A Treatise of Legal Philosophy and General Jurisprudence Volume 12 Legal Philosophy in the Twentieth Century: the Civil Law Worl

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

A Treatise of Legal Philosophy and General Jurisprudence Volume 12 Legal Philosophy in the Twentieth Century: the Civil Law Worl A Treatise of Legal Philosophy and General Jurisprudence Volume 12 Legal Philosophy in the Twentieth Century: The Civil Law World A Treatise of Legal Philosophy and General Jurisprudence Editor-in-Chief Enrico Pattaro, CIRSFID and Law Faculty, University of Bologna, Italy Advisory Board Norberto Bobbio † Ronald M. Dworkin † Lawrence M. Friedman, Stanford Law School, Stanford University, USA Knud Haakonssen, Department of History, University of Sussex, UK Associate Editors Gerald J. Postema, Department of Philosophy, The University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill, USA Peter G. Stein, Emeritus Regius Professor of Civil Law, University of Cambridge, UK Assistant Editor Antonino Rotolo, Department of Legal Studies and CIRSFID, University of Bologna, Italy A Treatise of Legal Philosophy and General Jurisprudence Volume 12 Legal Philosophy in the Twentieth Century: The Civil Law World Tome 1: Language Areas edited by Enrico Pattaro CIRSFID and Law Faculty, University of Bologna and Corrado Roversi Department of Legal Studies and CIRSFID, University of Bologna with contributions by Mikhail Antonov, André Jean Arnaud, José Manuel Aroso Linhares, Manuel Atienza, Carla Henriete Bevilacqua Piccolo, Uta Bindreiter, Vihren Bouzov, Alexander Bröstl, Pierre Brunet, Agostino Carrino, Veronique Champeil-Desplats, Svein Eng, Carla Faralli, Tomasz Gizbert-Studnicki, Jean Louis Halpérin, Jasminka Hasanbegoviü, Carlos Miguel Herrera, Hasso Hofmann, Adrian-Paul Iliescu, Federico Lijoi, Susanna Lindroos-Hovinheimo, Ronaldo Macedo, Luís Meneses do Vale, Eric Millard, Ivan Padjen, Henrik Palmer Olsen, Marijan Pavþnik, Krzysztof Páeszka, Benjamín Rivaya, Antonino Scalone, Alessandro Serpe, Ana Margarida Simões Gaudêncio, Arend Soeteman, José de Sousa e Brito, Constantinos Stamatis, Giuliana Stella, Simina Tănăsescu, Mark Van Hoecke, Csaba Varga, Rodolfo Vázquez, Jan WoleĔski Assistant Editors: Erica Calardo, Francesca Faenza, Nicoletta Bersier Ladavac, Migle Laukyte, and Filippo Valente Editors Enrico Pattaro Corrado Roversi CIRSFID CIRSFID University of Bologna University of Bologna Bologna, Italy Bologna, Italy ISBN 978-94-007-1478-6 ISBN 978-94-007-1479-3 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-94-007-1479-3 Library of Congress Control Number: 2016945793 © Springer Netherlands 2016 This work is subject to copyright. All rights are reserved by the Publisher, whether the whole or part of the material is concerned, specifically the rights of translation, reprinting, reuse of illustrations, recitation, broadcasting, reproduction on microfilms or in any other physical way, and transmission or information storage and retrieval, electronic adaptation, computer software, or by similar or dissimilar methodology now known or hereafter developed. The use of general descriptive names, registered names, trademarks, service marks, etc. in this publication does not imply, even in the absence of a specific statement, that such names are exempt from the relevant protective laws and regulations and therefore free for general use. The publisher, the authors and the editors are safe to assume that the advice and information in this book are believed to be true and accurate at the date of publication. Neither the publisher nor the authors or the editors give a warranty, express or implied, with respect to the material contained herein or for any errors or omissions that may have been made. Printed on acid-free paper This Springer