The Two Indexical Uses Theory of Proper Names and Frege's Puzzle

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Two Indexical Uses Theory of Proper Names and Frege's Puzzle City University of New York (CUNY) CUNY Academic Works Graduate Student Publications and Research CUNY Academic Works 2015 The Two Indexical Uses Theory of Proper Names and Frege's Puzzle Daniel S. Shabasson CUNY Graduate Center How does access to this work benefit ou?y Let us know! More information about this work at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu/gc_studentpubs/18 Discover additional works at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu This work is made publicly available by the City University of New York (CUNY). Contact: [email protected] THE TWO INDEXICAL USES THEORY OF PROPER NAMES AND FREGE’S PUZZLE Daniel Shabasson [email protected] [email protected] ABSTRACT: To solve Frege’s puzzle, I develop a novel theory of proper names, the “Two Indexical Uses Theory” of proper names (the “TIUT”), according to which proper names are used as indexicals. I distinguish two types of indexical uses: (1) ‘Millian’ uses on which a proper name merely refers (contributing its referent alone to the proposition expressed); and (2) ‘Conception-indicating’ uses on which a proper name both refers and conveys the speaker’s “conception of” or “way of taking” the referent at the moment s/he utters the name (contributing both referent and conception to the proposition expressed). Unlike Millianism, the TIUT is consistent with speaker intuitions about cognitive value vis-à-vis Frege’s puzzle about identity sentences and is consistent with speaker intuitions about truth-value vis-à-vis Frege’s puzzle about propositional attitude ascriptions. Unlike Descriptivism, the TIUT is not vulnerable to Kripke’s modal, epistemic, or semantic arguments because on the TIUT proper names are always used as rigid designators and lack descriptive meanings—instead possessing character (the sort of meaning borne by indexicals). Among theories of proper names, the TIUT is uniquely able to explain how co-referential name pairs such as ‘Clark Kent’/‘Superman’ can simultaneously have the following three properties: (a) rigidity, (b) lack of descriptive meaning, and (c) difference in semantic content. The TIUT explains the difference in cognitive value between identity sentences such as ‘Clark Kent is Clark Kent’ and ‘Clark Kent is Superman’ by demonstrating that they may be used to semantically express different propositions with identical modal profiles (unlike Descriptivism, according to which they would have different modal profiles). The TIUT explains the difference in truth-value intuited by ordinary speakers between propositional attitude ascriptions such as ‘Lois Lane believes that Clark Kent flies’ and ‘Lois Lane believes that Superman flies’ by demonstrating that they may be used to semantically express different propositions genuinely differing in truth-value, the former false and the latter true. The TIUT also solves Kripke’s puzzle by explaining how a rational and reflective agent might simultaneously believe P and ⌐P and why one may accurately and without inconsistency ascribe the belief both that P and that ⌐P to that agent. Hence, we may accurately and without inconsistency report Peter as both believing that Paderewski had musical talent and believing that he did not. KEYWORDS: Frege’s puzzle, proper names, indexicals, cognitive value, Millianism, Descriptivism, Kripke’s puzzle ©2015 DANIEL SHABASSON All Rights Reserved TABLE OF CONTENTS INTRODUCTION………………………………………………………………………... ii 1 THE PUZZLES TO BE SOLVED 1.1 Frege’s Puzzle(s)……………………………………………….................………... 1 1.2 The Problem of Rational Inconsistent Belief………………….…………………… 12 2 THE TWO INDEXICAL USES THEORY OF PROPER NAMES AND ITS SOLUTION TO THE PUZZLES 2.1 The Two Uses of Proper Names………………………………………………….... 16 2.2 Definitions: “Dossier Tokens,” “Dossier Types,” “Subjects” …………………...... 24 2.3 Names Used in a ‘Millian’ Way…………………………………………………… 32 2.4 Names Used in a ‘Conception-Indicating’ Way…………………………………… 33 2.5 Names are Rigid Designators on the TIUT……………………................................ 37 2.6 Solution to Frege’s Puzzle about Informative Identity Sentences…………………. 38 2.7 Solution to Frege’s Puzzle about Propositional Attitude Ascriptions……………... 41 2.7.1 Conception-Indicating Ascriptions…............................................................ 