University of Massachusetts Amherst ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst

Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014

1-1-1989

Moral education : a comparative study of the Confucian, Platonic and Kohlbergian approaches.

Young Il Shin University of Massachusetts Amherst

Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.umass.edu/dissertations_1

Recommended Citation Shin, Young Il, "Moral education : a comparative study of the Confucian, Platonic and Kohlbergian approaches." (1989). Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014. 4492. https://scholarworks.umass.edu/dissertations_1/4492

This Open Access Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. It has been accepted for inclusion in Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014 by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. For more information, please contact [email protected].

MORAL EDUCATION: A COMPARATIVE STUDY OF THE CONFUCIAN, PLATONIC AND KOHLBERGIAN APPROACHES

A Dissertation Presented

by YOUNG IL SHIN

Submitted to the Graduate School of the University of Massachusetts in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of

DOCTOR OF EDUCATION

FEBRUARY, 1989

Education © Young II Shin 1989 All Rights Reserved MORAL EDUCATION: A COMPARATIVE STUDY OF

THE CONFUCIAN, PLATONIC AND KOHLBERGIAN APPROACHES

A Dissertation Presented

by

YOUNG IL SHIN Dedicated to my father and mother

and

to my children

Dongsok, Sujeong and Haeryung ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS

I would like to acknowledge with deep gratitude several individuals without whom the completion of this humble work, which has taken so many years, would not have been possible: first, the members of my dissertation committee, Professors Robert Wellman, Philip Eddy and Fred Drake, and

Graduate Program Director of the School of Education, Professor William

Kornegay for their patient guidance; next, my colleagues at Northfield Mount

Hermon School, Jerry Davis, Glenn Vandervliet and Robert Treat, for their encouragement and support in various forms; also my devoted wife, Chonghyo, whose perpetual quest for excellence as an individual, artist, wife, mother, and in more recent times, indefatigable gardener of perennials, has provided me with constant inspiration throughout the years; finally, I thank my youngest daughter, Haeryung for her editorial assistance and actual typing of this paper, surviving numerous jens, yis, lis and chihs.

In addition, I would like to thank Northfield Mount Hermon School for its financial support, both at the beginning and the end of my doctoral program at the University. ABSTRACT

MORAL EDUCATION: A COMPARATIVE STUDY

OF

THE CONFUCIAN, PLATONIC AND KOHLBERGIAN APPROACHES

February, 1989

YOUNG IL SHIN, B.D., YONSEI UNIVERSITY

B.A., LEWIS AND CLARK COLLEGE

S.T.M., ANDOVER-NEWTON THEOLOGICAL SCHOOL

Ed.D., UNIVERSITY OF MASSACHUSETTS

Directed by: Dr. Robert R. Wellman

This study examines the philosophies and practices of moral education of three groups of thinkers, two classical and one modern. To attain this goal, it first compares the philosophy and practice of moral education of Confucius and

Mencius of Chou China with those of Socrates and of Athens based on the Confucian Four Books and the Platonic Dialogues. Then, it examines the theory and practice of moral education of Lawrence Kohlberg of the United

States in light of the classical wisdom of the Chinese and the Athenian thinkers.

The ultimate purpose of this study is, first, to see the similarities and differences

in their approaches to moral education and secondly, to gain some fresh ideas

to suggest for the improvement of our own approaches.

The first five chapters are devoted to the study of the two classical

groups. Chapter I surveys the histories of Chou China and the City-State of Athens to see what existing human conditions prompted our thinkers of two separate worlds to found moral education, and explores their reasons for thinking that moral education was the only way to improve their worlds.

Chapter II studies the Confucian and the Socratic/Platonic conceptions and analyses of human nature and their theories on man’s educability in moral excellence.

Chapter III examines the aims of moral education given by both groups and their justification for designating moral education a special education in moral excellence.

Chapter IV studies certain qualities and qualifications identified by both groups as essential in their teachers and students for moral education. Then, it compares the methods they used and their reasons.

Chapter V examines the curriculum selected by each group and the

reasons for including only certain courses in it. The chapter also examines

many virtues defined and discussed by both groups.

Chapter VI explores the theory and practice of moral education of

Lawrence Kohlberg against those of the classical thinkers. It also assesses

Kohlberg's contributions to modern day moral education.

