Topology Proceedings 42 (2013) Pp. 275-297: Wallman Compactifications and Tychonoff's Compactness Theorem in {\Sf

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Topology Proceedings 42 (2013) Pp. 275-297: Wallman Compactifications and Tychonoff's Compactness Theorem in {\Sf Volume 42, 2013 Pages 275–297 http://topology.auburn.edu/tp/ Wallman Compactifications and Tychonoff’s Compactness Theorem in ZF by Kyriakos Keremedis and Eleftherios Tachtsis Electronically published on January 26, 2013 Topology Proceedings Web: http://topology.auburn.edu/tp/ Mail: Topology Proceedings Department of Mathematics & Statistics Auburn University, Alabama 36849, USA E-mail: [email protected] ISSN: 0146-4124 COPYRIGHT ⃝c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved. http://topology.auburn.edu/tp/ TOPOLOGY PROCEEDINGS Volume 42 (2013) Pages 275-297 E-Published on January 26, 2013 WALLMAN COMPACTIFICATIONS AND TYCHONOFF’S COMPACTNESS THEOREM IN ZF KYRIAKOS KEREMEDIS AND ELEFTHERIOS TACHTSIS Abstract. We show that the following statements are pairwise equivalent in ZF: (1) The axiom of choice (AC). (2) For every T1 space (X; T ) and every T1 base C for X, the set W(X; C) of all C-ultrafilters when endowed with the Wallman topology TW(X;C) (definitions are provided in section 1) is a compactification of X. (3) For every T1 space (X; T ), for every T1 base C of X, every filter base G ⊂ C extends to a C-ultrafilter F. (4) “For every T1 space (X; T ), W(X) (here C = K(X), the fam- ily of all closed subsets of X) is a compactification of X” and f 2 g “ForQ every familyQ (Xi;Ti): i ! of compact T1 spaces, W( Xi) and W(Xi) are topologically homeomorphic.” i2! i2! We also show that “ For every T1 space (X; T ), W(X) is a com- pactification of X” implies that every infinite set has a countably infinite subset. In addition, we show that “ For every T1 space (X; T ), W(X) is a compactification of X” if and only if CFE1 (= every filter base G of closed subsets of a T1 space (X; T ) extends to a closed ultrafilter F). 1. Notation and Terminology f 2 g QLet (Xi;Ti): i I be a family of topological spaces and let X = Xi be their Tychonoff product. A closed subset F of X is called basic i2I closed in case [f −1 2 g 2 <! 2 c 2 F = πq (Fq): q Q where Q [I] and for all q Q; Fq Tq: 2010 Mathematics Subject Classification. Primary 03E25; Secondary 03E35, 54B10, 54D30. Key words and phrases. axiom of choice, compactness, closed ultrafilters, Ty- chonoff’s compactness theorem. ⃝c 2013 Topology Proceedings. 275 276 K. KEREMEDIS AND E. TACHTSIS We shall denote the collection of all basic closed subsets of X by C(X). C(X) is a base for the closed subsets of X (every closed subset of X can be expressed as an intersection of members of C(X)). A closed set F of X isQ called restricted closed Qif there is a finite set Q ⊆ I such that F = V × Xi, with V ⊂ YQ = Xi a closed set. Note that for a given i2Qc i2Q restricted closed set F in X, there is not a unique set Q satisfying the aforementioned condition. (Let F , V , and Q be as in the latter definition, j n j ≥ 2 n and (for our convenience)Q suppose that I Q 2 and let i0 I Q. 0 × 0 [ f g 0 × Then F = V Xi, where Q = Q i0 and V = V Xi0 ). i2(Q0)c However, it is fairly easy to see that to every nonempty proper restricted closed subset F of X, there corresponds a finite set QF ⊆ I which is the ⊆-smallest set Q in [I]<! with respect to the above condition on Q. (If F is a nonempty (proper) restricted closed set in X, then the ⊆ ⊆ -smallest set QF I can be definedQ so that there is a closed set VF × \f 2 g in YQF such that F = VF Xi, VF = Zj : j J , where c i2(QF ) [f −1 2 g ⊂ 2 2 Zj = πq (Gqj): q QF YQF and for all q QF , for