42 2.7.2 Millian Ascriptions………………………………………………………… 47 2.8 Solution to the Problem of Rational Inconsistent Belief…………….…………...... 53 2.9 Informative Identities Without Substitution………………………………………... 57 2.10 Informative Identities: A Priori or A Posteriori Propositions?.................................. 62 2.11 Ascribing Belief to Non-Verbal Agents…………………………………………… 74 2.12 Solution to Kripke’s Puzzle……………………………………………................... 77 2.13 Conclusion…………………………………………………………………………. 86 REFERENCES………………………………………………………………………………......... 92 i INTRODUCTION The theory of proper names presented here, the Two Indexical Uses Theory of proper names or “TIUT,” is, to my knowledge, sui generis. The central claim is that proper names are used as indexicals. I distinguish two types of indexical uses: (1) ‘Millian’ uses on which a name merely refers (contributing its bearer/referent alone to the proposition expressed); and (2) ‘Conception-indicating’ uses on which a name both refers and conveys the speaker’s “conception of” or “way of taking” the bearer/referent at the moment s/he utters the name (contributing both referent and conception to the proposition expressed). The TIUT is designed specifically to solve Frege’s puzzle, as well as other semantic puzzles such as the puzzle I call the ‘Problem of Rational Inconsistent Belief’ (see section 1.2, infra) and a related puzzle, Kripke’s Paderewski puzzle. I aim to show that the TIUT is the best theory of proper names because it offers the most comprehensive solution to this set of puzzles. It avoids the problems bedeviling other theories of proper names that pretend to solve the puzzles. On the one hand, we have Descriptivism, which was largely refuted by Saul Kripke in Naming and Necessity. Kripke famously argued that Descriptivism was defective because, inter alia, it held proper names to have descriptive meanings and to be non-rigid designators. The TIUT, in full agreement with Kripke and the current philosophical consensus, maintains that proper names are devoid of descriptive meaning (as indexicals, their meaning is their character) and are always rigid designators. On the other hand, we have Millianism, which makes numerous highly counterintuitive claims. For example, Millians dubiously maintain that the true sentence ‘Lois Lane believes that Clark Kent is Clark Kent’ semantically expresses the same proposition as the sentence ‘Lois Lane believes that Clark Kent is Superman,’ and therefore, according to Millians, Lois Lane does in fact believe that Clark Kent is Superman. Millians ii also implausibly claim that the sentences ‘Clark Kent is Clark Kent’ and ‘Clark Kent is Superman’ semantically express the same proposition—the trivial proposition that a particular individual is identical to himself. The TIUT avoids the absurd implications of Millianism, and, consistent with common sense, maintains that these sentences semantically express different propositions. The TIUT answers the central question posed by Frege’s puzzle: how can co-referential proper names such as ‘Clark Kent’ and ‘Superman’ simultaneously be all of the following: (a) rigid, (b) lacking descriptive meaning, and (c) different in semantic content? Unlike some other anti-Millian theories of proper names, the TIUT recognizes that Millianism gets a lot right, even if it cannot be a fully correct theory of proper names because it cannot solve the puzzles. Most of the time proper names are used just as Millians say—just to refer to their bearers and nothing else. This is so in the case of names occurring in ordinary simple sentences, identity sentences, and within the ‘that’-clauses of propositional attitude ascriptions. A good theory of proper names must take into account the plausibility of the Millian picture vis-à-vis the majority of uses of proper names. However, the failure of Millians to offer plausible solutions to Frege’s puzzle and other semantic puzzles militates in favor of the judgment that proper names must be used in non-Millian ways in some cases. The proper conclusion to draw is that names can be used in at least two ways—a Millian way, where a name just refers to its bearer, and a non-Millian way where the speaker uses a name to refer to its bearer and also to indicate a conception of or way of taking that bearer. In short, I am proposing that names are semantically ambiguous between these two kinds of uses: a ‘Millian’ use and a ‘Conception-indicating’ use. I am positing a semantic distinction and not a pragmatic one. Some philosophers