Democracy and Distrust. by John Hart Ely Andrew L

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Democracy and Distrust. by John Hart Ely Andrew L Hofstra Law Review Volume 9 | Issue 3 Article 6 1981 Democracy and Distrust. By John Hart Ely Andrew L. Kaufman Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarlycommons.law.hofstra.edu/hlr Recommended Citation Kaufman, Andrew L. (1981) "Democracy and Distrust. By John Hart Ely," Hofstra Law Review: Vol. 9: Iss. 3, Article 6. Available at: http://scholarlycommons.law.hofstra.edu/hlr/vol9/iss3/6 This document is brought to you for free and open access by Scholarly Commons at Hofstra Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in Hofstra Law Review by an authorized administrator of Scholarly Commons at Hofstra Law. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Kaufman: Democracy and Distrust. By John Hart Ely BOOK REVIEW DEMOCRACY AND DISTRUST. By JOHN HART ELY.* Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1980. Pp. viii, 261. $15.00. Andrew L. Kaufman** My opinion of John Ely's new book, Democracy and Distrust, is revealed by the fact that I agreed to write this review. I do not ordinarily review books by friends or colleagues; criticism would be indelicate and praise suspect. Ely's book is so wonderful and so im- portant and it issues such a challenge to scholarly debate that I have made an exception. This is the rare book that lives up to its dust-cover raves. It must be read by anyone who has any interest in the role of courts in our constitutional scheme. And it can be read easily. Ely is that rare modem legal scholar who knows how to present the most subtle and complex thought in simple English, with charm and often with humor. Beg, borrow, or better yet buy this book, for you will want to have it in your library. The subject is timeless. The book has several major themes. It begins with a discus- sion of the major alternative views of the appropriate method of constitutional adjudication. Ely uses the currently popular labels of interpretivism and noninterpretivism: the former indicating that judges deciding constitutional issues should confine themselves to enforcing norms that are stated or clearly implicit in the written Constitution, the latter the con- trary view that courts should go beyond that set of references and enforce norms that cannot be discovered within the four cor- ners of the document.1 Addressing interpretivism first, Ely points to its obvious at- tractions. Our usual conception of a court's role in interpreting a * Professor of Law, Harvard University. ** Professor of Law, Harvard University,A.B., 1951, LL.B. 1954, Harvard Uni- versity. 1. J. ELY, DEMOCRACY AND DISTRUST 1 (1980) (footnote omitted) (citing Grey, Do We Have an Unwritten Constitution?, 27 STAN. L. REV. 703 (1975)). Published by Scholarly Commons at Hofstra Law, 1981 1 Hofstra Law Review, Vol. 9, Iss. 3 [1981], Art. 6 HOFSTRA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 9:1111 writing is that it limits itself to the express or implicit purposes of the language. Any other theory has enormous difficulty "'reconcil[ing] itself with the underlying democratic theory of our government." 2 He distinguishes two kinds of interpretivism. The first is a "clause bound" interpretivism that seeks to interpret a constitutional provision on the basis of its language and any rele- vant legislative history. The second is a broad form of interpre- tivism proceeding from a realization that a more open-ended constitutional provision cannot be sensibly interpreted solely on the basis of its language and legislative history, and so looks be- yond these criteria. It derives meaning, however, from "general themes of the entire constitutional document and not from some source entirely beyond its four corners." 3 I am sure that no one will accuse me of the premature revelation that "the butler did it" if I say that a broad-form, process-oriented interpretivism is Ely's choice. First, however, Ely demolishes the contenders. Clause-bound interpretivism is easy. Moving from the somewhat open-textured provisions of the Constitution, such as the first and eighth amend- ments, to the extremely open-ended equal protection clause, privi- leges or immunities clause, and ninth amendment,4 Ely demon- strates quite persuasively that these important provisions cannot sensibly be interpreted within their four corners. While their lan- guage and history indicate general concerns, their more specific contents are simply not apparent. I am delighted to see the power- ful support he gives to arguments for a major substantive role for both the privileges or immunities clause and the ninth amend- ment,5 for I have long thought that they were the appropriate um- 2. Id. at 4. 3. Id. at 12. 