imprint is published by Springer Nature The registered company is Springer Netherlands Niente è fatto finché tutto non è fatto. Nothing is done until everything is done. (Pietro Nenni, Diari, 25 July 1944) TABLE OF CONTENTS A Note on the Authors and the Editors XXI General Editor’s Preface XXXIII Preface by the Editors of Volume 12 (by Enrico Pattaro and Corrado Roversi) XXXV Part One - The German-Speaking Countries Premise (by Agostino Carrino and Hasso Hofmann) 3 Introduction: Philosophy of Law and Conceptions of the World (by Agostino Carrino) 5 Chapter 1 - The Rebirth of Legal Philosophy within the Frame of Neo-Kantianism (by Agostino Carrino) 13 1.1. Neo-Kantianism of the Baden School as a Philosophy of Values: Windelband, Rickert, and Lask 13 1.2. The Neo-Kantianism of the Marburg School: Cohen, Natorp, Cassirer 16 1.3. Rudolf Stammler’s Social Idealism 18 1.4. Emil Lask’s Philosophy of Law 23 1.5. Ethics and the Science of Law in Hermann Cohen 26 1.6. Ethics and Law in Paul Natorp (by Federico Lijoi) 29 1.7. Ernst Cassirer and Natural Law 31 1.8. Law and Worldviews: Gustav Radbruch’s Three-Dimensional Conception of Law 34 1.9. Sovereignty and Legal Consciousness in Leonard Nelson’s Legal Philosophy 39 1.10. Fritz Münch’s and Max Ernst Mayer’s Philosophy of Culture 42 1.10.1. The Philosophy of Culture 42 1.10.2. Fritz Münch 45 1.10.3. Max Ernst Mayer’s Philosophy of Law 47 VIII TREATISE, 12 (1) - 20TH CENTURY: THE CIVIL LAW WORLD Chapter 2 - Logistic Normativism: The Wiener rechtstheoretische Schule (by Agostino Carrino) 51 2.1. Precursors of the Pure Theory of Law: František Weyr 51 2.1.1. Introductory Remarks 51 2.1.2. The Law as a Unitary System 51 2.1.3. Validity and Causality 53 2.1.4. The Autonomy of Legal Science 54 2.1.5. Public Law and Private Law 55 2.1.6. The Hierarchical Structure of the Legal System and the “Metanormative” 57 2.1.7. Sein and Sollen 58 2.1.8. Teleology 60 2.1.9. The Practice and Theory of Law 61 2.1.10. On the Concept of Sovereignty 62 2.2. Precursors of the Pure Theory of Law: Hugo Krabbe (by Giuliana Stella) 65 2.3. Hans Kelsen’s Normativist Logicism (from 1911 to 1934) 72 2.3.1. Substance and Function in Kelsen’s Philosophy of Law 72 2.3.2. The Problem of Legal Science in Kelsen’s Pure Theory of Law 83 2.3.2.1. The Disavowal 83 2.3.2.2. The Irrationalism Marking the Second Phase of the RRL 89 2.3.2.3. The Aporias in the RRL 93 2.3.2.4. What Is the RRL Good For? 99 2.3.2.5. A Pessimistic Anthropology 103 2.3.2.6. The Basic Norm: Critical Idealism or Critical Positivism? 105 2.3.2.7. Formal Logical Natural-Law Theory and Pacifism 108 2.3.2.8. Kelsen and Hegel 110 2.3.2.9. Kelsen’s Theory of Law as a Logic of Law 112 2.3.2.10. Between Purity and Reality: The Theory of Legal Interpretation in the RRL 114 2.4. The Vienna School of Law: Merkl and Verdross 116 2.4.1. Adolf J. Merkl and the Hierarchical Construction of Law 116 2.4.2. Alfred Verdross and the Grundnorm of International Law 119 2.5. Kelsen’s Critics 124 2.5.1. Introduction 124 2.5.2. Fritz Sander (by Federico Lijoi) 124 2.5.3. Alexander Hold von Ferneck (by Antonino Scalone) 129 TABLE OF CONTENTS IX 2.5.4. Ernst Schwind: Between History and the Philosophy of Law 131 Chapter 3 - The Sociological Philosophy of Law as an Alternative to Normativism (by Agostino Carrino) 133 3.1. Hermann Ulrich Kantorowicz and the Free Law Movement 133 3.2. Ignatz Kornfeld and the Law as Force 139 3.3. Eugen Ehrlich and the Foundation of Legal Sociology 142 3.4. Karl Georg Wurzel and the Social Dynamics of Law 149 3.5. Ernst Seidler and Empirical Social Science 152 3.6. Legal Science and Psychology According to Wilhelm Wundt (by Federico Lijoi) 154 Chapter 4 - From Criticism to the Phenomenology of Law (by Giuliana Stella) 157 4.1. Introduction: The Genesis