will object that I am going too far in positing a semantic distinction—perhaps agreeing with my claim that proper names, as well as many classes of expressions, can be used in various ways, but objecting that not all iii differences in use mark a semantic distinction. However, I do really do want to posit a semantic distinction. For there is, as far as I can see, no pragmatic mechanism—neither implicature, descriptive enrichment, nor any other pragmatic mechanism—that could explain the fundamentally different ways in which proper names are regularly and consistently used. Unfortunately, there is a dogma in the current philosophy of language according to which the positing of a semantic distinction is viewed as something close to a mortal sin. Wherever possible, according to this dogma,
Recommended publications
  • AKA Clark Kent) Middle Name Is Joseph
    Superman’s (AKA Clark Kent) Middle Name Is Joseph. What’s that?! There in the sky? Is it a bird? Is it a plane? No! It’s the Man of Tomorrow! Superman has gone by many names over the years, but one thing has remained the same. He has always stood for what’s best about humanity, all of our potential for terrible destructive acts, but also our choice to not act on the level of destruction we could wreak. Superman was first created in 1933 by Joe Shuster and Jerry Siegel, the writer and artist respectively. His first appearance was in Action Comics #1, and that was the beginning of a long and illustrious career for the Man of Steel. In his unmistakable blue suit with red cape, and the stylized red S on his chest, the figure of Superman has become one of the most recognizable in the world. The original Superman character was a bald telepathic villain that was focused on world domination. It was like a mix of Lex Luthor and Professor X. Superman’s powers include incredible strength, the ability to fly. X-ray vision, super speed, invulnerability to most attacks, super hearing, and super breath. He is nearly unstoppable. However, Superman does have one weakness, Kryptonite. When exposed to this radioactive element from his home planet, he becomes weak and helpless. Superman’s alter ego is mild-mannered reporter Clark Kent. He lives in the city of Metropolis and works for the newspaper the Daily Planet. Clark is in love with fellow reporter Lois Lane.
    [Show full text]
  • Lois Lane Would Identify Clark Kent As Superman by His Body Language 1 November 2016
    Lois Lane would identify Clark Kent as Superman by his body language 1 November 2016 understand that we're using information other than faces so we can get an insight into how we achieve this unique skill. "Our results show that we are able to use body motion when other cues are ambiguous or unavailable—so we basically assume that we can use body motion as a reliable cue to identity when other information is less available or reliable such as when a person is far away or when they're in bad lighting conditions. "I've always questioned why Lois Lane doesn't recognise Clark Kent or why Bruce Wayne has never been identified as Batman—now we know that they should be recognised based on their body motion!" Credit: University of Aberdeen More information: Karin S. Pilz et al. Idiosyncratic body motion influences person recognition, Visual Cognition (2016). DOI: Researchers from the University of Aberdeen have 10.1080/13506285.2016.1232327 found evidence that suggests that superheroes would be identifiable as their alter-ego personalities due to their unique body movements. Provided by University of Aberdeen The study published in the journal Visual Cognition, investigated how we are able to identify our peers, and found that when facial information is not available we can use body motion instead. The study was the first of its kind to use life-like avatars to get to the bottom of how we are so good at recognising each other. Dr Karin Pilz, from the School of Psychology at the University of Aberdeen said: "The current perception is that identity recognition is usually done on faces alone but obviously body motion is also important because we usually see people as whole bodies! "Even in difficult conditions, we are really good at person recognition and so, I think it's important to 1 / 2 APA citation: Lois Lane would identify Clark Kent as Superman by his body language (2016, November 1) retrieved 24 September 2021 from https://medicalxpress.com/news/2016-11-lois-lane-clark-kent- superman.html This document is subject to copyright.