4. Ely argues that the privileges or immunities clause and the ninth amend- ment, and not the due process clause, should have been the vehicles for considera- tion of constitutional issues, other than those relating to fair procedures, that are not specifically dealt with elsewhere in the Constitution. Id. at 22-41. His argument, based on the language and history of the ninth and fourteenth amendments, is quite powerful, except that it becomes marred to some extent by his rather expansive no- tions of process. His argument is not made for the esthetic purpose of tidying up the Court's his- torically muddled treament of the fourteenth amendment. Ely sees the Court's fal- tering protection of so-called "procedural" due process in Paul v. Davis, 424 U.S. 693 (1976), and its progeny as attributable, at least in part, to its fear of the unconfined nature of the due process clause after "substantive" due process was re- invigorated. J. ELY, supra note 1, at 19. 5. J. ELY, supra note 1, at 22-30, 34-41. Ely quotes with approval Justice http://scholarlycommons.law.hofstra.edu/hlr/vol9/iss3/6 2 Kaufman: Democracy and Distrust. By John Hart Ely 1981] BOOK REVIEW brellas under which much of substantive due process should have been sheltered. Ely's demonstration of the "impossibility of a clause-bound interpretivism" ends on a curious note that sets the tone for the rest of the book. He states: "If a principled approach to judicial en- forcement of the Constitution's open-ended provisions cannot be developed, one that is not hopelessly inconsistent with our nation's commitment to representative democracy, responsible commenta- tors must consider seriously the possibility that courts simply should stay away from them." 6 There are, of course, other possibil- ities. If there is a clash between the words of the open-ended pro- visions and some theory of "representative democracy," Ely's com- mon sense insistence that we focus heavily on the words of the document points to the conclusion that the words should prevail. After all, "representative democracy" is not constitutional language. Any potential theory of "democracy" that is to be given constitu- tional status by inference should be inferred from all the provisions of the Constitution, including the very important open-ended pro- visions. Such a prospect might cause one with Ely's concerns to reexamine the institution of judicial review itself. Short of that, however, a new amendment-e.g., the fourteenth amendment- ought not to be viewed as judicially unenforceable because judges or scholars think its judicial enforcement to be inconsistent with their view of "our representative democracy." That would be the height of anti-constitutionalism. Ely does not pursue this hypothetical problem. Instead, he next considers an alternative theory of constitutional adjudication, noninterpretivism, by which the content of open-ended constitu- tional clauses is provided by identifying those principles that seem "fundamental" at any given time. He identifies several method- ologies for selecting those principles: The judge's own values, natu- Field's dissent in the Slaughter-House Cases, 83 U.S. (16 Wall.) 36 (1872), which ob- served that if the privileges or immunities clause only refers, as held by the majority of the court in their opinion, to such privileges and immunities as were before its adoption specially designated in the Constitution or necessarily implied as belonging to citizens of the United States, it was a vain and idle enactment, which accomplished noth- ing, and most unnecessarily excited Congress and the people on its passage. Id. at 96 (Field, J., dissenting), quoted in J. ELY, supra, at 22. As to the ninth amend- ment, Ely's point is simply that to reject its open-textured provision of rights and yet accept substantive interpretations of the due process clause "puts the world exactly upside down .... for whereas the Due Process Clause speaks of process, the Ninth Amendment refers to unenumerated rights." J. ELY, supra note 1, at 34. 6. J. ELY, supra note 1, at 41. Published by Scholarly Commons at Hofstra Law, 1981 3 Hofstra Law Review, Vol. 9, Iss. 3 [1981], Art. 6 HOFSTRA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 9:1111 ral law, neutral principles, reason, tradition, consensus, and pre- dicting progress. The judge's own values7 is Ely's bugaboo for, although that methodology is seldom advocated openly, he believes that judges who adopt the noninterpretivist position often reach decisions based simply on their own values. Natural law8 is quickly dismissed as either providing such general or abstract principles as to be useless in adjudication or as losing its universality if specific content is sought. Herbert Wechsler's neutral principles9 also fail the test because they "do not provide a source of substantive con- tent."10 Reason, 1" that is, moral reasoning, also fails because it pro- vides too much substantive content. One person's moral right is so often another's moral wrong. Tradition 12 has a similar problem: Whose tradition? Moreover, tradition, which is backward looking, seems an odd source of values for an open-ended provision capable of growth.