all j J, c 2 2 2 Gqj Tq, and for each q QF , there exists an index j QJ such that <! Gqj =6 ?;Xq. Then any Q 2 [I] for which F = V × Xi with i2(Q)c V closed in YQ is such that Q ⊇ QF ; recall that V is expressible as an 0 [f −1 0 2 g 2 0 intersection of basic closed subsets Zj = πq (Gqj): q Q , j J , of 2 2 0 0 YQ. Then discard those q Q, each being such that for every j J , Gqj is either empty or all of Xq.) The set QF is called the set of restricted coordinates of F . The collection of all restricted closed subsets of X shall be denoted by CR(X). Clearly, C(X) is closed under finite unions but not closed under finite intersections. However, the collection C(X) consisting in all sets of the form \f[f −1 2 g 2 g (1.1) G = πq (Fqi): q Qi : i n 2 N 2 2 <! 2 c 2 where n and for all i n, Qi [I] , and for all q Qi, Fqi Tq, or, equivalently, Y [f\f 2 g 2 f −1 2 gg (1.2) G = f(i): i n : f πq (Fqi): q Qi , i2n is easily seen to be a base for the closed subsets of X, closed under finite unions and finite intersections. Likewise, CR(X) is a larger base for the closed subsets of X which is also closed under finite unions and finite intersections. WALLMAN COMPACTIFICATIONS AND TYCHONOFF PRODUCTS IN ZF 277 Q For every S ⊂ I, pS : X ! YS = Xi will denote the projection of i2S X onto YS. In particular, if S = fig for some i 2 I, then we will denote the projection pS by πi. C1(X) denotes the collection of all 1-basic closed C f −1 2 c 2 g subsets of X, i.e., 1(X) = πi (F ): i I;F Ti . Let (X; T ) be a topological space. X is compact if every open cover U of X has a finite subcover V. Equivalently, X is compact if and only if for every familyT G of closed subsets of X having the finite intersection property (fip) G 6= ?. Let X be a nonempty set and let E be a collection of subsets of X which is closed under finite intersections. A nonempty subcollection F of E n f?g is an E-filter if and only if (i) if F1, F2 2 F, then F1 \ F2 2 F. (ii) if F 2 F, F 0 2 E and F ⊆ F 0, then F 0 2 F. If E = P(X), then an E-filter is called a filter on X. If E is the collection of all closed subsets of a topological space, then we say that F is a closed filter. A nonempty collection H ⊆ E n f?g is called an E-filter base if, for 2 H 2 H ⊆ \ every H1;H2 , there is an H3 T such that H3 H1 H2. A filter base H ⊆ E n f?g is called free if H = ?. A maximal, with respect to inclusion, E-filter is called an E-ultrafilter. An E-filter F is called countably closed if it satisfies the condition: If fFi : i 2 !g ⊆ F, then \fFi : i 2 !g 2 F. An E-filter F is called countably prime if it satisfies the condition: If fFi : i 2 !g ⊂ E and [fFi : i 2 !g 2 F, then there exists i 2 ! such that Fi 2 F. Let (X; T ) be a T1 space and let B be a base for the closed subsets of X. Then B is called a T 1 base for X if it satisfies the following. (i) ? 2 B. (ii) If B1;B2 2 B, then B1 \ B2 2 B and B1 [ B2 2 B. (iii) If x2 = B 2 B, then there is Bx 2 B such that x 2 Bx and Bx \ B = ?. f 2 g C If (Xi;Ti): i I is a family of T1 topologicalQ spaces, then R(X) and C(X) are T1 bases for the product X = Xi. Note that C(X) is not a i2I T1 base forQX. If X = Xi is a product of topological spaces and F is an E-ultrafilter, i2I where C(X) ⊂ E ⊆ K(X) (= the family of all closed subsets of X), then for every i 2 I; Fi denotes the family of all closed subsets of Xi whose inverse image under πi is a member of F, i.e., F f ⊆ c 2 −1 2 Fg (1.3) i = F Xi : F Ti; πi (F ) . 278 K. KEREMEDIS AND E. TACHTSIS Let (X; T ) be a T1 topological space and let C be a T1 base for X. W(X; C) denotes the set fF ⊂ C : F is a C-ultrafilterg. In particular, for C = K(X), we shall denote W(X; K(X)) by W(X). The topology TW(X;C) on W(X; C), having as a base for the closed sets the family B = fA∗ : A 2 Cg;A∗ = fF 2 W(X; C): A 2 Fg; is called the Wallman topology corresponding to the base C. Since for every A 2 C, (A∗)c = fF 2 W(X; C): 9F 2 F such that F \ A = ?g, it follows that (1.4) U = fU ∗ : U c 2 Cg and U ∗ = fF 2 W(X; C): 9 F 2 F such that F ⊆ Ug is a base for W(X; C).