    [Show full text]
  • Superman Ebook, Epub
    SUPERMAN PDF, EPUB, EBOOK Jerry Siegel | 144 pages | 30 Jun 2009 | DC Comics | 9781401222581 | English | New York, NY, United States Superman PDF Book The next event occurs when Superman travels to Mars to help a group of astronauts battle Metalek, an alien machine bent on recreating its home world. He was voiced in all the incarnations of the Super Friends by Danny Dark. He is happily married with kids and good relations with everyone but his father, Jor-EL. American photographer Richard Avedon was best known for his work in the fashion world and for his minimalist, large-scale character-revealing portraits. As an adult, he moves to the bustling City of Tomorrow, Metropolis, becoming a field reporter for the Daily Planet newspaper, and donning the identity of Superman. Superwoman Earth 11 Justice Guild. James Denton All-Star Superman Superman then became accepted as a hero in both Metropolis and the world over. Raised by kindly farmers Jonathan and Martha Kent, young Clark discovers the source of his superhuman powers and moves to Metropolis to fight evil. Superman Earth -1 The Devastator. The next few days are not easy for Clark, as he is fired from the Daily Planet by an angry Perry, who felt betrayed that Clark kept such an important secret from him. Golden Age Superman is designated as an Earth-2 inhabitant. You must be a registered user to use the IMDb rating plugin. Filming on the series began in the fall. He tells Atom he is welcome to stay while Atom searches for the people he loves.
    [Show full text]
  • Kripke's Naming and Necessity: Lecture II
    Kripke’s Naming and Necessity: Lecture II PHIL 83104 October 12, 2011 1. Varieties of descriptivism (end of Lecture I) ....................................................................1 2. Kripke’s arguments against descriptivism (71-90) ...........................................................2 2.1. The modal argument (48-49, 71-77) 2.1.1. Rigidified descriptions 2.1.2. Wide-scoping descriptions 2.2. The semantic argument (78-85) 2.3. The epistemic argument (86-87) 3. Kripke’s alternative picture of reference (91-97) ..............................................................5 4. Identity sentences and the necessary a posteriori (97-105) ..............................................7 4.1. The necessity of identity 4.2. A prioricity and qualitatively identical situations 4.3. Some sources of skepticism about Kripke’s claim 4.3.1. Contingent identities? 4.3.2. The illusion of contingency 4.3.3. Millianism about names 1. VARIETIES OF DESCRIPTIVISM (END OF LECTURE I) We’ve already seen two distinctions Kripke makes between different versions of descriptivism: • The distinction between descriptivist views which let a single description do the work, and those which rely on a cluster of descriptions • The distinctiopn between views according to which a description gives the meaning of a name, and those according to which it merely fixes the reference of the name Here Kripke introduces a third distinction: between circular and non-circular descriptivist views. This distinction is not like the others; it is less a distinction between varieties of descriptivism than a constraint on descriptivist views. What exactly is this constraint? Suppose we identified the meaning of the name “Aristotle” with the meaning of the description “the person called ‘Aristotle’” or “the referent of ‘Aristotle.’” These would be examples of descriptivist views which fail to meet the non-circularity condition, since to determine what object satisfies the description, we must first know which object is the referent of the name in question.