Recommended publications
  • John Hart Ely's "Invitation"
    Indiana Law Journal Volume 54 Issue 2 Article 5 Winter 1979 Government by Judiciary: John Hart Ely's "Invitation" Raoul Berger Member, Illinois and District of Columbia bars Follow this and additional works at: https://www.repository.law.indiana.edu/ilj Part of the Courts Commons, Fourteenth Amendment Commons, and the Judges Commons Recommended Citation Berger, Raoul (1979) "Government by Judiciary: John Hart Ely's "Invitation"," Indiana Law Journal: Vol. 54 : Iss. 2 , Article 5. Available at: https://www.repository.law.indiana.edu/ilj/vol54/iss2/5 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Law School Journals at Digital Repository @ Maurer Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in Indiana Law Journal by an authorized editor of Digital Repository @ Maurer Law. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Government by Judiciary: John Hart Ely's "Invitation" RAOUL BERGER* Professor John Hart Ely's Constitutional Interpretivism: Its Allure and Impossibility' solves the problem of government by judiciary quite simply: the framers of the Fourteenth Amendment issued an "open and across-the-board invitation to import into the constitutional decision pro- cess considerations that will not be found in the amendment nor even, at least in any obvious sense, elsewhere in the Constitution. ' 2 This but rephrases the current view, framed to rationalize the Warren Court's revolution, that the "general" terms of the amendment were left open- 3 ended to leave room for such discretion. By impossible "interpretivism" Ely refers to the belief that constitu- tional decisions should be derived from values "very clearly implicit in the written Constitution"; he labels as "non-interpretivism" the view that courts must range beyond those values to "norms that cannot be discovered within the four corners of the document."'4 But unlike most of his confreres, Ely insists that a constitutional decision must be rooted in the Constitution,5 though he does not explain how extra-constitutional factors can be so rooted.
    [Show full text]
  • The Political Process, Equal Protection, and Substantive Due Process
    ARTICLES THE POLITICAL PROCESS, EQUAL PROTECTION, AND SUBSTANTIVE DUE PROCESS Jesse H. Choper* Stephen F. Ross** ABSTRACT In its landmark decision in Carolene Products, the Supreme Court crafted a uniquely American solution to the counter-majoritarian dilemma present in any constitutional democracy: when unelected judges should substantively review policy choices made by elected legislators and executives. The political process theory underlying that decision is that a court with a history of decisions based on judicial ideology should limit close review of government actions to three situations: (1) when the action contravenes a specific provision of the Bill of Rights, (2) when the action threatens to improperly limit the political process, or (3) with regard to the broadly worded Due Process and Equal Protection Clauses, when courts determine that the political process does not work normally. The Supreme Court has not faithfully implemented this approach over the years. However, neither Justices nor commentators have developed a superior alternative approach. We believe that most Americans ought to prefer a return to Carolene Products, as superior (either philosophically or because of risk aversion) to leaving important constitutional precedents subject to the vagaries of highly partisan politics. Our approach builds upon insights of Justices Harlan Fiske Stone, Robert Jackson, and Thurgood Marshall. First, courts should consider challenges initially under the Equal Protection Clause. Second, the category of cases warranting heightened judicial scrutiny should be expanded to include those in which claimants can prove that they are excluded from the Madisonian factional “wheeling and dealing” that characterizes ordinary politics. Third, substantive due process claims should remain available, but only where claimants can demonstrate that animus or prejudice precludes their ability to use the political process to redress their grievances.
