Christology. To be specific, we seek to answer: is the doctrine of divine immutability compatible with an aesthetic-soteriology, in which Christological glory elicits faith? This paper will contend for the affirmative: indeed, not only is divine immutability compatible with such an aesthetic-soteriology, it is necessary for it to work. Christology will thus serve as the gravitational center for this study, pulling these two areas of interest together. The aesthetic interest of saving faith is Christ, the Word made flesh. Likewise, the central challenge to divine immutability is Christ, the Word made flesh. Structurally, this paper will move from an examination of the aesthetic dimension of saving faith, to Christ’s revelatory role of the immutable God in the incarnation, and will conclude with a brief consideration and response to divine immutability’s challenge in light of the incarnation. Thus, we will show that saving faith in Jesus—as a response to his irresistible beauty—results in mediated access to the unchanging, beautiful Triune God. 1 E.g., David Bently Hart, The Beauty of the Infinite: The Aesthetics of Christian Truth (Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 2003); Jonathan King, The Beauty of the Lord: Theology as Aesthetics (Bellingham: Lexham Press, 2018); Patrick Sherry, Spirit and Beauty: An Introduction to Theological Aesthetics, 2nd Edition (Albans Place: SCM Press, 2002). 2 E.g., James E. Dolezal, God without Parts: Divine Simplicity and the Metaphysics of God’s Absoluteness (Eugene: Pickwick Publications, 2011), All That Is In God: Evangelical Theology and the Challenge of Classical Christian Theism (Grand Rapids: Reformed Heritage Books, 2017); Jordan P. Barrett, Divine Simplicity: A Biblical and Trinitarian Account (Minneapolis: Fortress Press, 2017). 1 Comprehending and Apprehending Christological Glory We begin our study where new life for a Christian begins: the apprehension of Christ in gratuitous faith. New life begins when those who live in the darkness “receive” the “true light,” and “believe in his name” (Jn. 1:9, 12).3 This apprehension, if it be legitimate (cf., Jn. 2:24), must be glad.4 To sell one’s positions to buy a field wherein lies a hidden treasure out of compulsion will not do; saving faith is the joyous reception of such a treasure (Matt. 13:44).5 The object of saving faith is Jesus Christ.6 Our present interest is the nature of the subjective experience of “believing” and “receiving” Jesus—his person and his message. What is the sinner feeling in his transformation into sainthood as he clings to Christ? Of the many responses that 3 Those who “receive” and “believe” are the very ones who become the children of God, who are “born again” and who experience “eternal life:” “The prologue thus introduces us to the ‘new birth’ theme of ch.3… Those who receive the Word are identical with those who believe in his name, and they are identical with those who are born of God.” D.A. Carson, The Gospel According to John (Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1991), 126. Cf., Andreas J. Köstenberger and Scott R. Swain, Father, Son and Spirit: The Trinity and John’s Gospel (Downers Grove: InterVarsity Press, 2008), 81. 4 “The ‘name’ is more than a label; it is the character of the person, or even the person himself… at its best, such faith yields allegiance to the Word, trust him completely, acknowledge his claims and confesses him with gratitude. That is what it means to ‘receive’ him.” Carson, John, 125-126. Emphasis added. 5 J.C. Ryle makes the point beautifully: “We see, in this simple picture, the conduct of a true Christian explained. He is what he is, and does what he does in his religion, because he is thoroughly persuaded that it is worthwhile… He sees in Christ an endless ‘treasure;’ he sees in Christ a precious ‘pearl:’ to win Christ he will make any sacrifice. This is true faith: this is the stamp of a genuine work of the Holy Ghost.” Expository Thoughts on Matthew (Edinburgh: Banner of Truth, 1986), 122-123. Cf., David Platt, Christ-Centered Exposition Commentary: Exalting Jesus In Matthew (Nashville: B&H Publishing Group, 2013), 183. 6 “Faith, after all, is not belief of propositions of truth respecting the Savior, however essential an ingredient of faith such belief is. Faith is trust in a person, the person of Christ, the Son of God and Savior of the lost. It is entrustment of ourselves to him. It is not simply believing him; it is believing in him and on him.” John Murray, Redemption Accomplished and Applied (Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1955), 117. 