    [Show full text]
  • PROPER NAMES: ONE CENTURY of DISCUSSION Uxía RIVAS
    Logica Trianguli, 3, 1999, 119-138 PROPER NAMES: ONE CENTURY OF DISCUSSION Uxía RIVAS MONROY Abstract The main objective of this paper is to offer an overview of some of the most relevant and at the same time controversial aspects of proper names over this last century. Therefore, the intention is not to go deeply into all the issues re- lated to proper names, though special attention will be paid to one of them for its importance, namely, the discussion as to whether proper names have sense or meaning associated to them or whether they are directly referential expressions. In the same way, only a few of all the authors who have made theories, comments or analyses about proper names will be mentioned in this article. The subject of proper names is complex enough in spite of its apparent simplicity, so as to leave many lines of analysis open, which are not deeply dealt with in this pres- entation. 1. Introduction Proper names form part of the most general category of singular terms, that is, of expressions characterised for referring or denoting only one object or individual; therefore, and taking this consideration into account, definite descriptions and the wide range of indexicals will also be singular terms. Following Strawson’s terminology we could say that singular terms, and in particular proper names, are the types of expressions generally used to make singularizing references, i.e. they are the expressions which tend to have a “uniquely referring use”. What we generally have in mind as speakers of a language when talking about proper names is the most paradigmatic examples of them, such as Galicia, Paris, Socrates, Atenea, Ulises, Mary, John; however, we may also consider “The Holy Roman Empire”, “The United States of America”, “The Hercules Tower”, “The Second World War” as proper names; and surely we would not consider “The dean of the Faculty of Philosophy”, “The present king of France”, “The director of the gen- eral library of Santiago” as proper names.
    [Show full text]
  • A Defense of Denotative Theory from Kripke's Criticism
    Tomoya Imaizumi 57 A Defense of Denotative Theory from Kripke’s Criticism Tomoya Imaizumi n Naming and Necessity, Kripke criticizes the denotative theory of reference and proposes a version of the causal theory of ref- erence. The outline of the discussion between these two theo- I ries is the following: the denotative theory is advocated by Rus- sell, who thinks that the reference of a name is determined by the definite description the name gives. Kripke, however, opposes this idea; he thinks that names can designate objects without description, and proposes his version of the causal theory. In this paper, I attempt to examine the criticism given by Kripke and defend the denotative theory from it. I then challenge the causal theory. Finally, I will show the ad- vantages and disadvantages of the denotative theory and the causal theory, along with a comparison between the two. To achieve this goal, it is first necessary to explain the denotative theory, the foundation of which is the notion of definite descriptions, before moving to an expla- nation of Kripke's version of the causal theory, the foundation of which is the notion of rigid designators. I. Description Theory and Denotative Theory In this section, I will explain what the description theory is, Tomoya Imaizumi is a senior studying philosophy at Kyoto University in Japan. His philosophical interests lie in philosophy of mathematics, philosophical logic and philosophy of physics. He is particularly inter- ested in Dummettian generalization from intuitionism to anti-realism, on which he is writing his senior thesis. He would like to continue studying philosophy at a graduate school in the U.S.
    [Show full text]
  • Thinking About Journalism with Superman 132
    Thinking about Journalism with Superman 132 Thinking about Journalism with Superman Matthew C. Ehrlich Professor Department of Journalism University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign Urbana, IL [email protected] Superman is an icon of American popular culture—variously described as being “better known than the president of the United States [and] more familiar to school children than Abraham Lincoln,” a “triumphant mixture of marketing and imagination, familiar all around the world and re-created for generation after generation,” an “ideal, a hope and a dream, the fantasy of millions,” and a symbol of “our universal longing for perfection, for wisdom and power used in service of the human race.”1 As such, the character offers “clues to hopes and tensions within the current American consciousness,” including the “tensions between our mythic values and the requirements of a democratic society.”2 This paper uses Superman as a way of thinking about journalism, following the tradition of cultural and critical studies that uses media artifacts as tools “to size up the shape, character, and direction of society itself.”3 Superman’s alter ego Clark Kent is of course a reporter for a daily newspaper (and at times for TV news as well), and many of his closest friends and colleagues are also journalists. However, although many scholars have analyzed the Superman mythology, not so many have systematically analyzed what it might say about the real-world press. The paper draws upon Superman’s multiple incarnations over the years in comics, radio, movies, and television in the context of past research and criticism regarding the popular culture phenomenon.
