The Problem of the Socratic Elenchus" Jyl Gentzler

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Problem of the Socratic Elenchus Colloquium 7 Recollection and "The Problem of the Socratic Elenchus" Jyl Gentzler I. The Positive and Negative "Arms of Philosophy" Ever since Socrates' began his mission to cross-examine those with a reputation for wisdom, it has been a matter of dispute just what he was trying to accomplish. This is not because Socrates is reluctant to explain, but rather because the explana- tion that he offers seems so implausible. He says that he ques- tions others in order to test their claim to knowledge,2 to per- suade them to be as virtuous as possible,3 to determine whether a particular proposition is true,4 to inquire into the way things are 5 and to gain knowledge. 6 In addition, he claims to be fight- ing for justice (Ap. 32a). He should be rewarded for his efforts because, as a result of them, he has been making his fellow Athenians happy: "[The Olympian victor] makes you think that you are happy; I make you so" (Ap. 36d9-el). Not only do some of these goals seem overly ambitious for someone who merely cross-examines others, but in addition, they seem to be uncon- nected. 1. Throughout this paper, I will use "Socrates" to refer to the character Socrates in Plato's dialogues. 2. See Ap. 21c; Eu. 4e, 9b; Ch. 166c-d; L. 189e-190c; G. 472c-d. 3. Ap. 30b, e, 31b, 36c; Cr. 48e; L. 181d; Pr. 352e; G. 493c-d, 494a; Eud. 278d. 4. Eu. 6d, 7a, 9a; Ch. 161c, 162e, 166d, 175d; L. 194a-b; Lys. 212a-b; HMi. 369d; 360e-361a; Pr. 384a,G. 458a, 464a, 467b, 473e, 487e, 495a. 5. L. 194a; Ch. 165b, e, 175b, d, e, 176a; G. 457d, 506a. 6. Eu. 9a; G. 453b. However, on Socrates' view, these goals are closely related. Ultimately, I suggest, Socrates represents himself as attempting to make himself and others as happy as possible. For, on Socrates' view, virtue is necessary and sufficient for happiness;7 and moral knowledge8 is necessary and sufficient for virtue.9 So, to make himself and his interlocutors happy, he must insure that they have acquired the moral knowledge that is necessary and sufficient for virtue. Socrates believes that he lacks moral expertise, but many of his interlocutors believe that they possess it. If they do, then, by being cross-examined by Socrates, they can teach him what they know, and thus help him to move clos- er to virtue and happiness (Eu. 9a). If they do not possess moral expertise, then, through Socratic cross-examination, they can be disabused of their false self-conception. Only if they are con- vinced that they lack moral knowledge, can they be persuaded to pursue it. But sometimes even an awareness of their igno- rance is not enough. Some of Socrates' interlocutors are not yet convinced of the importance of moral knowledge or of virtue, and in these cases it is necessary for Socrates to exercise a little persuasion. Socrates claims that his method of cross-examina- tion serves this function, too. Once Socrates' interlocutors are inspired to pursue the moral knowledge necessary and suffi- cient for virtue, they are ready to inquire into the nature of virtue. By pursuing true beliefs and knowledge through cross- examination, Socrates seems to indicate that he believes that cross-examination is also the method of choice for moral inquiry. Socrates' remarks about the function of cross-examination thus fit together into a neat package: through cross-examination, Socrates claims to move his interlocutor from a false conceit of moral knowledge to the genuine possession of such knowledge. However, in most of the early dialogues, Socrates and his inter- 7. Ap. 30b; Cr. 47c-e; Ch. 156a-157b; G. 470e, 472eff. 8. Socrates often speaks of the virtue of wisdom when he has moral knowledge primarily in mind. I will generally use the phrase "moral knowledge", since it is more precise. 9. Ap. 29d-30a; L. 192c-194d; Ch. 174b-176a; Pr. 349e-360e. For some discussion of Socrates' commitment to this view, see Irwin 1977, 71-3, 86-91. locutors conclude by expressing bewilderment and confusion instead of confidence about the positive results of their inquiry. It might seem, then, that there is a tension between Socrates' stated goal of acquiring knowledge and his actual result. Since it is hard to believe that Plato represents Socrates as naively attempting to achieve a goal by means of a method that is com- pletely inadequate to the task, we might be tempted to attribute to Socratic cross-examination a less exalted function. According to Grote, Socrates' procedure of questioning others is merely "the negative arm of philosophy."10 By this, he meant that while Socratic questioning is capable of providing the valuable service of "testing, exercising, [and] refuting" various interlocutors' beliefs, it is incapable of "finding or providing" justified beliefs to put in their