2 can be given, “affectious delight in Jesus” is the most relevant at present. The sinner considers Jesus, in the moment of saving faith, attractive, desirable, and worthy of devotion. In a word, the sinner considers him beautiful. One figure for whom this concept was of preeminent concern is Jonathan Edwards. Few theologians in the Church’s history feature beauty in their theological system as much as Edwards.7 For Edwards, salvation occurred on account of a dialogue between divine beauty and saving faith—the objective display of divine beauty and the subjective apprehension thereof.8 Roland Delattre, identifying these two dialogical elements as beauty (objective) and sensibility (subjective), explains that they are “essentially and internally related not only as sense of beauty and object of that sense but also together constituting the more objective and more subjective aspects of what Edwards calls the ‘inherent good.’”9 Edwards specifies the enjoyment of this good arises not initially from an apprehension of God in general, rather the “first foundation” of 7 See, Michael J. McClymond and Gerald R. McDermott, The Theology of Jonathan Edwards (New York: Oxford University Press, 2012), 93. Cf., Kin Yip Louie, The Beauty of the Triune God: The Theological Aesthetics of Jonathan Edwards (Eugene: Pickwick Publications, 2013), 13. 8 “Edwards’s teaching on beauty and aesthetics moved back and forth from an objective to a subjective pole... For Edwards, beauty was both objective and subjective. Beauty had an effect, and the effect was an affect (i.e., feeling). Yet Edwards balanced the objective and subjective aspects of beauty so that neither eclipsed the other.” McCymond and McDermott, The Theology of Jonathan Edwards, 99. 9 Roland Andre Delattre Beauty and Sensibility in the Thought of Jonathan Edwards: An Essay in Aesthetics and Theological Ethics (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1968), 3. Or, in Edwards’ own words, when God imparts a “divine and supernatural light” to elicit saving faith, there “is not only a rational belief that God is holy, and that holiness is a good thing; but there is a sense of the loveliness of God’s holiness. There is not only a speculatively judging that God is gracious, but a sense how amiable God is upon that account; or a sense of the beauty of this divine attribute.” Jonathan Edwards, “A Divine and Supernatural Light” in Works of Jonathan Edwards Online, vol. 17, Sermons and Discourses, 1730-1733 (Jonathan Edwards Center at Yale University 2008). 3 this delight is in Christ and “is His own beauty.”10 Edwards is saying, in other words, seeing Christ in his beauty creates saving faith. Edwards is not alone here.11 In fact, Paul seems make the very point in 2 Corinthians 4:6: “For God, who said, ‘Let light shine out of darkness,’ has shone in our hearts to give the light of the knowledge of the glory of God in the face of Jesus Christ.”12 Peter Balla, commenting on this verse, explains “God creates the Christian by showing a person God’s glory on Christ’s face.”13 This verse’s context in 2 Corinthians further demonstrates the experience is soteriologically normative; it is not idiosyncratic to Paul and his Corinthian audience. This creation occurs 10 Jonathan Edwards, Works of Jonathan Edwards Online, vol.2, Writings on the Trinity, Grace, and Faith, 1740, Ed. Paul Ramsey (Jonathan Edwards Center at Yale University 2008), 250. 11 Space does not allow us to give a treatment of Owen on this subject, for example. However, it would be a shame to include at least one of his meditations: “And where God shines into the heart, by that faith which is of divine operation—there, with ‘open face, we behold the glory of God, as in a glass;’ or have the knowledge of the glory of God in the face of Jesus Christ. There is not the meanest believer, but—in the real exercise of faith in Christ—hath more glorious apprehensions of God, his wisdom, goodness, and grace, of all his glorious excellencies, than the most learned and wise in the world can attain unto, in the exercise of reason on the proper objects of it.” John Owen, The Works of John Owen: Volume 1, William H. Goold, Editor (Edinburgh: The Banner of Truth Trust, 1967), 77. 12 George H. Guthrie writes, “This light, moreover, is ‘the personal comprehension of God’s glory.’ Here we read the genitive τῆς γνώσεως (tēs gnōseōs, the knowledge) as epexegetical, meaning ‘the light, which is the personal comprehension’; and the sense of ‘knowledge’ has relational overtones, rather than mere cognative assent to God’s existence… this ‘light, which is the personal comprehension of God’s glory,’ is found ‘in the face of Christ’ (ἐν προσώπῳ Χριστοῦ, en prosōpō Christou), whom Paul has proclaimed as ‘the image of God’ (4:4).” 2 Corinthians: Baker Exegetical Commentary on the New Testament (Grand Rapids: Baker Academic, 2015), 245-246.