    [Show full text]
  • A Review of John Hart Ely's on Constitutional Ground John D
    Notre Dame Law Review Volume 73 | Issue 1 Article 23 6-1-1999 Living the American Dream: A Review of John Hart Ely's On Constitutional Ground John D. Feerick Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.nd.edu/ndlr Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation John D. Feerick, Living the American Dream: A Review of John Hart Ely's On Constitutional Ground, 73 Notre Dame L. Rev. 213 (1997). Available at: http://scholarship.law.nd.edu/ndlr/vol73/iss1/23 This Book Review is brought to you for free and open access by NDLScholarship. It has been accepted for inclusion in Notre Dame Law Review by an authorized administrator of NDLScholarship. For more information, please contact [email protected]. BOOK REVIEWS LIVING THE AMERICAN DREAM: A REVIEW OF JOHN HART ELY'S ON CONSTITUTIONAL GROUND John D. Feerick* I was privileged to be asked by the editors of the Notre Dame Law Review to review Professor John Hart Ely's book, On Constitutional Ground.' I was surprised by the invitation, however, since I have not been actively engaged in the discussions of the academy on the role of the Supreme Court, or more precisely, what theory of constitutional interpretation should be used by the Court in discharging its review- ing function. I confess that I initially thought the invitation was in- tended for one of the several constitutional law theorists on my school's faculty. When I realized that I did not have an "out" on this ground, I concluded that I had little choice but to take on the chal- lenge of reviewing this book by one of the formidable constitutional theorists of this century.
    [Show full text]
  • Notes a Political Process Theory of Judicial Review Under the Religion
    NOTES A POLITICAL PROCESS THEORY OF JUDICIAL REVIEW UNDER THE RELIGION CLAUSES CARLTON MORSE∗ “[One] explanation for the Court’s deviation from political process theory inheres in another quasi-psychological need that has manifested itself in constitutional law since at least Marbury v. Madison: the notion that the legal system should provide remedies for all serious wrongs. The problem with this expectation in the constitutional law context is that it ignores the relative institutional competencies that should inform judicial review.”1 “[I]nstitutions of religion should be unfettered to make their maximum contribution to the public interest.”2 TABLE OF CONTENTS I. INTRODUCTION.................................................................................795 II. JOHN HART ELY’S PARTICIPATION-ORIENTED, REPRESENTATION-REINFORCING THEORY OF JUDICIAL REVIEW......................................................................800 ∗ Class of 2007, University of Southern California Gould School of Law; B.A. 2003, Azusa Pacific University. This note is dedicated to my parents, David and Muriel Morse, for their faithful attention to the wisdom of Proverbs 22:6. I owe sincere thanks to Professor Nomi Stolzenberg for her fine teaching, invaluable insights, and generous encouragement throughout this project. I am also indebted to Professors Danielle Keats Citron and Peter Danchin for helpful comments on earlier drafts. 1. Michael J. Klarman, The Puzzling Resistance to Political Process Theory, 77 VA. L. REV. 747, 824 (1991) (footnotes omitted). 2. PETER L. BERGER & RICHARD JOHN NEUHAUS, TO EMPOWER PEOPLE: THE ROLE OF MEDIATING STRUCTURES IN PUBLIC POLICY 33 (1977). 793 794 SOUTHERN CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 80:793 III. PROCESS THEORY AND RELIGION TODAY: A DIAGNOSIS WITHOUT A CURE................................................804 A. SUFFERING JUDICIAL PREPOSSESSIONS: TODAY’S SUBSTANTIVE RELIGION CLAUSE JURISPRUDENCE.................806 B.
    [Show full text]
  • The Right Stuff
    University of Miami Law Review Volume 58 Number 4 Article 7 7-1-2004 The Right Stuff Harold Hongju Koh Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.law.miami.edu/umlr Recommended Citation Harold Hongju Koh, The Right Stuff, 58 U. Miami L. Rev. 969 (2004) Available at: https://repository.law.miami.edu/umlr/vol58/iss4/7 This A Tribute to John Hart Ely is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at University of Miami School of Law Institutional Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in University of Miami Law Review by an authorized editor of University of Miami School of Law Institutional Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Right Stuff HAROLD HONGJU KOH* "You don't need many heroes if you choose carefully." With that dedication to Earl Warren, John Hart Ely began Democracy and Dis- trust,' and with that dedication to John Hart Ely, I begin this tribute. John was my teacher long before he was my friend. I really met him twice, at very different times in my life. I met him first, in print, 27 years ago, when I was a first-year student at Harvard Law School. It was mid-December and I was struggling to understand the doctrine of Erie R.R. Co. v. Tompkins,2 and how it applied to a case called Hanna v. Plumer.3 After looking at a few turgid hornbooks, and wondering why on Earth I was in law school, I ran across an article in the Harvard Law Review called "The Irrepressible Myth of Erie."'4 "The ones I feel sorry for," John confided, "are the people who bought the federal evidence tapes." And with those words I was hooked.