of the Method 157 4.2. Adolf Reinach and the A Priori Elements of Law 159 4.3. Gerhart Husserl and Law between Time and History 165 4.4. Felix Kaufmann: The Form and Meaning of Legal Norms 174 4.5. Fritz Schreier and Legal Interpretation 180 Chapter 5 - From the Criticism of Neo-Kantianism to Neo-Hegelianism in the Philosophy of Law (by Agostino Carrino) 189 5.1. The Crisis of Neo-Kantianism in Erich Kaufmann’s Philosophy of Law 189 5.2. Two Precursors of Legal Neo-Hegelianism: Josef Kohler and Fritz Berolzheimer 193 5.3. Julius Binder, Founder of the Neo-Hegelian School 194 5.4. Karl Larenz up to 1933 202 5.5. Walther Schönfeld: From Idealistic Personalism to Christian Theology of Law 204 Chapter 6 - Law and the State in the Conservative Revolution (by Agostino Carrino) 209 6.1. Law and the State in Oswald Spengler 209 6.2. Law and the State in Othmar Spann’s Universalist Philosophy 212 6.3. Nihilism, Power, and Bourgeois Law in Ernst Jünger 216 6.4. Rudolf Smend and the Constitution as “Integration” 220 X TREATISE, 12 (1) - 20TH CENTURY: THE CIVIL LAW WORLD Chapter 7 - Marxism in the Philosophy of Law (by Agostino Carrino) 223 7.1. Anton Menger and “Ex Cathedra Socialism” 223 7.2. Austro-Marxism 224 7.2.1. Karl Renner 225 7.2.2. Max Adler 230 7.3. Georg Lukács, Karl Korsch, and “Western Marxism” 232 7.3.1. The Concrete Totality in Georg Lukács’s History and Class Consciousness 233 7.3.2. Karl Korsch: From the Free Law Movement to the Materialist Critique of Law 237 7.4. Hermann Heller: Socialism, the State, and Culture 241 7.5. Franz L. Neumann’s Critical Theory of the State 244 Chapter 8 - From Norm to Decision to the Concrete Order: The Legal Philosophy of Carl Schmitt (by Agostino Carrino) 247 8.1. Constitutional Theory 247 8.2. On European Jurisprudence 256 Chapter 9 - Nazi Philosophy of Law and of the State (by Agostino Carrino) 269 9.1. Introduction 269 9.2. Race as the Foundation of Law: Helmut Nicolai and Others 270 9.3. The Fight against Rights 272 9.4.
Recommended publications
  • Jurisprudence--Philosophy Or Science Henry Rottschaefer
    University of Minnesota Law School Scholarship Repository Minnesota Law Review 1927 Jurisprudence--Philosophy or Science Henry Rottschaefer Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.umn.edu/mlr Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Rottschaefer, Henry, "Jurisprudence--Philosophy or Science" (1927). Minnesota Law Review. 1465. https://scholarship.law.umn.edu/mlr/1465 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the University of Minnesota Law School. It has been accepted for inclusion in Minnesota Law Review collection by an authorized administrator of the Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. MINNESOTA LAW REVIEW Journal of the State Bar Association VOLUI%1E 11 MARCH, 1927 No. 4 JURISPRUDENCE- PHILOSOPHY OR SCIENCE By HENRY ROTTSCHAEFER* T WOULD perhaps be practically impossible to secure for any definition of the term Jurisprudence any very general accep- tance. It is doubtful whether there exists even any general agree- ment as to what subjects are within its scope. The problem of whether, and in what sense, it is to be considered philosophy or science, cannot, however, be discussed without adopting at least some tentative notion of its meaning that shall serve as the basis for the discussion. This can be more effectively done by a general description of the types of problem usually dealt with in treatises and courses on Jurisprudence than by framing a logically correct definition that secured accuracy and completeness by resort to a convenient vagueness. Investigation discloses its use to denote lines of inquiry having little in common other than a professed interest in general questions and problems concerning law and justice.