place. Instead, according to Grote, "a state of non-belief, or painful consciousness of ignorance" is substituted in the place of a false conceit of knowledge.ll What, then, should we make of Socrates' claims to be inquir- ing ? Those sympathetic to Grote's assessment of the function of the Socratic method suggest two sorts of answers. Richard Robinson argues that we should understand Socrates' character- ization of the purpose of his cross-examinations as a classic instance of Socratic irony.12 Alternatively, in a series of recent articles, Hugh Benson concedes that Socrates is "ultimately con- cerned with the acquisition of knowledge of the nature of F-ness [in this case, virtue]"; and so, we need not read all of Socrates' claims to be pursuing knowledge as ironic. However, Benson insists that the only function that cross-examination by itself is meant to serve is the exposure of ignorance.l4 By exposing his interlocutors' ignorance, Socrates puts himself in a position to move his interlocutors closer to knowledge; but, Benson argues, "[i]n no case ... do we have evidence for Socrates' method [for 10. Grote 1867, vol. 1, 242. 11. Ibid., 245-6. 12. Robinson 1953, 8-9,17. 13. Benson 1990a, 48; my emphasis. 14. Benson 1987, 67-68;1989, 591-599; 1990a, 47-65; and 1990b,137-153. acquiring knowledge] once the false conceit has been eliminat- ed. We do not know how Socrates will proceed to lead the inter- locutor to the knowledge of the nature of F-ness, now that the interlocutor is in a condition to be so led ...."15 There is, however, one more piece of information that we must consider before we agree that the Socratic method of cross- examination is best viewed merely as the negative "arm of phi- losophy"-namely, Socrates' actual procedure in the early dia- logues. I will suggest that a deflationary analysis of the Socratic method cannot provide an adequate explanation of Socrates' procedure on all occasions. II. The Socratic Method of Inquiry Consider, for example, the Euthyphro and the Hippias Major,.16 Questions about value—about the just and the unjust, the fine 15. Benson 1990a, 63. 16. Gregory Vlastos would dispute my suggestion that the Socratic method of cross-examination is practiced in the Hippias Major. Vlastos argues that, in the Euthydemus, Lysis, and Hippias Major, Socrates abandons "adversary argument as [a] method of philosophical investigation" (Vlastos 1983b, 57-58). The method applied in these dialogues is non-adversarial because "the theses which are ser- iously debated in these dialogues are not contested by the interlocutor; Socrates himself is both their author and critic" (ibid., 57). Vlastos must believe that "adversary argument" is essential to the Socratic method of cross-examination, because from the premise that Socrates has abandoned "adversary argument", Vlastos draws the conclusion that "... Socrates ditches the elenchus" (ibid., 58). Since Vlastos maintains that philosophical theses are "seriously debated" in dia- logues in which "adversary argument" has been abandoned, he cannot believe that what is distinctive of "adversary argument" is simply that a proposed philosophical thesis is subjected to severe examination and criticism ("Elenchus and Mathematics", in Vlastos 1991,113 n28). Rather, it seems that it is also essen- tial to "adversary argument" that the author and critic of a particular philosophical thesis are distinct individuals: "Though Socrates is intensely self- critical, confiding that he is always more eager to examine himself than others .. , the procedural form of elenctic argument prevents him from making any of his own doctrines the target of elenctic refutation by himself" (ibid., 113 n 28). That an author and critic of a particular philosophical thesis are distinct individ- uals, however, is not a sufficient condition for an argument counting as "adver- sarial" : this condition is sometimes met in the Euthydemus, the Lysis and the Hippias Major, where, according to Vlastos, the "adversarial" elenchus is never applied. If an argument is "adversarial", Vlastos suggests, each of the interlocu- tors engaged in the argument must be a competent dialectician capable of putting up a good fight (ibid., 113, 115-116). In the Euthydemus, Vlastos com- ments, Socrates' interlocutor is a "yes-man", who "never puts up any sustained and the base, the good and the bad—are much disputed (Eu. 7b-d; HMa. 294d). Yet many of Socrates' interlocutors begin their con- versations believing that they are experts about such things. Euthyphro claims to be an expert about piety (Eu. 4b, 5a), and Hippias claims to be an expert about the fine (HMa. 286a); but after a few rounds of questioning, it becomes clear that neither can defend his views adequately. Like the statues of Daedalus, every proposition that Euthyphro puts forward "goes around and refuses to stay put" (Eu.