Recommended publications
  • Nearly Metacompact Spaces
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Elsevier - Publisher Connector Topology and its Applications 98 (1999) 191–201 Nearly metacompact spaces Elise Grabner a;∗, Gary Grabner a, Jerry E. Vaughan b a Department Mathematics, Slippery Rock University, Slippery Rock, PA 16057, USA b Department Mathematics, University of North Carolina at Greensboro, Greensboro, NC 27412, USA Received 28 May 1997; received in revised form 30 December 1997 Abstract A space X is called nearly metacompact (meta-Lindelöf) provided that if U is an open cover of X then there is a dense set D ⊆ X and an open refinement V of U that is point-finite (point-countable) on D: We show that countably compact, nearly meta-Lindelöf T3-spaces are compact. That nearly metacompact radial spaces are meta-Lindelöf. Every space can be embedded as a closed subspace of a nearly metacompact space. We give an example of a countably compact, nearly meta-Lindelöf T2-space that is not compact and a nearly metacompact T2-space which is not irreducible. 1999 Elsevier Science B.V. All rights reserved. Keywords: Metacompact; Nearly metacompact; Irreducible; Countably compact; Radial AMS classification: Primary 54D20, Secondary 54A20; 54D30 A space X is called nearly metacompact (meta-Lindelöf) provided that if U is an open cover of X then there is a dense set D ⊆ X and an open refinement V of U such that Vx DfV 2 V: x 2 V g is finite (countable) for all x 2 D. The class of nearly metacompact spaces was introduced in [8] as a device for constructing a variety of interesting examples of non orthocompact spaces.
    [Show full text]
  • 1. Introduction in a Topological Space, the Closure Is Characterized by the Limits of the Ultrafilters
    Pr´e-Publica¸c˜oes do Departamento de Matem´atica Universidade de Coimbra Preprint Number 08–37 THE ULTRAFILTER CLOSURE IN ZF GONC¸ALO GUTIERRES Abstract: It is well known that, in a topological space, the open sets can be characterized using filter convergence. In ZF (Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory without the Axiom of Choice), we cannot replace filters by ultrafilters. It is proven that the ultrafilter convergence determines the open sets for every topological space if and only if the Ultrafilter Theorem holds. More, we can also prove that the Ultrafilter Theorem is equivalent to the fact that uX = kX for every topological space X, where k is the usual Kuratowski Closure operator and u is the Ultrafilter Closure with uX (A) := {x ∈ X : (∃U ultrafilter in X)[U converges to x and A ∈U]}. However, it is possible to built a topological space X for which uX 6= kX , but the open sets are characterized by the ultrafilter convergence. To do so, it is proved that if every set has a free ultrafilter then the Axiom of Countable Choice holds for families of non-empty finite sets. It is also investigated under which set theoretic conditions the equality u = k is true in some subclasses of topological spaces, such as metric spaces, second countable T0-spaces or {R}. Keywords: Ultrafilter Theorem, Ultrafilter Closure. AMS Subject Classification (2000): 03E25, 54A20. 1. Introduction In a topological space, the closure is characterized by the limits of the ultrafilters. Although, in the absence of the Axiom of Choice, this is not a fact anymore.