Recommended publications
  • March 2019 RADICAL ORTHODOXYT Theology, Philosophy, Politics R P OP Radical Orthodoxy: Theology, Philosophy, Politics
    Volume 5, no. 1 | March 2019 RADICAL ORTHODOXYT Theology, Philosophy, Politics R P OP Radical Orthodoxy: Theology, Philosophy, Politics Editorial Board Oliva Blanchette Michael Symmons Roberts Conor Cunningham Phillip Blond Charles Taylor Andrew Davison Evandro Botto Rudi A. te Velde Alessandra Gerolin David B. Burrell, C.S.C. Graham Ward Michael Hanby David Fergusson Thomas Weinandy, OFM Cap. Samuel Kimbriel Lord Maurice Glasman Slavoj Žižek John Milbank Boris Gunjević Simon Oliver David Bentley Hart Editorial Team Adrian Pabst Stanley Hauerwas Editor: Catherine Pickstock Johannes Hoff Dritëro Demjaha Aaron Riches Austen Ivereigh Tracey Rowland Fergus Kerr, OP Managing Editor & Layout: Neil Turnbull Peter J. Leithart Eric Austin Lee Joost van Loon Advisory Board James Macmillan Reviews Editor: Talal Asad Mgsr. Javier Martínez Brendan Sammon William Bain Alison Milbank John Behr Michael S Northcott John R. Betz Nicholas Rengger Radical Orthodoxy: A Journal of Theology, Philosophy and Politics (ISSN: 2050-392X) is an internationally peer-reviewed journal dedicated to the exploration of academic and policy debates that interface between theology, philosophy and the social sciences. The editorial policy of the journal is radically non-partisan and the journal welcomes submissions from scholars and intellectuals with interesting and relevant things to say about both the nature and trajectory of the times in which we live. The journal intends to publish papers on all branches of philosophy, theology aesthetics (including literary, art and music criticism) as well as pieces on ethical, political, social, economic and cultural theory. The journal will be published four times a year; each volume comprising of standard, special, review and current affairs issues.
    [Show full text]
  • Actus and Potentia: from Philosophy of Nature to Metaphysics
    Actus and Potentia: From Philosophy of Nature to Metaphysics (Dedicated to Lawrence Dewan, OP and Reginald Garrigou-Lagrange, OP) Alfred J. Freddoso University of Notre Dame Thomistic Philosophy Workshop Mt. St. Mary College, Newburgh June, 2015 1. Introduction cum exhortation In this presentation I want to lay out the general parameters of the distinction between actus and potentia, and to indicate how the order of learning here takes us fairly directly from philosophy of nature to the heights of metaphysics — more particularly, to St. Thomas’s teaching on creation ex nihilo, both (a) in its positing of the distinction between esse and essentia in the creature that receives, as it were, the act of creating and (b) in its characterization of the agent of creation. This is just one example of the power of St. Thomas’s Aristotelian philosophy of nature. I hope that what I say here will help you to recognize indications within contemporary mainstream philosophy of the enduring importance of the distinction between actus and potentia, acknowledged or unacknowledged, not just for philosophy of nature and philosophy of science, but for philosophical anthropology (aka philosophy of mind), natural theology, and moral theory as well. Now our best approach to the distinction between potentia and actus is precisely to begin from the principles of change as Aristotle lays them out in Physics 1 and to link the various specifications of the distinction to distinctive exercises of efficient causality. Before I get to that, however, I want to insert a word of encouragement and exhortation to the budding Thomists out there.