Recommended publications
  • Gregory Vlastos, Socrates
    72 Gregory Vlastos, Socrates: Ironist and ~oral Philosopher (Cam­ bridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), ISBN 0 521 307333 hardback £35/$57-50; ISB~ 0 521 31450X paperback £11-95/S16-95. Socrates: Ironist and Noral Philosopher (SINP) is a book that all students of Socrates and of Greek philosophy will have to read, and will benefit from reading. It isn't the complete portrait of Socrates that many of us hoped it would be (for example, it contains no full discussion of the elenchus) and it is not all new much of it is already familiar from journal articles. It reads, indeed, more like a collection of articles than a unified book, but it is none the less engaging and provocative for that, the product of hard thinking by a major scholar and a life-long Socratist It is also very well written. I shall focus on only a few central themes. 1. Socrates and Plato Vlastos (pp. 46-7) divides the Platonic dialogues into four classes: (1) ELENCTIC; Apology, Charmides, Crico, Euthyphro, Gorgias, Hippias Ninor, Ion, Laches, Protagoras, Republic I (2) TRANSITIONAL: Eu thydemus, Hippias l1ajor, Lysis, l1enexenus, l1eno (3) MIDDLE: Cratylus, Phaedo, Symposium, Republic II-X, Phaedrus, Parmenides, Theaetetus (4) LATE: Timaeus, Crit ias, Sophist, Politicus, Philebus, Laws 73 He believes that the protagonist of the elenctic dialogues ("SocratesE") is the historical Socrates. while the protagonist of the middle and later dialogues ("SocratesM") is little more than a mouthpiece for Plato. Many scholars would go along with this thesis. but they might well balk at the members of (2).
    [Show full text]
  • Sophist Revisited Trends in Classics Q Supplementary Volumes
    Plato’s Sophist Revisited Trends in Classics Q Supplementary Volumes Edited by Franco Montanari and Antonios Rengakos Scientific Committee Alberto Bernabe´ · Margarethe Billerbeck · Claude Calame Philip R. Hardie · Stephen J. Harrison · Stephen Hinds Richard Hunter · Christina Kraus · Giuseppe Mastromarco Gregory Nagy · Theodore D. Papanghelis · Giusto Picone Kurt Raaflaub · Bernhard Zimmermann Volume 19 De Gruyter Plato’s Sophist Revisited Edited by Beatriz Bossi Thomas M. Robinson De Gruyter ISBN 978-3-11-028695-3 e-ISBN 978-3-11-028713-4 ISSN 1868-4785 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data A CIP catalog record for this book has been applied for at the Library of Congress. Bibliographic information published by the Deutsche Nationalbibliothek The Deutsche Nationalbibliothek lists this publication in the Deutsche Nationalbibliografie; detailed bibliographic data are available in the Internet at http://dnb.dnb.de. Ą 2013 Walter de Gruyter GmbH, Berlin/Boston Logo: Christopher Schneider, Laufen Printing: Hubert & Co. GmbH & Co. KG, Göttingen ϱ Printed on acid-free paper Printed in Germany www.degruyter.com Preface This book consists of a selection of papers presented at the International Spring Seminar on Plato’s Sophist (26–31 May 2009, Centro de Ciencias de Benasque ‘Pedro Pascual’, Spain) with the financial support of MI- CINN, CSIC, Universidad de Zaragoza and Gobierno de Aragón. The Conference was organized by the editors, under the auspices of the Director of the Centre, Prof. José Ignacio Latorre, who provided invaluable assistance at every stage of the Conference, up to its close with a lecture on Quantum Physics for Philosophers. The aim of the conference was the promotion of Plato studies in Spain in the framework of discussions with a number of international scholars of distinction in the field, whilst at the same time looking afresh at one of Plato’s most philosophically profound dialogues.