    [Show full text]
  • The Utilitarian Influence on American Legal Science in the Early Republic
    1 The Utilitarian Influence on American Legal Science in the Early Republic Steven J. Macias California Western School of Law [email protected] (rev. 9/8) In Utilitarian Jurisprudence in America, Peter King held up Thomas Cooper, David Hoffman, and Richard Hildreth, as those early American legal thinkers most notably influenced by Bentham.1 For King, Hildreth represented “the first real fruition of Benthamism in America,” whereas Cooper’s use of Bentham was subservient to his Southern ideology, and Hoffman’s use was mainly to “reinforce” a utilitarianism otherwise “derived from Paley.”2 Although Hildreth’s work falls outside the timeframe of early-American legal science, Cooper’s and Hoffman’s work falls squarely within it. What follows is, in part, a reevaluation of Cooper and Hoffman within the broader context of early republican jurisprudence. Because Cooper became an advocate of southern secession late in life, too many historians have dismissed his life’s work, which consisted of serious intellectual undertakings in law and philosophy, as well as medicine and chemistry. Hoffman, on the other hand, has become a man for all seasons among legal historians. His seven-year course of legal study contained such a vast and eclectic array of titles, that one can superficially paint Hoffman as advocating just about anything. As of late, Hoffman has been discussed as a leading exponent of Scottish Common Sense philosophy, second only to James Wilson a generation earlier. This tension between Hoffman-the-utilitarian and Hoffman-the-Scot requires a new examination. A fresh look at the utilitarian influence on American jurisprudence also requires that we acknowledge 1 PETER J.
    [Show full text]
  • The Politics of Jurisprudence: Liberty and Equality in Rawls and Dworkin
    The Catholic Lawyer Volume 25 Number 2 Volume 25, Spring 1980, Number 2 Article 4 The Politics of Jurisprudence: Liberty and Equality in Rawls and Dworkin Stephen C. Hicks Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.stjohns.edu/tcl Part of the Jurisprudence Commons This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at St. John's Law Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in The Catholic Lawyer by an authorized editor of St. John's Law Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE POLITICS OF JURISPRUDENCE: LIBERTY AND EQUALITY IN RAWLS AND DWORKIN STEPHEN C. HICKS* Law as a general system of rules impartially applied acts as the me- dium of sovereign governmental order harmonizing the interests of indi- viduals and groups in society as equally and fairly as possible. The indi- vidual is free within the rules establishing security and order and is free from law which is not conducive to the general good. Similarly, an indi- vidual is free to pursue his own ends if they are compatible with the greatest happiness of the greatest number and also is free not to act on behalf of the common good. While these boundaries are defined by law, the actual social relations within them are the concern of ethics or psy- chology, not legislation.' Thus, political theory as utilitarianism sees the law according to its own representation of the good and its own descrip- tion of human nature. This is the original coordination of individual soci- ety and the body politic in our tradition.
    [Show full text]
  • Martin Loughlin Political Jurisprudence
    Martin Loughlin Political jurisprudence Article (Accepted version) (Refereed) Original citation: Loughlin, Martin (2016) Political jurisprudence. Jus Politicum: Revue de Droit Politique, 16 . ISSN 2101-8790 © 2016 Revue internationale de droit politique This version available at: http://eprints.lse.ac.uk/67311/ Available in LSE Research Online: August 2016 LSE has developed LSE Research Online so that users may access research output of the School. Copyright © and Moral Rights for the papers on this site are retained by the individual authors and/or other copyright owners. Users may download and/or print one copy of any article(s) in LSE Research Online to facilitate their private study or for non-commercial research. You may not engage in further distribution of the material or use it for any profit-making activities or any commercial gain. You may freely distribute the URL (http://eprints.lse.ac.uk) of the LSE Research Online website. This document is the author’s final accepted version of the journal article. There may be differences between this version and the published version. You are advised to consult the publisher’s version if you wish to cite from it. POLITICAL JURISPRUDENCE MARTIN LOUGHLIN I: INTRODUCTION Political jurisprudence is a discipline that explains the way in which governmental authority is constituted. It flourished within European thought in the period between the sixteenth and nineteenth centuries and since the twentieth century has been in decline. That decline, attributable mainly to an extending rationalization of life and thought, has led to governmental authority increasingly being expressed in technical terms. And because many of the implications of this development have been masked by the growth of an academic disciplinary specialization that sacrifices breadth of understanding for depth of knowledge, sustaining the discipline has proved difficult.