    [Show full text]
  • Natural Theology and the Christian Contribution to Metaphysics: on Thomas Joseph White’S Wisdom in the Face of Modernity
    Nova et Vetera, English Edition, Vol. 10, No. 2 (2012): 539 –62 539 Natural Theology and the Christian Contribution to Metaphysics: On Thomas Joseph White’s Wisdom in the Face of Modernity NICHOLAS J. H EALY , J R. John Paul II Institute Washington, DC From the very heart of Christian faith and, at the same time, the heart of Greek thought now joined to faith, Manuel II was able to say: Not to act “with logos” is contrary to God’s nature. [T]he faith of the Church has always insisted that between God and us, between his eternal Creator Spirit and our created reason there exists a real analogy, in which unlike - ness remains infinitely greater than likeness, yet not to the point of abol - ishing analogy and its language (cf. Lateran IV). God does not become more divine when we push him away from us in a sheer, impenetrable voluntarism; rather, the truly divine God is the God who has revealed himself as logos and, as logos, has acted and continues to act lovingly on our behalf. This inner rapprochement between biblical faith and Greek philosophical inquiry was an event of decisive importance not only from the standpoint of the history of religions, but also from that of world history—it is an event which concerns us even today. 1 It is my view that the neoscholastic rationalism that was trying to reconstruct the praeambula fidei, the approach to faith, with pure rational certainty, by means of rational argument that was strictly inde - pendent of any faith, has failed; and it cannot be otherwise for any such attempts to do that kind of thing.
    [Show full text]
  • The Revival of Political Hesychasm in Greek Orthodox Thought: a Study of the Hesychast Basis of the Thought of John S
    ABSTRACT The Revival of Political Hesychasm in Greek Orthodox Thought: A Study of the Hesychast Basis of the Thought of John S. Romanides and Christos Yannaras Daniel Paul Payne, B.A., M.Div. Mentor: Derek H. Davis, Ph.D. In the 1940s Russian émigré theologians rediscovered the ascetic-theology of St. Gregory Palamas. Palamas’s theology became the basis for an articulation of an Orthodox theological identity apart from Roman Catholic and Protestant influences. In particular the “Neo-Patristic Synthesis” of Fr. Georges Florovsky and the appropriation of Palamas’s theology by Vladimir Lossky set the course for future Orthodox theology in the twentieth century. Their thought had a direct influence upon the thought of Greek theologians John S. Romanides and Christos Yannaras in the late twentieth century. Each of these theologians formulated a political theology using the ascetic-theology of Palamas combined with the Roman identity of the Greek Orthodox people. Both of these thinkers called for a return to the ecclesial-communal life of the late Byzantine period as an alternative to the secular vision of the modern West. The resulting paradigm developed by their thought has led to the formation of what has been called the “Neo- Orthodox Movement.” Essentially, what the intellectual and populist thinkers of the movement have expressed in their writings is “political hesychasm.” Romanides and Yannaras desire to establish an Orthodox identity that separates the Roman aspect from the Hellenic element of Greek identity. The Roman identity of the Greek people is the Orthodox Christian element removed from the pagan Hellenism, which, as they argue, the Western powers imposed on the Greek people in the establishment of the modern nation-state of Greece in 1821.
    [Show full text]
  • Maurice Blondel at the Intersection of Theology and Philosophy
    Edinburgh Research Explorer Adam C. English, The Possibility of Christian Philosophy: Maurice Blondel at the Intersection of Theology and Philosophy Citation for published version: Grumett, D 2011, 'Adam C. English, The Possibility of Christian Philosophy: Maurice Blondel at the Intersection of Theology and Philosophy', New Blackfriars, vol. 92, no. 1039, pp. 380-381. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1741-2005.2011.01435_4.x Digital Object Identifier (DOI): 10.1111/j.1741-2005.2011.01435_4.x Link: Link to publication record in Edinburgh Research Explorer Document Version: Peer reviewed version Published In: New Blackfriars Publisher Rights Statement: This is the peer reviewed version of the following article: GRUMETT, D. (2011), THE POSSIBILITY OF CHRISTIAN PHILOSOPHY: MAURICE BLONDEL AT THE INTERSECTION OF THEOLOGY AND PHILOSOPHY by Adam C. English. New Blackfriars, 92: 380-381, which has been published in final form at https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/full/10.1111/j.1741-2005.2011.01435_4.x. This article may be used for non- commercial purposes in accordance with Wiley Terms and Conditions for Self-Archiving. General rights Copyright for the publications made accessible via the Edinburgh Research Explorer is retained by the author(s) and / or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing these publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. Take down policy The University of Edinburgh has made every reasonable effort to ensure that Edinburgh Research Explorer content complies with UK legislation. If you believe that the public display of this file breaches copyright please contact [email protected] providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim.