    [Show full text]
  • Gregory Vlastos
    Gregory Vlastos: A Preliminary Inventory of His Papers at the Harry Ransom Center Descriptive Summary Creator: Vlastos, Gregory, 1907-1991 Title: Gregory Vlastos Papers Dates: circa 1930s-1991 Extent: 100 document boxes (42.00 linear feet) Abstract: The papers of philosopher Gregory Vlastos, a scholar of ancient Greek philosophy who spent most of his career studying the thought of Plato and Socrates, document his studies, his writings, and his career as an educator at several American universities. Call Number: Manuscript Collection MS-4361 Language: English, with Ancient Greek, French, German, Italian, Latin, Modern Greek, and Spanish Access: Open for research Administrative Information Acquisition: Gifts, 1993-2010 (G9070, G9134, G9163, G9225, G9252, G9628, G9979, G9982, G10214, G10288, G11877, 10-03-014-G) Processed by: Hope Rider, 2006; updated by Joan Sibley, 2016 Repository: The University of Texas at Austin, Harry Ransom Center Vlastos, Gregory, 1907-1991 Manuscript Collection MS-4361 Scope and Contents The papers of philosopher Gregory Vlastos (1907-1991), a scholar of ancient Greek philosophy who spent most of his career studying the thought of Plato and Socrates, document his studies, his writings, and his career as an educator at several American universities, especially Cornell, Princeton, and The University of California at Berkeley. The papers are arranged in six series: I. Correspondence and Offprint Files, II. Study, Lecture, and Teaching Files, III. Works, IV. Works by Others, V. Miscellaneous, and VI. Offprints Removed from Manuscripts. The Correspondence and Offprint Files (35 boxes) in Series I. represent Vlastos' extensive correspondence with other philosophers, classicists, former students, academics, and others. The files are arranged alphabetically by correspondent name, and generally include not only letters received, but copies of Vlastos' responses.
    [Show full text]
  • The Science of Philosophy: Discourse and Deception in Plato's Sophist
    The Science of Philosophy - Discourse and Deception in Plato’s Sophist - For Epoché [Penultimate ver.] The Science of Philosophy: Discourse and Deception in Plato’s Sophist Olof Pettersson Abstract: At 252e1 to 253c9 in Plato’s Sophist, the Eleatic Visitor explains why philosophy is a science. Like the art of grammar, philosophical knowledge corresponds to a generic structure of discrete kinds and is acquired by systematic analysis of how these kinds intermingle. In the literature, the Visitor’s science is either understood as an expression of a mature and authentic platonic metaphysics, or as a sophisticated illusion staged to illustrate the seductive lure of sophistic deception. By showing how the Visitor’s account of the science of philosophy is just as comprehensive, phantasmatic and self-concealing as the art of sophistry identified at the dialogue’s outset, this paper argues in favor of the latter view. Introduction At 252e1 to 253c9 in Plato’s Sophist, the Eleatic Visitor1 explains what he means by philosophy. Like the art of grammar, philosophy is about parts: All things can be analyzed. But not all parts fit together. Just like the letters of the alphabet, some can be combined and some cannot. According to the Visitor, it is knowledge about this that constitutes philosophy (253d1-e2) – a science he classifies as the greatest of them all (253c4-9). In the literature there are two main takes on this. Either the Visitors’ philosophical science is taken to be an expression of an authentic and mature platonic metaphysics; or it is said to be a sophisticated illusion staged to illustrate the seductive lure of sophistic deception.