    [Show full text]
  • Flag Desecration" Under the First Amendment Mohammed Saif-Alden Wattad
    Barry Law Review Volume 17 Article 1 Issue 2 Spring 2012 2012 John Hart Ely: An Influential Constitutional Scholar—Protecting "Flag Desecration" under the First Amendment Mohammed Saif-Alden Wattad Follow this and additional works at: https://lawpublications.barry.edu/barrylrev Part of the Constitutional Law Commons, and the First Amendment Commons Recommended Citation Mohammed Saif-Alden Wattad (2012) "John Hart Ely: An Influential Constitutional Scholar—Protecting "Flag Desecration" under the First Amendment," Barry Law Review: Vol. 17 : Iss. 2 , Article 1. Available at: https://lawpublications.barry.edu/barrylrev/vol17/iss2/1 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Digital Commons @ Barry Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in Barry Law Review by an authorized editor of Digital Commons @ Barry Law. : John Hart Ely: Protecting "Flag Desecration" JOHN HART ELY: AN INFLUENTIAL CONSTITUTIONAL SCHOLAR- PROTECTING "FLAG DESECRATION" UNDER THE FIRST AMENDMENT* Mohammed Saif-Alden Wattad ** I. INTRODUCTION He was the leading constitutional law expert of his time; a superb scholar and an even more superb individual.' The principle scholarly work of American legal academics is the production of articles in law reviews and other periodicals.2 Legal scholarship, however, has become a vast enterprise in the American legal system. Despite the extraordinary level of production and immense influence, both on courts and other scholars, legal education continues to pretend that the two important branches of the system are solely legislation and appellate opinions. A quick glimpse at the American legal system, including case law, makes it clear that the above-mentioned imbalance is incorrect.
    [Show full text]
  • Representation Reinforcement Revisited: Citizens United and Political Process Theory
    REPRESENTATION REINFORCEMENT REVISITED: CITIZENS UNITED AND POLITICAL PROCESS THEORY Evan Barret Smith† INTRODUCTION The perennial presence of campaign-finance and campaign-speech cases on the Supreme Court’s docket reflects a doctrine that even experts in political law consider incoherent.1 The public debate since Citizens United v. Federal Election Commission2 highlights the need for a sound theory of the judicial role in regulation of the political process. A starting point is John Hart Ely’s influential theory of constitutional interpretation, “representation reinforcement,” which focuses judges on failures in the democratic process.3 This Article provides the first thorough analysis of how Ely would view Citizens United. Ely did not address campaign-speech restrictions, and it is debatable how process theory should handle Citizens United, a hard case with arguments on both sides about reinforcing democracy. This Article applies Ely’s theory of constitutional interpretation to Citizens United by analyzing what Ely explicitly said as well as what he implicitly assumed. It finds that Ely would side with the majority in Citizens United, but that a deconstruction of Ely’s main work, Democracy and Distrust, reveals more about the substantive judgments—namely, his distrust of judges—that entered Ely’s ostensibly process-based theory than it does about the way a process-based theory must handle campaign speech. This Article argues that critics of Citizens United should recognize the appeal of Democracy and Distrust and reformulate a representation- reinforcement theory of constitutional interpretation that trusts judges and legislators to regulate the political process and protect democracy. This Article fills a number of important gaps in the existing literature.