    [Show full text]
  • Robin West, "Jurisprudence and Gender": Defending a Radical
    The University of Chicago Law Review Volume 75 Summer 2008 Number 3 © 2008 by The University of Chicago DEMISESQUICENTENNIAL Robin West, Jurisprudence and Gender: Defending a Radical Liberalism Martha C. Nussbaumt Robin West's Jurisprudenceand Gender' has justly had consider- able influence. West argues persuasively that people concerned with achieving sex equality need to do both practical, political work and theoretical, conceptual work. If the concepts and normative theories remain incompletely developed, they will offer defective guidance to practical work. Therefore, "[f]eminism must envision a post-patriarchal world, for without such a vision we have little direction."2 This conten- tion is both true and important. West then argues that the vision of feminist jurisprudence must be of a world in which all forms of life will be recognized, respected and honored. A per- fect legal system will protect against harms sustained by all forms of life, and will recognize life affirming values generated by all forms of being.... Masculine jurisprudence must become human- ist jurisprudence, and humanist jurisprudence must become a ju- risprudence unmodified.' I find this conclusion a bit underdeveloped: surely a "humanist" juri- sprudence is far from being a jurisprudence in which "all forms of life" t Ernst Freund Distinguished Service Professor of Law and Ethics, Philosophy Department, Law School, and Divinity School, The University of Chicago. 1 Robin West, Jurisprudenceand Gender, 55 U Chi L Rev 1 (1988). 2 Id at 72. 3 Id. The University of Chicago Law Review [75:985 are respected and valued. I would like to know what sorts of respect and recognition animal lives are due in West's conception, and also what forms of respect she would support for nonsentient beings such as plants and ecosystems.
    [Show full text]
  • Norberto Bobbio's Right and Left Between Classic Concepts And
    Norberto Bobbio’s Right and Left between Classic Concepts and Contemporary Crises M. F. N. Giglioli “Doktor König, der linksgerichtet war, mit Rußland sympathisierte und sich für einen Revolutionär hielt, dem nur eine Revolution fehlt, hörte mit der Andacht zu, die Gegner der bürgerlichen Gesellschaftsordnung für deren Stützen immer bereithalten. Bernheim hielt ihn für einen mächtigen Führer des Proletariats, und er sah in Bernheim einen geheimen Vertrauten der Schwerindustrie. So saßen sie einander gegenüber, die Repräsentanten zweier feindlicher Mächte, persönlich objektiv bis zur Freundschaft und jeder erfüllt von dem Gedanken an die Wirkung, die er auf den andern ausübte.” Joseph Roth, Rechts und Links Eighteen years after the publication of Norberto Bobbio’s classic statement on the concepts of Right and Left (Bobbio, 1994), the dichotomy is as central as ever to the functioning of democratic institutions and to the self-perception of ordinary people. At the same time, its political content appears eroded, to the point where many have claimed it lingers merely as an empty signifier. In order to account for this discrepancy, I will sketch an argument drawing on the pragmatic valence and on the historical development of the Left- Right cleavage. Tracing the paradigm of the dichotomy, underlying Bobbio’s argument, to 19th century debates regarding the speed of progress understood as a linear process ultimately productive of social leveling, I interpret the contemporary predicament not as a transcendence of the antagonism of Right and Left, but as a displacement of the locus of political decision that renders national politics irrelevant for the issues that characterize the dichotomy.
    [Show full text]
  • Hart's Postscript and the Character of Political Philosophy
    Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, Vol. 24, No. 1 (2004), pp. 1–37 Hart’s Postscript and the Character of Political Philosophy RONALD DWORKIN* Abstract—Several years ago I prepared a point-by-point response to this postscript as a working paper for the NYU Colloquium in Legal, Moral and Political Philosophy. I have not yet published that paper, but I understand that copies of it are in circulation. I do not intend to recapitulate the arguments of that working paper, but instead to concentrate on one aspect of Hart’s Postscript, which is his defence of Archimedean jurisprudence. I shall have something to say about his own legal philosophy, which was a form of legal positivism. But I shall mainly be concerned about the method that he said generated his legal positivism. 1. Archimedeans A. Hart’s Project When Professor H.L.A. Hart died, his papers contained a draft of a long comment about my own work in legal theory, which he apparently intended to publish, when Wnished, as an epilogue to a new edition of his best-known book, The Concept of Law. I have no idea how satisWed he was with this draft; it contains much that he might well not have found fully satisfactory. But the draft was indeed pub- lished as a Postscript to a new edition of the book. In this lecture I discuss the Postscript’s central and most important charge. In The Concept of Law, Hart set out to say what law is and how valid law is to be identiWed, and he claimed, for that project, two important features.