    [Show full text]
  • The Mathematical Anti-Atomism of Plato's Timaeus
    The mathematical anti-atomism of Plato’s Timaeus Luc Brisson, Salomon Ofman To cite this version: Luc Brisson, Salomon Ofman. The mathematical anti-atomism of Plato’s Timaeus. Ancient Philoso- phy, Philosophy Documentation Center, In press. hal-02923266 HAL Id: hal-02923266 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-02923266 Submitted on 26 Aug 2020 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. The mathematical anti-atomism of Plato’s Timaeus Luc Brisson Salomon Ofman Centre Jean Pépin CNRS-Institut mathématique de Jussieu- CNRS-UMR 8230 Paris Rive Gauche École normale supérieure Sorbonne Université Paris Sciences Lettres Paris Université Abstract. In Plato’s eponymous dialogue, Timaeus, the main character presents the universe as an almost perfect sphere filled by tiny invisible particles having the form of four regular polyhedrons. At first glance, such a construction may seem close to an atomic theory. However, one does not find any text in Antiquity tying Timaeus’ cosmology to the atomists, and Aristotle made a clear distinction between Plato and the latter. Despite the cosmology in the Timaeus is so far apart from the one of the atomists, Plato is commonly presented in contemporary literature as some sort of atomist, sometimes as supporting a so-called form of ‘mathematical atomism’.
    [Show full text]
  • AN INTRODUCTION to PRE-SOCRATIC ETHICS: HERACLITUS and DEMOCRITUS on HUMAN NATURE and CONDUCT (PART I: on MOTION and CHANGE) Erman Kaplama
    Cosmos and History: The Journal of Natural and Social Philosophy, vol. 17, no. 1, 2021 AN INTRODUCTION TO PRE-SOCRATIC ETHICS: HERACLITUS AND DEMOCRITUS ON HUMAN NATURE AND CONDUCT (PART I: ON MOTION AND CHANGE) Erman Kaplama ABSTRACT: Both Heraclitus and Democritus, as the philosophers of historia peri phuseôs, consider nature and human character, habit, law and soul as interrelated, emphasizing the links between phusis, kinesis, ethos, logos, kresis, nomos and daimon. On the one hand, Heraclitus’s principle of change (panta rhei) and his emphasis on the element of fire and cosmic motion ultimately dominate his ethics, reinforcing his ideas of change, moderation, balance and justice; on the other, Democritus’s atomist description of phusis and motion underlies his principle of moderation and his ideas of health and measured life. In this series, particularly referring to the main principles of motion, moderation and justice, I attempt to describe a coherent pre-Socratic ethical perspective based on the Heraclitean and Democritean fragments. I explore the connections between their physics and ethics, also borrowing from Nietzsche’s lectures and writings on the Pre-Socratics. I redefine such Heraclitean and Democritean concepts as harmony, order, perfection, health, self-control, contentment, cheerfulness, concord, sound judgment, wisdom, measure and balance and discuss them under the principles of motion (phusis), moderation (sophrosyne) and justice. In doing so, I also expose the relevance of the Heraclitean notion of logos (interpreting it as the underlying categorical principle of transition between phusis and ethos) in bringing together these ideas and principles. Finally, based on this pre-Socratic Weltanschauung, I assess the possibility of a coherent picture of humanity, its nature and conduct as extending from or fitting into or extending-from-when- fitting-into the cosmos of moving forces and atoms.
    [Show full text]
  • Rethinking Bernard Williams' Criticism of the City-Soul Analogy in Plato's Republic
    The 3rd BESETO Conference of Philosophy Session 14 Rethinking Bernard Williams’ Criticism of the City-Soul Analogy in Plato’s Republic (draft) WU Tianyue Peking University Abstract This essay takes a close look at Bernard Williams’ criticism of the city-soul analogy in Plato’s Republic, which “has dominated the discussion of its subject ever since.” (Myles Burnyeat). I start with reviving Williams’ arguments to elucidate the genuine challenge to Plato’s theory of justice by introducing city-soul analogy. The second part of this essay aims to show that Williams’ critics, such as Jonathan Lear, G.R.F. Ferrari, and Nobert Blössner have not successfully solved the problems Williams brought forth in his article. Finally, I call attention to a neglected aspect of the city-soul analogy, i.e. the predominance of reason in Plato’s theory of justice. By carefully analyzing Plato’s account of justice and briefly addressing the discussion about philosopher-kings in Book V–VII, I argue that Plato actually defines justice as the rule of the reasoning part. With this new definition of justice, the city-soul analogy will be shown philo- sophically accountable within the whole argumentative structure of Republic. It is well known that Republic is not an accurate translation of the ancient Greek word πολιτεία, whose meanings range from “condition and rights of a citizen” to “constitution of a state”1. The Chinese translation Li Xiang Guo, which literally means the ideal state, even goes further to iden- tify Plato’s magnum opus as a utopian writing. However, Plato’s or Socrates’ mythical narrative2 of the ideal city (καλλιπόλις) and its constitution starts rather late in the middle of Book II of Republic.