    [Show full text]
  • 4. the Superman/Kent Hypothesis: on the Epistemological Limit Between Human and Superhuman
    Page no.57 4. The Superman/Kent hypothesis: On the epistemological limit between human and superhuman. Alexandros Schismenos PhD Scholar Philosophy of Science University of Ioannina Greece ORCID iD: http://orcid.org/0000-0001-8490-4223 E-Mail: [email protected] Abstract Everybody knows that Superman is Clark Kent. Nobody knows that Superman is Clark Kent. Located between these two absolute statements is the epistemological limit that separates the superhero fictitious universe from our universe of causal reality. The superheroic double identity is a secret shared by the superhero and the reader of the comic or the viewer of the movie, and quite often the superhero winks at the outside world, thus breaking the 4th wall and establishing this collusive relationship. However, in our hypothesis, we are interested in Superman not as a fictitious archetype, but rather as a fictitious metaphor. We are not interested in his double identity as the matrix of superheroic attributes and narratives, but rather as the differential limit between superhuman and human within the fictional universe. Because, the reader or the viewer may share the secret identity with Superman and also with Spiderman or Batman or any other superhuman, but the secret equivalence of Superman and Clark Kent contains another hidden antithesis. Keywords Epistemology; Superman; Nostalgia; Ubermensch; Cognition Vol 3 No 1 (2015) ISSUE – March ISSN 2347-6869 (E) & ISSN 2347-2146 (P) The Superman/Kent hypothesis by Alexandros Schismenos Page No. 57-65 Page no.58 The Superman/Kent hypothesis: On the epistemological limit between human and superhuman Everybody knows that Superman is Clark Kent.
    [Show full text]
  • Knowledge Organization: an Epistemological Perspective
    Knowl. Org. 31(2004)No.1 49 Ch. Zins: Knowledge Organization: An Epistemological Perspective Knowledge Organization: An Epistemological Perspective Chaim Zins Department of Information ScienceHuman Services, Bar-Ilan University of Haifa Email: [email protected]. Dr. Chaim Zins is an information scientist, at the Department of Information Science, Bar-Ilan Uni- versity. He is a former member at the Department of Human Services, University of Haifa. Dr. Zins' current research is focused on knowledge organization, foundations of information science, knowl- edge management, information and referral services, and information retrieval. Zins, Chaim. (2004). Knowledge Organization: An Epistemological Perspective. Knowledge Or- ganization, 31(1). 49-54. 11 refs. ABSTRACT: This philosophical essay explores the epistemological foundations of knowledge organization and discusses im- plications for classification research. The study defines the concept of “knowledge,” distinguishes between subjective knowl- edge (i.e., knowledge as a thought in the individual’s mind) and objective knowledge (i.e., knowledge as an independent ob- ject), establishes the necessity of knowledge organization in the construction of knowledge and its key role in the creation, learning, and dissemination of knowledge, and concludes with implications for the development of classification schemes and knowledge maps. Overview second stage, I will discuss the relationship between subjective knowledge and objective knowledge. (No- Scholars and practitioners in the field of knowledge te that “subjective knowledge” is equivalent here to organization rarely stop to reflect and ponder upon the knowledge of the subject or the individual kno- the philosophical foundations of their field of exper- wer, and “objective knowledge” is equivalent here to tise.
    [Show full text]
  • What Superman Teaches Us About the American Dream and Changing Values Within the United States
    TRUTH, JUSTICE, AND THE AMERICAN WAY: WHAT SUPERMAN TEACHES US ABOUT THE AMERICAN DREAM AND CHANGING VALUES WITHIN THE UNITED STATES Lauren N. Karp AN ABSTRACT OF THE THESIS OF Lauren N. Karp for the degree of Master of Arts in English presented on June 4, 2009 . Title: Truth, Justice, and the American Way: What Superman Teaches Us about the American Dream and Changing Values within the United States Abstract approved: ____________________________________________________________________ Evan Gottlieb This thesis is a study of the changes in the cultural definition of the American Dream. I have chosen to use Superman comics, from 1938 to the present day, as litmus tests for how we have societally interpreted our ideas of “success” and the “American Way.” This work is primarily a study in culture and social changes, using close reading of comic books to supply evidence. I argue that we can find three distinct periods where the definition of the American Dream has changed significantly—and the identity of Superman with it. I also hypothesize that we are entering an era with an entirely new definition of the American Dream, and thus Superman must similarly change to meet this new definition. Truth, Justice, and the American Way: What Superman Teaches Us about the American Dream and Changing Values within the United States by Lauren N. Karp A THESIS submitted to Oregon State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts Presented June 4, 2009 Commencement June 2010 Master of Arts thesis of Lauren N. Karp presented on June 4, 2009 APPROVED: ____________________________________________________________________ Major Professor, representing English ____________________________________________________________________ Chair of the Department of English ____________________________________________________________________ Dean of the Graduate School I understand that my thesis will become part of the permanent collection of Oregon State University libraries.