Chapter VII summarizes the study and offers my own conclusion.

VII INTRODUCTION AND BACKGROUND OF THE STUDY

Objectives of the Study

The purpose of this study is to examine, first, two of the world's most influential and enduring theories and practices of moral education, which have shaped the minds of East Asians and Europeans for over two thousand years; second, the most publicized and controversial modern theory and practice of moral education of Lawrence Kohlberg of the United States; and then, to compare all three in the hope of getting some fresh ideas and methods to enrich and improve our own moral education in a pluralistic society such as the United

States.

The first five chapters are devoted to the study of the classical thinkers.

Chapter I surveys the histories of Chou China and the City-State of Athens to see what existing human conditions, moral and political, made Confucius and

Mencius in China and Socrates and Plato in Athens emerge as the founders of moral education for a special group of people. Chapter II examines the

Confucian and the Socratic/Platonic conception of man and his nature and compares their views on man's capacity to learn to be moral. Chapter III studies the aims of moral education given by both groups of people. Chapter IV compares natural and acquired human qualities considered as essential by both groups in their teachers and students for moral education. Various

methods used by each group and the degrees of effectiveness and danger they

saw are also discussed.

viii Chapter V examines the courses of study each group used and the reasons for including them in their curriculum. Many important virtues, private and public, which both groups expected to have their students acquire are also discussed.

Chapter VI explores the theory and practice of moral education of

Lawrence Kohlberg and measures his contribution, as compared to the classical thinkers' of China and Athens, to moral education today. Chapter VII presents this student’s concluding reflections and suggestions for further studies.

Significance of the Study

Living in a world where, since the last World War, all sorts of barriers, which had kept human races and their cultures isolated from each other for millennia, are fast coming down at ever increasing speed, we are now compelled to coexist with all human races on this planet whether we want to or not. It is now imperative that we discover and define some universal values that must be learned by all human races to live as one civilized human family, sharing their cultural fruits and enjoying the good life the wonders of technology can provide. The author of this study believes that moral education must assume a major portion of that effort. And also, he feels strongly that in the

United States, a dynamic moral education for the future and the world must start, for there is no better place in the world to start it.

The United States is a microcosm of the world in every sense of the word, and it is here that a universal human dream, such as that of Martin Luther King,

Jr., of enjoying equal rights, equal opportunities, and equal freedom can be and has become a reality, however slowly but surely. A slim but fascinating book just published by the MIT Press, An Agenda fpr the 21 §t Century, which is a collection of interviews conducted by Christian

Science Monitor columnist Rushworth Kidder with twenty-two thinkers of distinction - philosophers, politicians, economists, social scientists, educators, artists, business people, physicists, and authors - asking each one question:

What are the major issues that humanity will face in the 21 st century?

According to Kidder, the following six items or areas of concern "to which humanity must devote its full attention and its unstinting resources," in the 21st century are:

1. The threat of nuclear annihilation. 2. The danger of overpopulation. 3. The degradation of the global environment. 4. The gap between the developing and the industrial worlds. 5. The need for a fundamental restructuring of educational systems. 6. The breakdown in public and private morality.

Kidder points out that "the list is not in order of priority although the nuclear issue appears to to rank first." (p. 195) The question is: Which of the six agenda items should be most urgently dealt with? The answer is impossible, for all

items are interconnected. But the author of this study believes that the last two

items are fundamental and urgent, because all improvements and problem¬

solving must be carried out by educated and moral individuals, who draw upon

values that are universal and human to guide their specialized works and

actions for the welfare of all mankind.

Many of the interviewees mention that such universally necessary values

- trust, compassion, dignity, and obedience - must be restored to expect a

happier 21 st century. Kidder’s statement at the conclusion of the book agrees

with what the classical thinkers of China and Athens had stated all along.