    [Show full text]
  • Confusion About the Socratic Method
    68 Confusion About the Socratic Method Confusion about the Socratic Method: Socratic Paradoxes and Contemporary Invocations of Socrates Rob Reich Stanford University Ask the average person, “Who was Socrates and what did he do?” and you are likely to get the following response: Socrates was a old philosopher who bothered people with questions and was ultimately put to death. Almost twenty-five hundred years after placidly drinking the hemlock, what we remember Socrates for is his habitual questioning, his demand to live an examined life.1 The figure of Socrates is in ordinary discourse synonymous with his method — the Socratic method. Contemporary scholars echo this commonplace opinion. Gregory Vlastos, who devoted his entire life to Socratic scholarship, reflects that the Socratic method is Socrates’ “greatest contribution” and moreover, one which ranks “among the greatest achievements of humanity.”2 The results of Socrates’ life, the conclusions he drew about how we ought to live, Vlastos argues, are less important than the manner in which he conducted his life, the style of inquiry he originated and bequeathed to future generations. Indeed, aside from philosophers, few today could identify what specific beliefs Socrates held. In contrast to most other great thinkers, Socrates’ primary legacy is not a contribution to humanity’s storehouse of knowl- edge, but a pedagogy; not substance but process. To overstate only slightly, for Socrates, and for our understanding of him, method is all. Yet despite the general acknowledgment of Socrates’ achievement, it is not at all clear what exactly the Socratic method is, and more specifically, what the Socratic method does, either in the dialogues or in contemporary invocations.
    [Show full text]
  • The Republic and Allegory
    Studia Antiqua Volume 4 Number 1 Article 3 April 2005 Plato in Context: The Republic and Allegory Joseph Spencer Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarsarchive.byu.edu/studiaantiqua Part of the Classics Commons BYU ScholarsArchive Citation Spencer, Joseph. "Plato in Context: The Republic and Allegory." Studia Antiqua 4, no. 1 (2005). https://scholarsarchive.byu.edu/studiaantiqua/vol4/iss1/3 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at BYU ScholarsArchive. It has been accepted for inclusion in Studia Antiqua by an authorized editor of BYU ScholarsArchive. For more information, please contact [email protected], [email protected]. Plato in Context: The Republic and Allegory JOSEPH SPENCER n his early work, The Birth rif Tragetfy, Friedrich Nietzsche promoted the idea that Plato was the source of everything I strait-laced in Western civilization. For Nietzsche, that meant that Plato had ruined the fun because he had repressed the Dionysian camp, casting himself prostrate before the Socratic altar. Because Nietzsche's claim was well received in his era of continental confusion and soul-searching, scholarship since has inherited the prejudiced opinion that the ancient philosopher was more than a little tainted with predilections toward the clear!J pious and saintly Apollonian Athenian.l Hundreds of volumes written in the last century are built on the premise that Plato was as we say he was-that there was not much more to him than his Theory of Forms and a few other idealist propositions. Indeed, once a conclusion has been drawn, it is easy to simply insert it again and again into the primary texts.