    [Show full text]
  • Is Epistemology Tainted?1
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Universidade de Lisboa: Repositório.UL Disputatio Lecturer 2015 Is Epistemology Tainted?1 Jason Stanley Yale University BIBLID [0873-626X (2016) 42; pp. 1-35] Abstract Epistemic relativism comes in many forms, which have been much discussed in the last decade or so in analytic epistemology. My goal is to defend a version of epistemic relativism that sources the relativ- ity in the metaphysics of epistemic properties and relations, most sa- liently knowledge. I contrast it with other relativist theses. I argue that the sort of metaphysical relativism about knowledge I favor does not threaten the objectivity of the epistemological domain. Keywords Knowledge, vagueness, relativism. In Stanley 2005 (henceforth KPI), I defend the view that knowledge is interest-relative. I also there defend the view that all important epistemic properties and relations are interest-relative. I was and am sympathetic to knowledge first epistemology. The interest-relativity of the epistemic domain is inherited from the dependence of all im- portant epistemic properties and relations on knowledge. This is the distinctive version of epistemic relativism I endorse. The view I defend is explicitly relativist. Relativist views are widely considered to be problematic. It is therefore important for me to distinguish it from relativist views that I also reject. Chapter 7 of KPI distinguishes my view favorably from truth-relativism about knowledge, as defended in John MacFarlane’s work. Chapter 8 of KPI distinguishes my view favorably from Delia Graff Fara’s thor- oughgoing interest-relativity about empirical properties, which un- derlies her theory of vagueness.
    [Show full text]
  • Superman: Darkseid Rising
    Superman: Darkseid Rising Based on "Superman" created by Jerry Siegel and Joe Schuster and characters appearing in DC Comics Screenplay by Derek Anderson Derek Anderson (949)933-6999 [email protected] SUPERMAN: DARKSEID RISING Story by Larry Gomez and Derek Anderson Screenplay by Derek Anderson EXT. KENT FARM - NIGHT We pan over the Kent Farm, closing in on a barn. A soft BLUE GLOW emanates from within. INT. KENT BARN - NIGHT Inside the barn, underneath the FLOORBOARDS, the glow FLASHES BRIGHTLY. A ROBOTIC VOICE is heard speaking in an unknown language. FLASHBACK INT. KRYPTON - JOR-EL'S LAB - NIGHT KAL-EL'S POV BABY KAL-EL sits in a makeshift ROCKET, somewhat crude, but sturdy. JOR-EL is talking to Kal-El, but we cannot understand him. He is speaking in Kryptonian. The building shakes, CRYSTALLINE STRUCTURES collapse around. Jor-El walks away from us, holding his wife's hand as they move to a CONTROL PANEL. Behind Jor-El, a ROBOT with blue eyes, standing as tall as a man, enters the launching bay of Jor-El's lab. A robotic voice speaks. Baby Kal-El reaches out for the robot as it walks close to Jor-El's rocket. It transforms into a SMALL SIZED ROCKET with a BLUE EGG-SHAPED NOSE CONE. EXT. OUTER SPACE The rocket ship fires away from Krypton as it EXPLODES into shards of DUST and CRYSTAL. INT. ROCKET SHIP Kal-El sleeps as the rocket increases to hyper speed. Within the craft, a soft BLUE LIGHT grows brighter, illuminating Kal-el.
    [Show full text]