    [Show full text]
  • “God's Acting Upon the World” – a Meta- Metaphysical Perspective
    2017 TheoLogica An International Journal for Philosophy of Religion and Philosophical Theology DOI: https://doi.org/10.14428/thl.v1i1.133 “God’s Acting upon the World” – A Meta- metaphysical Perspective CHRISTINA SCHNEIDER LMU Munich and Hochschule für Philosophie [email protected] Abstract: There may be good theological reasons for adopting one or the other of the two “God-world”-relations: “God’s acting upon the world” vs. “God’s not acting upon the world”, from a philosophical/metaphysical point of view, these options pose a “decision-problem”. The article is in search for metaphysical criteria that support any decision on behalf of “God’s acting vs. His not acting upon the world”. In this, it is meta-metaphysical in character. Keywords: classical theism, alternative theisms, acting, coherence, meta-meta- physics “How is it possible that God acts upon the world?” For Christians that are faithful to the biblical narratives, to God’s revelation, to their religious practices and traditions, the question presumably sounds pointless.1 As is well-known, the question has two different, inconsistent and extreme answers: One answer is: He cannot act. The other answer is: What else could He do? Both answers are not better than the embedding theoretical, better: metaphysical, frameworks. Inconsistent as the answers are, so are the embedding frameworks and by this their different notions of God: roughly, His being transcendent vs. His being immanent. This has as consequence that the answers are rooted in fundamentally different relations of God and “world”. Theories that conceive of God as being transcendent are called classical theisms here.
    [Show full text]
  • The Contribution of Fr. Georges Florovsky to the Rediscovery of the Orthodox Teaching on the Distinction Between the Divine Essence and Energies Tanev, Stoyan
    University of Southern Denmark Energeia vs Sophia The contribution of Fr. Georges Florovsky to the rediscovery of the Orthodox teaching on the distinction between the Divine essence and energies Tanev, Stoyan Published in: International Journal of Orthodox Theology Publication date: 2011 Document version: Final published version Citation for pulished version (APA): Tanev, S. (2011). Energeia vs Sophia: The contribution of Fr. Georges Florovsky to the rediscovery of the Orthodox teaching on the distinction between the Divine essence and energies. International Journal of Orthodox Theology, 2(1), 15-71. http://orthodox-theology.com/media/PDF/IJOT1-2011/05-tanev-energeia-1.pdf Go to publication entry in University of Southern Denmark's Research Portal Terms of use This work is brought to you by the University of Southern Denmark. Unless otherwise specified it has been shared according to the terms for self-archiving. If no other license is stated, these terms apply: • You may download this work for personal use only. • You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain • You may freely distribute the URL identifying this open access version If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details and we will investigate your claim. Please direct all enquiries to [email protected] Download date: 02. Oct. 2021 Stoyan Tanev ΕΝΕΡΓΕΙΑ vs ΣΟΦΙΑ The contribution of Fr. Georges Florovsky to the rediscovery of the Orthodox teaching on the distinction between the Divine essence and energies Abstract The objective of this essay is to discuss the re-emergence of the distinction between Divine essence and energies in Orthodox theology by focusing on the sophiological controversy in the first half of 20th century with a specific emphasis on the theology of Fr.