    [Show full text]
  • Lawyerord SPRING 2004
    stanfLawyerord SPRING 2004 Anthony Romero ’90 has persuaded thousands of people that it’s patriotic to join the ACLU. Who’s Un-American? stanfLawyerord Issue 68 / Vol. 38 / No. 2 Editor JONATHAN RABINOVITZ Communications Director ANN DETHLEFSEN (BA ’81, MA ’83) [email protected] Art Director ROBIN WEISS [email protected] Production Coordinator LINDA WILSON [email protected] Copy Editor DEBORAH FIFE Contributing Editors MANDY ERICKSON JUDITH ROMERO [email protected] Class Correspondents 61 RESOURCEFUL ALUMNI Editorial Interns LIEF N. HANIFORD (BA ’03, MA ’04) JOSEPHINE LAU (BA ’03, MA ’04) CHRISTINE LIYANTO (BA ’05) Production Associates JOANNA MCCLEAN ON THE DOCKET MARCH ROBERT MARY ANN RUNDELL Stanford Lawyer Upcoming Law School events* (ISSN 0585-0576) is published for alumni and friends of Stanford Law School. Battle of the Brains: Mar. 12 Fiduciary College: May 20–21 Correspondence and A Jeopardy-like contest among http://www.fiduciarycollege.com information should be sent to faculty and students sponsored Editor, Stanford Lawyer Stanford Law School annually by the Stanford Law Directors’ College: June 20–22 Crown Quadrangle Students Association. This year’s http://www.directorscollege.com 559 Nathan Abbott Way Stanford, CA 94305-8610 master of ceremonies: Ben Stein. or to: Best Practices in Marketing Software [email protected] Bringing Africa to the Forefront: and Other Content to the World over Changes of address should be sent to: Contemporary and International the Internet: June 25 [email protected] Law and Development in “Africa’s http://www.law.stanford.edu/ Copyright 2004 by the Board of Trustees Century”: Mar.
    [Show full text]
  • Originalism's Claims and Their Implications
    Arkansas Law Review Volume 70 | Number 4 Article 5 January 2018 Originalism’s Claims and Their mplicI ations André LeDuc Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarworks.uark.edu/alr Part of the Constitutional Law Commons Recommended Citation André LeDuc, Originalism’s Claims and Their Implications, 70 Ark. L. Rev. 1007 (2018). Available at: http://scholarworks.uark.edu/alr/vol70/iss4/5 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by ScholarWorks@UARK. It has been accepted for inclusion in Arkansas Law Review by an authorized editor of ScholarWorks@UARK. For more information, please contact [email protected], [email protected]. ORIGINALISM’S CLAIMS AND THEIR IMPLICATIONS André LeDuc* In this article I explore six of the most fundamental disagreements between originalism and its critics over originalism’s implications. These implications—and the implications of the critics’ alternatives—figure prominently in the arguments advanced in the debate. Reconstructing these arguments in their strongest possible form permits the confusion and misdirection in the debate over originalism to emerge. First, originalism argues that it best comports with our republican democracy. Judicial review, performed by unelected judges with lifetime appointments, may appear inconsistent with the fundamental principles of our democratic republic. Originalism argues that deference to the original understandings or expectations with respect to the Constitution answers this challenge. The critics offer three principal replies to that claim. First, the originalist strategy of finding the original understanding and intentions with respect to the Constitution is rejected as undoable. Second, even if and to the extent that such intentions and understandings existed, the originalist project of finding meaning is rejected as blinkered and mechanical.
    [Show full text]
  • View, and Includes This Provision in the Copyright Notice
    \\jciprod01\productn\N\NDL\89-5\NDL506.txt unknown Seq: 1 27-MAY-14 12:57 THE FORMER CLERKS WHO NEARLY KILLED JUDICIAL RESTRAINT Brad Snyder * ABSTRACT Richard Posner wrote that the theory of judicial restraint is dead and that the liberal deci- sions of the Warren Court killed it. Posner should have placed some of the blame on himself and other former Warren Court and early Burger Court clerks who joined the legal academy. As young law professors, they rejected legal process theory that they had learned in law school from Henry Hart and Albert Sacks at Harvard, Alexander Bickel and Harry Wellington at Yale, and from process theory’s patron saints on the Court—Felix Frankfurter and John M. Harlan. Legal process theory yielded to new theories, including rights protection (John Hart Ely and Owen Fiss), Critical Legal Studies (Duncan Kennedy and Mark Tushnet), and law and economics (Richard Posner and Guido Calabresi). This symposium piece explores the rise and fall of legal process theory as well as the scholar- ship of former Warren Court and early Burger Court clerks who nearly killed it. It also suggests that there could be a revival of a process-based judicial restraint based on a new generation of late Burger Court/early Rehnquist Court clerks-turned-academics who came of age during the mid- 1980s. These law clerks rejected judicial supremacy and adopted popular constitutionalism and other democratic approaches to constitutional interpretation. Popular constitutionalism is inspired by the same faith in the democratic political process as the judicial restraint advocated by James Bradley Thayer, Felix Frankfurter, and Alexander Bickel.