Kidder writes: At bottom, then, this book asks a single question: How can we have a better 21 st century? Part of the answer lies in the work that must be done by the relatively small number of people in leadership positions acting both locally and globally on the major items on the formal agenda! But the other part of the answer lies in the willingness of each individual to act on the personal agenda. If we are to make the next century an age worth inhabiting, we will not do it simply by resolving, from the top down, the issues on the formal agenda. We will do it because individuals everywhere, taking to heart the personal agenda, are building within themselves a sounder society from the ground up. The act of building, happening within private lives across the world, ultimately charts a way to resolve the issues on the agenda for the 21 st century, (pp. 204-205)

The problems exist and they must be resolved. The human individuals who are endowed with special affinity to be leaders or governors of all human institutions - political, economic, cultural, religious, and educational - must be educated in universal moral values in order to resolve the problems most

satisfactorily for all of mankind.

A study such as that of this author is significant, because it examines

human minds of different races, cultures and times and proves their equal

power to reason, their equal concern with human problems, and their equal

commitment to solve the problems. It can also help man overcome racial and

cultural myths of natural superiority of one race over others; help him embrace

the truth that there exists a common humanity of all races, equal in spiritual,

intellectual, and creative powers, if all are given an equal chance for

development; and help him do his share of the work, guided by universal

human moral values, to make the world a better place for all mankind.

Literature, Methods, and Limitations of the Study

The volume of literature that separately includes studies of the many

aspects of Confucianism or the philosophy of Socrates and Plato is enormous. However, a comparative study of the philosophies and practices of moral education of the two groups, based on the primary sources, has not yet appeared. This study is a humble contribution to fill that need.

The primary sources for this study were the Confucian Four Books and the Dialogues of Plato. The Four Books - the Analects of Confucius, the Great

Learning, the Doctrine of the Mean, and the Book of Mencius - were read in their Chinese originals and in Korean, Japanese, and English translations.

Of the Dialogues of Plato, only those relevant to this study were read thoroughly. They are: the Apology, the Protagoras, the Meno, the Gorgias, the

Republic, the Laws, and the Timaeus; and they were read in English translations. Many different translations were helpful in grasping the real and pure meaning of the sources and in selecting short and long passages from the sources to be quoted in the text of this study. The unavoidable task of comparative reading of different translations was most of the time rewarding, but frustrating and tedious, too. Sometimes, when the reading involved extended discussions on the meaning of a certain virtue in the Dialogues, for example, it seemed to go nowhere.

Books and articles listed in the Bibliography were read in full or in part, mainly to check the accuracy of this author's own reading of the primary sources. They were also sources to tap information useful in understanding the milieu from which the primary sources emerged and through which they have survived for so many centuries.

The scope of this study is limited to include two classical and one modern theories and practices of moral education. There should be more studies of this

nature that compare the educational foundations of other great civilizations -

Hindu, Buddhist, Jewish, Christian, and Islamic - and identify ideals, values, and

methods in them all to enrich the educational wisdom of our days and the future.

XII TABLE OF CONTENTS

ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS. v

ABSTRACT. vi

PREFACE. vjjj

CHAPTER

I. HISTORICAL BACKGROUNDS OF THE FOUR BOOKS AND THE DIALOGUES. 1

The Chou Dynasty (between 1027 - 211 B.C.). 1

The City-State of Athens (between 1023 - 347 B.C.). 11

In summary. 26

II. THE NATURE OF MAN. 29

In the Four Books. 29

In the Dialogues. 36

In summary. 45

III. THE AIM OF EDUCATION. 47

In the Four Books. 47

In the Dialogues. 55

In summary. 60

IV. THE METHODS OF EDUCATION. 62

In the Four Books. 62

In the Dialogues. 71

In summary. 77

xiii V. CURRICULUM. 82

In the Four Books. 32

Poetry. 83

History. 85

Li: The Art of Ceremony or Rite. 89

Music. 94

The Study of Moral Principles. 99

In the Dialogues. 114

Arithmetic. 122

Geometry. 124

Astronomy and Harmonics. 125

In the Dialects. 126

The Four Cardinal Virtues and the Good Itself. 128

Wisdom. 132

Temperance. 133

Courage. 135

Justice. 138

In summary. 142

VI. KOHLBERG AND THE ANCIENTS. 14?

VII. SUMMARY AND CONCLUSION. 174

NOTES. 182

BIBLIOGRAPHY. 206

xiv CHAPTER I

HISTORICAL BACKGROUNDS OF

THE FOUR BOOKS AND THE DIALOGUES

The purpose of this chapter, which reviews historically the socio-political experiences of the Chou Chinese and the classical Athenians, is to see why the most outstanding classical thinkers of China and Greece were also the major theorists and practitioners of moral education.