    [Show full text]
  • In a Topological Space (X, )
    Separation Suppose that we have a sequence xn in a topological space (X; ). In order to consider the convergencef ofg such a sequence, we considerT the corre- sponding convergence result for a metric space in terms of open sets: namely: A sequence converges to a limit l X if every (open) neighbourhood containing l contains all but a finite number of2 points of the sequence. Consequently, we define convergence in (X; ) by: A sequence converges to a limit l X if everyT open set containing l contains all but a finite number of points of the sequence.2 However, this definition can have some unexpected consequences. If = φ, X , then every sequence in (X; ) converges, and every l X is a limitT of thef sequence.g T 2 Similarly, if we have a sequence in MATH 3402 which converges to an element of S11 (say) then every element of S11 is a limit of the sequence. If we want convergent sequences to have unique limits in X, then we need to impose further restrictions on the topology of X. Basicly the problem arises because there are distinct points x1 and x2 such that every open set containing x1 contains x2. Hence any sequence converging to x2 converges to x1 also. (In the examples above, this works both ways, but this is not necessary. If we consider the set a; b with the topology φ, a ;X , then every open set containing b contains a, butf notg vice-versa.) f f g g This means that x1 is a limit point of the set x2 , and this latter set is not closed.
    [Show full text]
  • Topology: the Journey Into Separation Axioms
    TOPOLOGY: THE JOURNEY INTO SEPARATION AXIOMS VIPUL NAIK Abstract. In this journey, we are going to explore the so called “separation axioms” in greater detail. We shall try to understand how these axioms are affected on going to subspaces, taking products, and looking at small open neighbourhoods. 1. What this journey entails 1.1. Prerequisites. Familiarity with definitions of these basic terms is expected: • Topological space • Open sets, closed sets, and limit points • Basis and subbasis • Continuous function and homeomorphism • Product topology • Subspace topology The target audience for this article are students doing a first course in topology. 1.2. The explicit promise. At the end of this journey, the learner should be able to: • Define the following: T0, T1, T2 (Hausdorff), T3 (regular), T4 (normal) • Understand how these properties are affected on taking subspaces, products and other similar constructions 2. What are separation axioms? 2.1. The idea behind separation. The defining attributes of a topological space (in terms of a family of open subsets) does little to guarantee that the points in the topological space are somehow distinct or far apart. The topological spaces that we would like to study, on the other hand, usually have these two features: • Any two points can be separated, that is, they are, to an extent, far apart. • Every point can be approached very closely from other points, and if we take a sequence of points, they will usually get to cluster around a point. On the face of it, the above two statements do not seem to reconcile each other. In fact, topological spaces become interesting precisely because they are nice in both the above ways.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:Math/9810074V1 [Math.GN] 12 Oct 1998
    Unification approach to the separation axioms between ∗ T0 and completely Hausdorff Francisco G. Arenas,† Julian Dontchev‡and Maria Luz Puertas§ September 19, 2021 Abstract The aim of this paper is to introduce a new weak separation axiom that generalizes the separation properties between T1 and completely Hausdorff. We call a topological space (X,τ) a Tκ,ξ-space if every compact subset of X with cardinality ≤ κ is ξ-closed, where ξ is a general closure operator. We concentrate our attention mostly on two new concepts: kd-spaces and T 1 -spaces. 3 1 Introduction The definitions of most (if not all) weak separation axioms are deceptively simple. However, the structure and the properties of those spaces are not always that easy to comprehend. In this paper we try to unify the separation axioms between T0 and completely Hausdorff by introducing the concept of Tκ,ξ-spaces. We call a topological space (X, τ) a Tκ,ξ-space arXiv:math/9810074v1 [math.GN] 12 Oct 1998 if every compact subset of X with cardinality ≤ κ is ξ-closed where ξ is a given closure operator. With different settings on κ and ξ we derive most of the well-known separation properties ‘in the semi-closed interval [T0, T3)’. We are going to consider not only Kuratowski closure operators but more general closure operators, such as the λ-closure operator [1] for ∗1991 Math. Subject Classification — Primary: 54A05, 54D10; Secondary: 54D30, 54H05. Key words and phrases — θ-closed, δ-closed, Urysohn, zero-open, λ-closed, weakly Hausdorff, T0, T1, com- pletely Hausdorff, kc-space, kd-space, Tκ,λ-space, anti-compact.