    [Show full text]
  • The Former Clerks Who Nearly Killed Judicial Restraint
    Notre Dame Law Review Volume 89 | Issue 5 Article 6 5-2014 The orF mer Clerks Who Nearly Killed Judicial Restraint Brad Snyder University of Wisconsin Law School, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.nd.edu/ndlr Part of the Constitutional Law Commons Recommended Citation 89 Notre Dame L. Rev. 2129 (2014). This Article is brought to you for free and open access by NDLScholarship. It has been accepted for inclusion in Notre Dame Law Review by an authorized administrator of NDLScholarship. For more information, please contact [email protected]. \\jciprod01\productn\N\NDL\89-5\NDL506.txt unknown Seq: 1 27-MAY-14 12:57 THE FORMER CLERKS WHO NEARLY KILLED JUDICIAL RESTRAINT Brad Snyder * ABSTRACT Richard Posner wrote that the theory of judicial restraint is dead and that the liberal deci- sions of the Warren Court killed it. Posner should have placed some of the blame on himself and other former Warren Court and early Burger Court clerks who joined the legal academy. As young law professors, they rejected legal process theory that they had learned in law school from Henry Hart and Albert Sacks at Harvard, Alexander Bickel and Harry Wellington at Yale, and from process theory’s patron saints on the Court—Felix Frankfurter and John M. Harlan. Legal process theory yielded to new theories, including rights protection (John Hart Ely and Owen Fiss), Critical Legal Studies (Duncan Kennedy and Mark Tushnet), and law and economics (Richard Posner and Guido Calabresi). This symposium piece explores the rise and fall of legal process theory as well as the scholar- ship of former Warren Court and early Burger Court clerks who nearly killed it.
    [Show full text]
  • Louis Lusky and John Hart Ely Vs. Harlan Fiske Stone
    University of Minnesota Law School Scholarship Repository Constitutional Commentary 1995 The aC rolene Products Footnote and the Preferred Position of Individual Rights: Louis Lusky and John Hart Ely Vs. Harlan Fiske Stone. Peter Linzer Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.umn.edu/concomm Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Linzer, Peter, "The aC rolene Products Footnote and the Preferred Position of Individual Rights: Louis Lusky and John Hart Ely Vs. Harlan Fiske Stone." (1995). Constitutional Commentary. 844. https://scholarship.law.umn.edu/concomm/844 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the University of Minnesota Law School. It has been accepted for inclusion in Constitutional Commentary collection by an authorized administrator of the Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE CAROLENE PRODUCTS FOOTNOTE AND THE PREFERRED POSITION OF INDIVIDUAL RIGHTS: LOUIS LUSKY AND JOHN HART ELY vs. HARLAN FISKE STONE Peter Linzer* We see no reason why the Takings Clause of the Fifth Amend­ ment, as much a part of the Bill of Rights as the First Amend­ ment or Fourth Amendment, should be relegated to the status of a poor relation .... Rehnquist, CJ., for the majority in Dolan v. City of Tigard, 114 S. Ct. 2309, 2320 (1994) Footnote four to Carolene Products v. United Statesl is the most famous footnote in constitutional law.z Since its appear­ ance in Justice Harlan Fiske Stone's 1938 opinion for the Supreme Court, its meaning has been much debated. Early on, it was interpreted to mean that "personal" rights were to be pre­ ferred to economic rights,3 but in recent years, largely through • Professor of Law, University of Houston Law Center.
    [Show full text]