In reviewing the history of Chou China and that of the City-State of

Athens, the following questions will be asked: 1) On what moral grounds or principles did the rulers of Chou and Athens want to build their states? 2) What major historical experiences and events were responsible for the deterioration of social morality in Chou China and in Athens? 3) What were the problems caused by the absence of moral principles in the China of Confucius (551-479

B.C.) and Mencius (372-289 B.C.) and in the Athens of Socrates (469-399 B.C.)

and Plato (428-348 B.C.), and how did these thinkers propose to resolve them?

The Chou Dvnastv (between 1027 and 211 B.C.)1

The Chou dynasty was founded by a frontier Chinese tribe who called

themselves Chou, whose origin is now traced to the Shensi Province area in

the northwestern part of China along the Wei River valley. In the latter part of

the 11th century B.C., they moved eastward and conquered the Kingdom of

Shang (ca. 1500-1027 B.C.), whose territory encompassed a good portion of

North China along the Yellow River by the time of its downfall.

i Being the products of the rugged frontier regions of China, the Chou were understandably less civilized than the ethnically identical Shang people now under their rule, and they were dynamic and progressive people who adopted some important social customs and religious rituals of the Shang and moved on to create their own culture and social values.2 The essentials of this culture provided the foundation for the guiding principles of the Chinese

people's thought and action down to the present day. Even Communist China

is Confucian under a new name!3

After establishing their own royal domain in Shensi near today's Siam,

the founders of the Chou dynasty divided up the conquered land out of

administrative necessity and awarded it to their own relatives and to the heads

of other tribes who had collaborated in the conquest. A territory was awarded

even to a Shang prince, thus making him a feudal lord under the Chou. Some

one thousand feudal states, great and small, were created, and the lord of each

state was left virtually free to rule in whatever way he wanted. The feudal lords

governed their states for the Chou kings, and the kings expected them, first, to

see that the land was put to productive cultivation; second, to send periodic

tribute to the court; third, to present themselves periodically at the court to show

their loyalty to the throne; and fourth, to raise an army in defense of the king

when required.4

The feudal system so instituted was a success, for it produced unbroken

political stability for at least two and a half centuries. Although the highly

idealized period of the Western Chou (1028-771 B.C.) was not without armed

conflicts between some of the territorially ambitious feudal lords and the

barbarians on the border regions, there was unity and cooperation among the

lords under the powerful and saintly kings who had the Mandate of Heaven. It

is important to note that for over twenty-five centuries, the traditional account of

2 this period has been accepted as the official model of the Chinese empire or state and it has been taught to all those who were preparing to be members of the ruling class. Loewe explains this further.

The house of Chou had been invested by a beneficent Heaven with religious authority and moral qualities, and that it was only under the auspices of Heaven, a superhuman and supernatural being, that the house had been established. It was thus only the head of the Chou house who was entitled to bear the title of King. Chinese moralists from an early time claimed that the fortunes of Chou depended directly on the moral qualities of the presiding rulers and their servants, and even explained the dynastic history of Chou in such terms. It was believed that the early rulers had been saintly kings, fully justified in expelling the last tyrannical ruler of Shang, and that their excellent government was operated over an increasingly wider area as the world became more civilized.5

As the dynasty entered the last third of the Western Chou period, the house of Chou began to lose its royal prerogatives, having enthroned some incompetent and immoral men as kings. By that time, some feudal lords had become more powerful than others, including the kings, having absorbed some and made alliances with some others through diplomatic and military

maneuvering. Preoccupied by the tasks of protection, survival, and expansion of their own individual states, the feudal lords were no longer reliable defenders

of the royal state when it came under attack. So it happened in 771 B.C. that

one of the lords, aided by non-Chinese nomadic tribes, rebelled against the

king and killed him. The royal remnants fled eastward to Loyang where the next

king was installed and the Eastern Chou period (771-221 B.C.) began. There

the king and all his successors for the next five hundred years were kept as the

titular heads of the kingdom without a territory large enough to base their own

political, military and economic powers. They were kept for the following

possible reasons.