    [Show full text]
  • Therapeutic Jurisprudence Lessons for Law Reformers
    Touro Law Review Volume 18 Number 3 Symposium: The Varieties of Therapeutic Experience Excerpts from the Article 4 Second International Conference on Therapeutic Jurisprudence May 2015 Rights are Not Enough: Therapeutic Jurisprudence Lessons for Law Reformers Nathalie Des Rosiers Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.tourolaw.edu/lawreview Part of the Jurisprudence Commons, and the Legal Profession Commons Recommended Citation Des Rosiers, Nathalie (2015) "Rights are Not Enough: Therapeutic Jurisprudence Lessons for Law Reformers," Touro Law Review: Vol. 18 : No. 3 , Article 4. Available at: https://digitalcommons.tourolaw.edu/lawreview/vol18/iss3/4 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Digital Commons @ Touro Law Center. It has been accepted for inclusion in Touro Law Review by an authorized editor of Digital Commons @ Touro Law Center. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Rights are Not Enough: Therapeutic Jurisprudence Lessons for Law Reformers Cover Page Footnote 18-3 This article is available in Touro Law Review: https://digitalcommons.tourolaw.edu/lawreview/vol18/iss3/4 Des Rosiers: Rights Are Not Enough RIGHTS ARE NOT ENOUGH: THERAPEUTIC JURISPRUDENCE LESSONS FOR LAW REFORMERS Nathalie Des Rosiers INTRODUCTION Therapeutic jurisprudence is a movement that examines the psychological effects of laws. It attempts to identify whether the law has healing or detrimental effects. 2 Although it is sometimes framed as a descriptive endeavor and a non-normative project, 3 it suggests that we should seek to minimize the detrimental effects of laws and maximize their healing effects. Ultimately, we want laws to do "more good" or, at least, less harm.
    [Show full text]
  • Conference: Rhetoric, Between the Theory and Practice of Politics
    Bobbio: the role of intellectuals and the political discourse in modern democracies Arnaldo M. A. Gonçalves PhD (Catholic University of Portugal) Abstract Noberto Bobbio, the Italian Political Philosopher has devoted several of his most relevant essays of political theory to the role of rhetoric within political discourse. In those texts he has tried to compose a political theory with a much focused philosophical component that he intends to oppose to a global theory of law. Bobbio saw the “Theory of Politics” as an equivalent to Political Philosophy and comprehending the four following disciplinary fields: a) the ideal Republic or a utopian society in the sense that is structured on Plato and on Marx; b) the question of legitimacy in the context of modern politics; c) politics as a sort of human activity independent from others; d) the epistemological dimension of political discourse. For the Italian philosopher only Political Philosophy can fulfil the role of securing a methodological and rhetorical supervision of the political discourse as it responds positively to three requisites: a) it is validated by the praxis of politics; b) pursues the objective to elucidate the facts; c) it is orientated by an ethical vision that has its own values. In Bobbio’s discussion of the role of political discourse in modern politics when the discourse is more scientific, it becomes a theory of persuasion and modelling of the others´ views. When politics is taken as an art it becomes a poetic rhetoric, the art of fine speech. Bobbio asserts a universal dimension to this dual distinction in political rhetoric and defines “regulatory discourse” the poetic and artistic dimension of politics and “descriptive discourse” the one that is considered by him as scientific, as it looks to reflect the practice of political interaction.