    [Show full text]
  • Epireflections in Topological Algebraic Structures
    REFLECTIONS IN TOPOLOGICAL ALGEBRAIC STRUCTURES JULIO HERNANDEZ-ARZUSA´ AND SALVADOR HERNANDEZ´ Abstract. Let C be an epireflective category of Top and let rC be the epireflective functor associated with C. If A denotes a (semi)topological algebraic subcategory of Top, we study when rC (A) is an epireflective subcategory of A. We prove that this is always the case for semi-topological structures and we find some sufficient conditions for topological algebraic structures. We also study when the epireflective functor preserves products, subspaces and other properties. In particular, we solve an open question about the coincidence of epireflections proposed by Echi and Lazaar in [6, Question 1.6] and repeated in [7, Question 1.9]. Finally, we apply our results in different specific topological algebraic structures. 1. Introduction In this paper we deal with some applications of epireflective functors in the inves- tigation of topological algebraic structures. In particular, we are interested in the following question: Let C be an epireflective subcategory of Top (i.e., productive and hereditary, hence containing the 1-point space as the empty product), and let rC be the epireflective functor associated with C. If A denotes a (semi)topological varietal subcategory of Top (that is, a subcategory that is closed under products, subalgebras and homomorphic images), we study when rC(A) is an epireflective subcategory of A. arXiv:1704.01146v2 [math.GN] 20 Nov 2018 From a different viewpoint, this question has attracted the interest of many researchers recently (cf. [18, 21, 22, 24, 25, 26, 27, 30]) and, to some extent, our motivation for Date: November 21, 2018.
    [Show full text]
  • 9. Stronger Separation Axioms
    9. Stronger separation axioms 1 Motivation While studying sequence convergence, we isolated three properties of topological spaces that are called separation axioms or T -axioms. These were called T0 (or Kolmogorov), T1 (or Fre´chet), and T2 (or Hausdorff). To remind you, here are their definitions: Definition 1.1. A topological space (X; T ) is said to be T0 (or much less commonly said to be a Kolmogorov space), if for any pair of distinct points x; y 2 X there is an open set U that contains one of them and not the other. Recall that this property is not very useful. Every space we study in any depth, with the exception of indiscrete spaces, is T0. Definition 1.2. A topological space (X; T ) is said to be T1 if for any pair of distinct points x; y 2 X, there exist open sets U and V such that U contains x but not y, and V contains y but not x. Recall that an equivalent definition of a T1 space is one in which all singletons are closed. In a space with this property, constant sequences converge only to their constant values (which need not be true in a space that is not T1|this property is actually equivalent to being T1). Definition 1.3. A topological space (X; T ) is said to be T2, or more commonly said to be a Hausdorff space, if for every pair of distinct points x; y 2 X, there exist disjoint open sets U and V such that x 2 U and y 2 V .