3 First, at least in theory, the Mandate of Heaven remained with the house of Chou, and the kings were the sole custodians of the rites to commune with

Heaven and to legitimize any of the feudal lords' right to rule any part of the kingdom. Obviously, the Chou lords were not inclined to discard these religious and ceremonial functions which only the royal Chou heirs had the knowledge and power to perform.

Second, all feudal lords considered themselves the inheritors of the

Chou culture and were proud of it in spite of the endless political and military

rivalries among themselves. In order to perpetuate this sense of cultural unity, it was necessary to keep the symbol of the Chou culture, the royal house of Chou.

At any rate, the Eastern Chou period, which is further divided into two

sub-periods of the "Spring and Autumn" (772-481 B.C.) and the "Warring

States" (403-221 B.C.),6 began without a controlling authority to ensure the

political unity of the kingdom. The once numerous Chou states merged and

absorbed each other into fewer and more powerful political units through

diplomatic maneuvering during the Spring and Autumn period, but through

more violent means in the Warring States period.7

The political tradition of Chou seemed to perpetuate war, for it demanded

that all Chinese live in harmony under one culture and the sovereignty of the

Chou kings. Obviously feeling the need for a unified kingdom to save it from

self-destruction and from ever increasing alien menace, some powerful feudal

lords organized a league of states on the authority of the Chou king,

superintended by pa (hegemon or overlord). The first pa was the head of the

most powerful Ch'i state, then succeeded by the heads of other powerful states

to substitute the role formerly played by the Chou kings. The institution of

hegemon appears to have worked during the reign of the first hegemon for

about four decades (between 685 and 643 B.C.), but simply faded away by the

4 late 5th century B.C.8 There was no single state powerful enough to exercise control over other states.

Those states whose borders were shared with the barbarians were, in general, militarily stronger and territorially bigger than the inner or central states, and the latter were often compelled to take sides with one or the other of the peripheral states and often change sides as the fortunes of war shifted.

Even the interstate alliances, though sealed by rigidly worded covenants and religious ceremonies, became unreliable as the tempo of the contest for supreme political power among the states accelerated. Breaking covenants and entering new ones between states shattered the kingdom’s religious and moral foundations. Mencius described the state of affairs of his time as follows:

The world was fallen into decay, and right principles had dwindled away. Perverse and oppressive deeds were again waxen rife. Cases were occurring of ministers who murdered the rulers, and of sons who murdered their fathers. (III. B. 9. vii: Legge)

He goes on to report that in the Spring and Autumn period, there were no righteous wars.9

As China entered the Warring States period around 400 B.C., there were only seven powerful and a handful of small states besides the powerless royal state of Chou. The struggle among surviving states became intense and violent, and China was in a hopeless state of political and social disorder. "It was win or lose, absorb or be absorbed, kill or be killed; the chaos could not be

resolved until one state eliminated all rivals."10 The people were victimized, and so were the members of the feudal aristocracy when their states were lost to the victorious. H.G. Creel reports:

Aristocrats had little enough security. The people had none. They were chiefly farmers, commonly virtual serfs. They had few if any rights as against the nobility; in practice, they were taxed, worked, expropriated, scourged, and killed by the aristocrats, with almost no check save the fact that, if goaded too far, they might rebel. The penalty for unsuccessful

5 rebellion, however, was death by torture... The frequent wars brouqht more dramatic sufferings. In 593 B.C., for instance, the capital of the state of Sun was besieged for so long that the inhabitants were reduced to eating the flesh of the children. Since they could not bear to eat their own, they exchanged children before killing them.11

The scale of war was no longer small, as it had been in the Spring and

Autumn period. Having absorbed many small states, the states which made it

into the Warring States period were big in territory and population. Huge and

mobile armies of foot-soldiers, equipped with deadlier new weapons of crossbows and iron spears, dramatically increased the misery of human

suffering. By the 4th century B.C., cavalry replaced the war chariots driven by

feuding aristocrats, followed by a small number of their foot-soldiers.12

To equip, feed, and move big armies, the heads of the remaining states

encouraged agricultural and industrial productivity. As the demands for the

services of specialized crafts and industries grew, the size and number of cities,

too, grew rapidly. To attract farmers from other places, the contending heads of

various states advertised new land policies, such as the encouragement to

reclaim the waste land for ownership.