    [Show full text]
  • Universidade Federal Da Bahia Faculdade De Filosofia E Ciências Humanas Programa De Pós-Graduação Em Filosofia
    UNIVERSIDADE FEDERAL DA BAHIA FACULDADE DE FILOSOFIA E CIÊNCIAS HUMANAS PROGRAMA DE PÓS-GRADUAÇÃO EM FILOSOFIA PEDRO LINO DE CARVALHO JÚNIOR DIREITO E IMAGINAÇÃO INSTITUCIONAL Salvador, 2017 PEDRO LINO DE CARVALHO JÚNIOR DIREITO E IMAGINAÇÃO INSTITUCIONAL Tese apresentada como requisito parcial à obtenção do grau de Doutor em Filosofia junto ao Programa de Pós-Graduação em Filosofia da Universidade Federal da Bahia - Área de concentração: Filosofia Contemporânea. Linha de pesquisa: Filosofia e Teoria Social. Orientador: Prof. Dr. José Crisóstomo de Souza. Salvador, 2017 TERMO DE APROVAÇÃO PEDRO LINO DE CARVALHO JÚNIOR DIREITO E IMAGINAÇÃO INSTITUCIONAL Tese aprovada como requisito parcial para obtenção do grau de Doutor em Filosofia junto ao Programa de Pós-Graduação em Filosofia da Universidade Federal da Bahia — Área de Concentração - Filosofia Contemporânea. Linha de pesquisa: Filosofia e Teoria Social, pela seguinte banca examinadora: Orientador: ______________________________________ ______________________________________ ______________________________________ ______________________________________ ______________________________________ Salvador, À memória de Morenita Matos de Carvalho. AGRADECIMENTOS Esta pesquisa não resultou tão somente de um esforço individual, mas teve origem, em grande parte, nas significativas contribuições hauridas no espaço público em que se desenvolve a reflexão teórica, em especial a comunidade formada por professores, colegas e alunos, pelo que faço os seguintes registros de agradecimento: A todos os
    [Show full text]
  • Law-As-Action and Integrative Jurisprudence Julius Stone
    Hastings Law Journal Volume 26 | Issue 5 Article 8 1-1975 Law-as-Action and Integrative Jurisprudence Julius Stone Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.uchastings.edu/hastings_law_journal Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Julius Stone, Law-as-Action and Integrative Jurisprudence, 26 Hastings L.J. 1331 (1975). Available at: https://repository.uchastings.edu/hastings_law_journal/vol26/iss5/8 This Note is brought to you for free and open access by the Law Journals at UC Hastings Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Hastings Law Journal by an authorized editor of UC Hastings Scholarship Repository. LAW-AS-ACTION AND INTEGRATIVE JURISPRUDENCEt By JuLIus STONE* FEW exercises are more salutary for the learned than explaining their activities to laymen. What, for example, is jurisprudence? as a radio audience once asked me (I am sure in fullest good faith) in a program allowing sixty seconds for reply. I replied desperately that people who act to interpret or apply the law were lawyers; that those who write or speak about lawyers' activities were jurists; and that those who write or speak about what jurists write or say about law were jurisprudents. The reply made the time-slot, which is, of course, the prime test of good radio. Yet it left out the important genre of which Jerome Hall's Foundations of Jurisprudence is a fine example. For I should really have gone on to say that those who write or speak about what jurisprudents write or say about what jurists write or say about law- yers' activities in interpreting or applying law are also jurisprudents, though of a special kind.
    [Show full text]
  • Law and Morality: a Kantian Perspective
    Columbia Law School Scholarship Archive Faculty Scholarship Faculty Publications 1987 Law and Morality: A Kantian Perspective George P. Fletcher Columbia Law School, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.columbia.edu/faculty_scholarship Part of the Jurisprudence Commons, and the Law and Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation George P. Fletcher, Law and Morality: A Kantian Perspective, 87 COLUM. L. REV. 533 (1987). Available at: https://scholarship.law.columbia.edu/faculty_scholarship/1071 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Publications at Scholarship Archive. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Scholarship by an authorized administrator of Scholarship Archive. For more information, please contact [email protected]. LAW AND MORALITY: A KANTIAN PERSPECTIVE George P. Fletcher* The relationship between law and morality has emerged as the cen- tral question in the jurisprudential reflection of our time. Those who call themselves positivists hold with H.L.A. Hart' that calling a statute or a judicial decision "law" need not carry any implications about the morality of that statute or decision.2 Valid laws might be immoral or unjust. Those who resist this reduction of law to valid enactments sometimes argue, with Lon Fuller, that moral acceptability is a neces- sary condition for holding that a statute is law; 3 or, with Ronald Dworkin, that moral principles supplement valid enactments as compo- 4 nents of the law. Whether the positivists or their "moralist" opponents are right about the nature of law, all seem to agree about the nature of morality. We have to distinguish, it is commonly said, between conventional and critical morality.
    [Show full text]