    [Show full text]
  • Theorem: Let X Be a Topological Space, and Let a Be a Subset of X Then a Is Closed Iff D(A) A
    1 Metric Space: Open sets: Let (X,d) be a metric space . A subset G of X is said to be d-open iff to each x G there exist r >o such that S(x,r) G. n + Def : Let (X,d) be a metric space, and let xо X if r R then the set {x X; d(x,xо)< r} is called an open sphere (or open ball).the point xо is called the center and r the radius of the sphere. and we denoted by S(xо,r) or by B(xо,r): i.e. S(xо,r)={ xо X; d(x,xо)< r} Closed set is define and denoted by S[xо,r]={ xо X; d(x,xо)≤ r}. Ex: Let x R then a subset N of R is U nbd of x iff there exist a u-open set G such that xG N , but G is U-open and x G implies that there exist an >0 such that (x-,x+) G. Thus N is a U-nbd of x if N contains an open interval (x-,x+) for some >0. In particular every open interval containing x is a nbd of x. Ex: Consider the set R of all real numbers with usual metric space d(x,y) = x y and find whether or not the following sets are open. A= (0,1) ,B=[0,1), C= (0,1] ,D=[0,1], E= (0,1) (2,3) , F={1}, G={1,2,3} . Soln : A is open set Let x be appoint in A, we take r=min{x-0,1-x}, then it is evident that (x-r, x+r) A 1 1 1 3 For example consider 4 (0,1), then r=min{ 4 -0,1- 4 }=min{ , 4 }= 1 ( - , + ) =(0, 2 ) (0,1)=A.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:1910.09186V1
    ON κ-BOUNDED AND M-COMPACT REFLECTIONS OF TOPOLOGICAL SPACES TARAS BANAKH Abstract. For a topological space X its reflection in a class T of topological spaces is a pair (TX,iX ) consisting of a space TX ∈ T and continuous map iX : X → TX such that for any continuous map f : X → Y to a space Y ∈ T there exists a unique continuous map f¯ : TX → Y such that f = f¯ ◦ iX . In this paper for an infinite cardinal κ and a nonempty set M of ultrafilters on κ, we study the reflections of topological spaces in the classes Hκ of κ-bounded Hausdorff spaces and HM of M-compact Hausdorff spaces (a topological space X is κ-bounded if the closures of subsets of cardinality ≤ κ in X are compact; X is M-compact if any function x : κ → X has a p-limit in M for every ultrafilter p ∈ M). 1. Introduction In this paper we shall describe the structure of reflections of topological spaces in some classes of Hausdorff compact-like spaces. By a reflection of a topological space X in a class T of topological spaces we understand a pair (TX,iX ) consisting of a space TX ∈ T and a continuous map iX : X → TX such that for any continuous map f : X → Y to a topological space Y ∈ T there exists a unique continuous map f¯ : TX → Y such that f = f¯◦ iX . The pair (TX,iX ) is called a T-reflection of X. The reflection (βX,iX ) of a topological space X in the class β of compact Hausdorff spaces is known in General Topology [2, §3.6] as the Stone-Cechˇ compactification of X.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:1906.00185V3
    EMBEDDING TOPOLOGICAL SPACES INTO HAUSDORFF κ-BOUNDED SPACES TARAS BANAKH, SERHII BARDYLA, AND ALEX RAVSKY Abstract. Let κ be an infinite cardinal. A topological space X is κ-bounded if the closure of any subset of cardinality ≤ κ in X is compact. We discuss the problem of embeddability of topological spaces into Hausdorff (Urysohn, regular) κ-bounded spaces, and present a canonical construction of such an embedding. Also we construct a (consistent) example of a sequentially compact separable regular space that cannot be embedded into a Hausdorff ω-bounded space. 1. Introduction It is well-known that a topological space X is homeomorphic to a subspace of a compact Hausdorff space if and only if the space X is Tychonoff. In this paper we address the problem of characterization of topological spaces that embed into Hausdorff (Urysohn, regular, resp.) spaces possessing some weaker compactness properties. One of such properties is the κ-boundedness, i.e., the compactness of closures of subsets of cardinality κ. It is clear that each compact space is κ-bounded for any cardinal κ. Any ordinal α := [0, α) of≤ cofinality cf(α) >κ, endowed with the order topology, is κ-bounded but not compact. More information on κ-bounded spaces can be found in [9], [10], [13]. Embedding of topological spaces into compact-like spaces were also investigated in [1, 2, 5, 6]. In this paper we discuss the following: Problem 1.1. Which topological spaces are homeomorphic to subspaces of κ-bounded Hausdorff (Urysohn, regular) spaces? In Theorem 3.4 (and Theorem 3.5) we shall prove that the necessary and sufficient conditions of embeddability of a T1-space X into a Hausdorff (Urysohn) κ-bounded space are the (strong) κ-regularity and the (strong) κ-normality of X, respectively.