    [Show full text]
  • Charles Hartshorne and the Ontological Argument
    Aporia vol. 18 no. 1—2008 Charles Hartshorne and the Ontological Argument JOSHUA ERNST HE ontological argument distinguishes itself from the cosmological and teleological arguments for God’s existence because it is a priori, T while the cosmological and teleological arguments are a posteriori. One of the first to formulate the ontological argument was St. Anselm, the Archbishop of Canterbury, who lived in the late eleventh century. Anselm’s argument rests on the idea that God, by definition, is “that than which none greater can be conceived” and that this definition, when used in a proof created by Anselm, proves God’s existence. Another key point in Anselm’s argument is that if God exists, he must exist necessarily, symbolized “p ⊃ Np.” According to Anselm, who represents a classical understanding of God, it is impossible for God to exist contingently. Anselm’s argument has been criticized and critiqued by many philoso- phers, one of whom was Immanuel Kant. Kant felt that an ontological proof of the existence of God was impossible (Pojman 5). He called into ques- tion the use of being or existence as a predicate, which is used throughout the ontological argument. Kant argued that existence is not a great making property—knowing that something exists does not enhance the thing itself (Pojman 7). A century later, Charles Hartshorne revised the ontological argument and presented a different interpretation of God’s mode of exis- tence or of the way God can and needs to be perfect. Hartshorne argued that not only does his version of the argument withstand critiques such as Kant’s, it eliminates the fallacy he feels Anselm’s original argument creates: rather than prove God’s existence, Anselm’s argument proves the necessity of God’s non-existence.
    [Show full text]
  • Seeing God: Thomas Aquinas on Divine Presence in the World1 Gledati Boga: Tomaž Akvinski O Božji Navzočnosti V Svetu
    739 Druge razprave Pregledni znanstveni članek/Article (1.02) Bogoslovni vestnik/Theological Quarterly 79 (2019) 3,739—749 Besedilo prejeto/Received:07/2019; sprejeto/Accepted:11/2019 UDK/UDC: 27-14Thomas Aquinas DOI: https://doi.org/10.34291/BV2019/03/Roszak Piotr Roszak and Tomasz Huzarek Seeing God: Thomas Aquinas on Divine Presence in the World1 Gledati Boga: Tomaž Akvinski o Božji navzočnosti v svetu Abstract: How to recognize the presence of God in the world? Thomas Aquinas’ proposition, based on the efficient, exemplary and intentional causality, includ- ing both the natural level and grace, avoids several simplifications, the conse- quence of which is transcendent blindness. On the one hand, it does not allow to fall into a panentheistic reductionism involving God into the game of His variability in relation to the changing world. The sensitivity of Thomas in inter- preting a real existing world makes it impossible to close the subject in the ‘’house without windows’’, from where God can only be presumed. On the other hand, the proposal of Aquinas avoids the radical transcendence of God, according to which He has nothing to do with the world. Keywords: transcendence, Thomas Aquinas, First Cause, Panentheism, Post-theism Povzetek: Kako prepoznati Božjo navzočnost v svetu? Predpostavka Tomaža Akvin- skega, ki temelji na vzročnosti učinka, primera in namena ter vključuje tako raven narave kot milosti, se izogne vrsti poenostavitev, katerih posledica je sle- pota za transcendentno. Po eni strani Tomaževa predpostavka ne dovoljuje, da bi zapadli v panenteistično redukcijo, ki Boga potiska v igro njegove spremen- ljivosti v razmerju do spreminjajočega se sveta.
    [Show full text]
  • Toward the Worship of God As Actus Purus
    TMSJ 31/2 (Fall 2020) 213–230 TOWARD THE WORSHIP OF GOD AS ACTUS PURUS Alan Quiñones Ph.D. Candidate, The Master’s Seminary God is Actus Purus, which is to say that He is eternally all that He can be. Potentiality is a trait of creatures, not God. The concept of Actus Purus was first articulated by Aristotle in his argument for the unmoved mover, and through its history, the church has considered this notion a valid articulation of the absolute perfection and preeminence of God over all things. This paper, then, explores the exegetical footing of Actus Purus. It also will seek to understand its implications for systematic theology. Careful exegesis will demonstrate that the doctrine of pure actuality is deducible from Scripture by good and necessary consequence. It is an instrument that helps to sound the unbounded perfection of God and arrive at a more settled understanding of His meticulous sovereignty. In short, pure actuality conveys that life cannot but belong to God, because He decrees, wills, knows, and does everything entirely from Himself. * * * * * Introduction There is an unfathomable chasm between God and creation. The soul can therefore only rise toward God by first supporting itself on the created order, where the Divine perfections are stamped.1 Christian theology, on the other hand, faces a monumental challenge in seeking to articulate the fundamental perfection and primacy of God over His creatures. After all, He is the eternal and infinite Creator of a temporal and finite world. More than that, He is Being, from whom all existence is derived; Sustainer, through whom all things are upheld; and End, to whom all things are (Rom 11:36).