The construction of new roads and waterways, too, went on briskly during

this period, primarily for military purposes, but also to promote commercial and

industrial activities. It is not difficult to imagine that a great number of people

were on the move, either voluntarily or through force, in search of a safer place

to live, new land to till, new jobs in the cities.13 It is ironic to note that the

Warring States period was a time of socio-political chaos and endless human

misery, yet it was also a period of technological progress and economic

opportunity for many people.

In a way, China’s political tradition, which demanded that all Chinese live

unified under one sovereignty and one culture, kept an ever diminishing

number of states at each other's throat, although the house of Chou was gone

6 in reality and the Chou culture was hardly definable. In the end, the state of

Ch'in succeeded in unifying China absolutely with determined ruthlessness unprecedented in the history of China. Rene Grousset describes the way this was done.

The struggles between the Warring States were implacable. Instead of nobly holding their prisoners to ransom, from now on conquerors put them to death in mass executions. The soldiers of the kingdom of Ch’in the most bellicose of the Warring States, received their pay only on the presentation of the severed heads of the enemies. In towns taken by assault, or even in those that capitulated, the whole population, women, old men, and children, were often put to the sword... In 331 Ch'in captured the arm of Wei and decapitated 80,000 men... in 260, in a major success against Chao, although he had promised to spare the lives of the conquered, more than 400,000 were decapitated...14

The number of enemies killed by the Ch'in warriors through the years between

331 and 260 B.C. totalled 1,132,000ns

The time was finally ripe for some reflective human beings to come forward, exercise their creative and constructive imaginations, and make proposals for certain reforms and changes. A small number of educated men of

China made their appearance in the middle of the 5th century B.C.

Throughout the history of ancient China, the scholars had played an indispensable role in the government, but only as subservient experts on the ritual and the techniques of government. Although they were aware of their intellectual superiority over the martial class, the scholars were politically powerless. Even so, they were important in Chou China, for example, for performing the following functions, among others. First, they were responsible in ordering ceremonies to bring together the Chou rulers and their enfiefed lords of the feudal domains with the spirits of the Chou ancestors in order to

make their mandate to rule the people legitimate. Second, as the observers of astronomical phenomena and the changing seasons, the scholars were

responsible for adjusting and proclaiming the calendar, which was the supreme

7 royal prerogative. They had to keep detailed and accurate records of their observations and calculations. Third, the scholars were depended upon as advisors by all those who possessed political legitimacy, derived from the royal house of Chou, for their expertise. Fourth, they educated the sons of Chou kings and feudal lords.16

As the Chou dynasty was founded by military conquest, it is understandable that the military men exercised most decisively their political power, especially during the Warring States period. But gradually the scholars came to play more important roles in the government with their ability to provide reasoned analyses of the existing human problems caused by socio-political disorders. Moreover, they began to present theories to solve the problems which had demoralized the life of the people for far too long.

Confucius (551-479 B.C.), "China's first self-conscious philosopher"17 and the most learned man of his time, became the first thinker who openly expressed his distress with the existing state of human affairs and proposed to

restore China to its ancient glory and moral excellence through education.

Having failed to secure for himself an influential government post as an expert

in statecraft in a number of states, Confucius returned to his native state of Lu

and began to share his vision of an ideal Chou state which would be humane

and just with anyone who came to him. Impressed by his broad and profound

knowledge of the literatures of the past, his sincere concern for the future of the

Chou kingdom, and his single-minded quest for the knowledge of moral

principles which he firmly believed would solve human problems and raise the

quality of China's socio-political life to new heights, the number of his students

and followers grew rapidly and the Confucian school of philosophy was a reality

in his lifetime. His school was the forerunner of the "Hundred Schools of

Philosophers" which followed it and flourished between 500 and 250 B.C., the

8 Golden Age of Chinese thought or the "greatest period of intellectual flowering of ancient China."18

The scholars before Confucius, too, taught, but only the sons of the nobles in poetry, histories, ceremonies, and music, using the books on these subjects long since in existence, and their lessons were privately arranged by fathers who felt the need to provide some cultural exposure for their sons. The only formal schools for the aristocratic youth mentioned in any of the pre-