    [Show full text]
  • Separation Axioms Between T0 and T1
    MATHEMATICS SEPARATION AXIOMS BETWEEN To AND T1 BY C. E. AULL AND W. J. THRON (Communicated by Prof. H. FREUDENTHAL at the meeting of September 30, 1961) l. Introduction. The first systematic treatment of separation axioms is due to URYSOHN [7]. A more detailed discussion was given by FREUDENTHAL and VAN EsT [2] in 1951. Both of these investigations are concerned with separation axioms stronger than T 1. The only separation axiom between To and T1 known heretofore was introduced by J. W. T. YouNGS [9] who encountered it in the study of locally connected spaces. Another axiom was suggested to us by an observation of C. T. YANG (see [4, p. 56]) that the derived set of every set is closed iff the derived set of every point is closed. After introducing some tools which will play an important role through­ out the article, we use these to give a new proof of a result of M. H. STONE [6] which states that by identifying "undistinguishable" points in a topological space every space can be made into a To-space. Next, we introduce a number of new separation axioms, giving equivalent forms for some, analyse their inclusion relations, and observe that they all can be described in terms of the behavior of derived sets of points. In the remaining sections some applications are considered. These include consideration of homogeneity, normality, behavior under a strengthening of the topology, and relation to discrete spaces of Alexandroff. We employ the terminology and notation used by KELLEY [4]. By a degenerate set we shall mean a set which contains at most one point.
    [Show full text]
  • Math 730 Homework 14
    Math 730 Homework 14 Austin Mohr November 24, 2009 1 Problem 13D3 n For a polynomial P in n real variables, let Z(P ) = f(x1; : : : ; xn) 2 R j P (x1; : : : ; xn) = 0g. Let P be the collection of all such polynomials. Definition 1.1. The Zariski topology on Rn is the one having the set fZ(P ) j P 2 Pg as a base for its closed sets. Proposition 1.2. On R, the Zariski topology coincides with the cofinite topology. Proof. Let FZ denote the closed sets in the Zariski topology and let Fco denote the closed sets in the cofinite topology. We show that FZ = Fco. T Let F 2 FZ . Observe that F = Z(Pα) for some subfamily fPαg ⊂ P. If the subfamily is merely the zero polynomial, then every real number is a root, and so F = R, which belongs to Fco. Otherwise, the number of roots of each polynomial is finite, and so the intersection of these sets of roots is finite. Hence, F is finite, and so F 2 Fco. Let F 2 Fco. If F = R, then F corresponds to the set of roots the zero polynomial. If F = ;, then F corresponds to the set of roots of a nonzero, constant polynomial. Otherwise, Q construct the polynomial P (x) = a2F (x−a) (since F is finite, this is indeed a polynomial). We see that F corresponds to the set of roots of the polynomial P . In any case, we conclude that F 2 FZ . Proposition 1.3. On Rn with n ≥ 2, the Zariski topology does not coincide with the cofinite topology.
    [Show full text]