    [Show full text]
  • Necessity and Form-Copies: Republic, Timaeus, and Laws [Abstract] Plato's Metaphysics Employs Three Distinct Ontological State
    Necessity and Form-Copies: Republic, Timaeus, and Laws [Abstract] Plato’s metaphysics employs three distinct ontological states: Forms, particulars, and form-copies. Fundamentally, Forms are static beings; particulars are dynamic non-beings; form- copies are dynamic instances of being(s). Plato’s metaphysics is met with difficulty when we start to question how exactly form-copies, mixtures of two seemingly incompatible ontological states (Forms and particulars), come into existence. In this paper, I offer an analysis concerning the relationship between Plato’s two cosmological causes (i.e. Reason and Necessity) and form- copy generation. I am chiefly interested in what finalizes the union between particulars and Forms to generate form-copies. I refer to this finalizing agent as the “form-copy agent.” Plato puts forth two causes: Reason and Necessity. Both Reason and Necessity possess operative limits (authority) defined by causal capabilities. The abstract parts and machinery are subsumed under Reason, while Necessity is broadly associated with physical reality. The causal role of Reason is to define all being. Necessity’s causal role, on the other hand, remains somewhat obscure. If Reason defines being, what does Necessity accomplish as a cause? Plato’s metaphysics needs a catalyzing agent that can account for particulars’ transition into form- copies. Necessity, I argue, is this agent. 1 Introduction In Plato’s first real attempts to outline the theory of Forms (Phaedo), two principal modes of being are posited: being (οὐσία) and participation (μετέχειν). These two modes of being give rise to three definitive ontological states: Forms, particulars, and form-copies. Forms are defined by being (οὐσία).
    [Show full text]
  • Truth and Falsehood in Plato's Sophist
    University of Kentucky UKnowledge Theses and Dissertations--Philosophy Philosophy 2014 Truth and Falsehood in Plato's Sophist Michael Oliver Wiitala University of Kentucky, [email protected] Right click to open a feedback form in a new tab to let us know how this document benefits ou.y Recommended Citation Wiitala, Michael Oliver, "Truth and Falsehood in Plato's Sophist" (2014). Theses and Dissertations-- Philosophy. 3. https://uknowledge.uky.edu/philosophy_etds/3 This Doctoral Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy at UKnowledge. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theses and Dissertations--Philosophy by an authorized administrator of UKnowledge. For more information, please contact [email protected]. STUDENT AGREEMENT: I represent that my thesis or dissertation and abstract are my original work. Proper attribution has been given to all outside sources. I understand that I am solely responsible for obtaining any needed copyright permissions. I have obtained needed written permission statement(s) from the owner(s) of each third-party copyrighted matter to be included in my work, allowing electronic distribution (if such use is not permitted by the fair use doctrine) which will be submitted to UKnowledge as Additional File. I hereby grant to The University of Kentucky and its agents the irrevocable, non-exclusive, and royalty-free license to archive and make accessible my work in whole or in part in all forms of media, now or hereafter known. I agree that the document mentioned above may be made available immediately for worldwide access unless an embargo applies. I retain all other ownership rights to the copyright of my work.
    [Show full text]
  • Socrates, Vlastos, and Analytic Philosophy
    chapter 36 Socrates, Vlastos, and Analytic Philosophy David Conan Wolfsdorf 1 Introduction Prior to World War II, the Anglo-Germanophone movement that came to be called “analytic philosophy”1 was largely ahistorical. Its governing philosophical concerns lay in epistemology and methodology, in the philosophy of mathematics and logic, the philosophy of language, and the philosophy of science. Notwithstanding the importance and influence of intuitionism in the first decades of the twentieth century,2 by the thirties noncognitivism had eclipsed cognitivism in ethics.3 Adherents of philosophical analysis by and large held that ethical utterances and thoughts are not truth-apt and thus that ethics is not a domain of knowledge. Illustrative statements by Wittgenstein, Carnap, and Russell follow: My whole tendency and the tendency of all men who ever tried to write or talk Ethics or Religion was to run against the boundaries of language. This running against the walls of our cage is perfectly, absolutely hopeless. Ethics so far as it springs from the desire to say something about the ultimate meaning of life, the absolute good, the absolute valuable, can be no science. What it says does not add to our knowledge.4 Wittgenstein 1965, 12 1 On the use of the phrase, cf. G.H. von Wright: “It has struck me that the name ‘analytic philosophy,’ as far as I know became current relatively late in the history of the movement. It only gradually supplanted the label ‘logical positivism’ which lingered on longer after it had become obsolete. To the change in terminology contributed, I should think, significantly the works of Arthur Pap [1949].
    [Show full text]