    [Show full text]
  • The Commedia's Metaphysics of Human Nature: Essays on Charity
    The Commedia’s Metaphysics of Human Nature: Essays on Charity, Free Will and Ensoulment Humberto Ballesteros Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of Arts and Sciences COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY 2015 © 2015 Humberto Ballesteros All rights reserved Abstract The Commedia’s Metaphysics of Human Nature: Essays on Charity, Free Will and Ensoulment Humberto Ballesteros This dissertation aims to show that the Commedia develops an original and coherent philosophy of human nature. Deploying the methodologies of two separate disciplines, the history of philosophy and literary criticism, it places the poem’s ideas in the intellectual context in which they developed, and analyzes the learnedness, freshness and validity of its conclusions. The topic is divided in three themes, discussed in the same number of chapters: 1) Love and desire. After following Arendt in tracing a tension in Augustine’s works between the theological primordiality of dilectio Dei and the biblically endorsed importance of love for one’s neighbor, I argue that the Commedia develops a concept of social charity that seeks to reconcile that seminal Christian paradox. 2) Free will. Based on a study of the theory of free will advanced by Purgatorio and Paradiso, I advance the idea that Dante’s metaphysics and psychology of human freedom, particularly in regards to his description of the workings of absolute and relative will, contrast in a fundamental way with Aquinas’ in the Appendix of the Summa theologica; and based on that conclusion, and on an analysis of the example of Piccarda Donati, it is possible to conclude that the Commedia not only postulates a hierarchy of volitions as a necessary condition for human freedom, but also defines free will as the ability to formulate a self-forming action.
    [Show full text]
  • Responses to Medieval Nominalism in John Wyclifs
    TRUTH, TIME AND SACRED TEXT: RESPONSES TO MEDIEVAL NOMINALISM IN JOHN WYCLIFS SUMMA DE ENTE AND DE VERITATE SACRAE SCRIPTURAE STEPHEN PENN DPHIL THE UNPVERSITY OF YORK DEPARTMENT OF ENGLISH AND RELATED LITERATURE SEPTEMBER 1998 TABLE OF CONTENTS page Acknowledgments v Abstract vi List of Abbreviations viii Note on Translations ix INTRODUCTION 1 CHAPTER I Nominalism, Realism and Hermeneutics 7 1. 'Textual' Theory, Hermeneutics and the Forms 7 of Theoretical Discourse 2. Nominalism and Realism: Contexts and Definitions 13 2.1. Nominalism in Early Scholastic Philosophy: 15 Vocales and Nonzinales 2.2. Nominalism in Wyclif's Oxford 18 3. Anti-Nominalism and Anti-Modemism in 26 Wyclif's Hermeneutic Writings CHAPTER 2 Philosophy and Scriptural Interpretation 1: Analogy 32 I The Concept of Analogy: Wyclif, Aquinas and the 33 Realist Tradition 2. Analogy and Trinitarian Doctrine: The Argument 45 of the De Trinitale 3. 'Proper' and Metaphorical Analogy 50 4. Sed Contra Mud Sic: Nominalist Objections 57 to Analogical Interpretation 5. From the Book of Nature to the Book of Life: 61 Six Kinds of Knowledge ii CHAPTER 3 Philosophy and Scriptural Interpretation 2: 67 The Truth of Propositions 1. Modes of Predication and the Logic of Holy Scripture 67 2. Time and Temporal Propositions 85 2.1 Time as Accident: The Argument of 86 De Ente Praedicantentali 2.2 The Reality of Time Beyond the 91 Present Instant 2.3 Teinpits and Ditratio: Wyclif's Distinction between 96 Finite and Infinite 2.4 Antpliatio Temporis and the Study of Scripture 99 CHAPTER 4 Contemporary Criticism of Wyclif's Scriptural Logic: 103 John Kenningham, OC I Kenningharn as Anti-Realist 104 2.
    [Show full text]