Confucian documents are the schools of archery according to Creel.19

Confucius changed all of this. First, declaring that "In teaching there should be no class distinction,"20 he was the first in the history of China who freed education from all barriers of privilege and social class. In his view, the aim of government was to ensure the welfare and happiness of the whole people, and the administration of the government ought to be carried out by men of high intelligence, deep sympathy, and broad learning regardless of what the social position of their families might have been. He wanted to see the future rulers and their officials come for a right education from all walks of life.21 Second, for

Confucius, a right education was an education which could help the learner's life and character, shaped by the knowledge of the highest moral principles, not by martial arts such as archery. A few opening passages in the Great Learning articulate what Confucius wished to accomplish in his school.

...Things have their roots and their branches. Affairs have their end and their beginning. To know what is first and what is last will lead near to what is taught in the Great Learning. The ancients who wished to illustrate illustrious virtue throughout the kingdom, first ordered well their own states. Wishing to order well their states, they first regulated their families. Wishing to regulate their families, they first cultivated their persons. Wishing to cultivate their persons, they first rectified their hearts. Wishing to rectify their hearts, they first sought to be sincere in their thoughts. Wishing to be sincere in their thoughts, they first extended to the utmost their knowledge. Such extension lay in the investigation of things.

9 Things being investigated, knowledge became complete. Their knowledge being complete, their thoughts were sincere. Their thouahts being sincere, their hearts were then rectified. Their hearts beinq rectified, their persons were cultivated. Their persons being cultivated their families were regulated. Their families being regulated, their states were rightly governed. Their states being rightly governed, the whole kingdom was made tranquil and happy. From the Son of Heaven down to the mass of the people, all must consider cultivation of the person the root of everything besides.22

Creel, in one of his studies, indicates that

...the founder of the Confucian tradition is commonly considered to be the Duke of Chou. Confucius was not, as is often supposed, its founder. As a matter of fact, there is very little in the philosophy of Confucius which cannot be found in the utterances of men who lived before him...Confucius was only the last and most famous of such men. It is in part because he came at the end of the early development of this tradition, and summed it up, that he has become its representative par excellence.23

Confucius himself said: "I transmit but do not innovate; I am truthful in what I say and devoted to antiquity."24 Nevertheless, he was the first professional teacher in China and gave his utmost to the education of men in his unflinching belief that the knowledge and practice of the highest moral values alone could solve the problems of his world. Although many of his utterances addressed to his

students, who included rulers and others in power, sound like pedantic and casual homilies, when the world of his time is understood, some of his remarks were, as Needham points out, "pointed denunciations of weaknesses, not to say

crimes, made directly to men who would have felt as much compunction about

having Confucius tortured to death as about crushing a fly."25 In a world where

endless war between the feudal states made the life of the common people

cheap and burdened while the life of the contending lords was ruthless in their

pursuit of power and extravagance at the cost of their subjects, Confucius' fresh

and penetrating exposition of moral values and principles was definitely

inspirational and efficacious. Mencius, the chief exponent and advocator of the

Confucian philosophy of the classical period, played an important role in instituting Confucianism as China's dominant philosophy of life. Lin Yutang explains this with the following words:

In the study of the character of Confucian thought, it is important to have some ideas of its chief developments in Mencius, because of the clearer exposition of philosophic values in Mencius and because of their actual influence. Mencius represents the "orthodox" development of the Confucian school. The Book of Mencius... is incomparably better prose than the Analects- Mencius was an eloquent writer and speaker, good at debates, and the passages often consist of long and sustained discourses, and there are so many brilliant passages...... The most important ideas in Mencius are the goodness of human nature, consequently the importance of revering that original good nature, the recognition that culture or education merely consists of preventing the good nature in us from becoming "beclouded" by circumstances, the theory of nourishing that amounts to an equivalent of Bergson’s elan vital (the hao jan chih ch'i), and finally the declaration that all men are equal in their inherent goodness, and that since the Emperors Yao and Shun were also human beings, "any man could become Yao or Shun."26

In his search for a better and more perfect human society, Mencius touches upon the whole range of human needs and capacities. Included in his discussions are not only subjects on man’s physical well-being, his needs for food and sex, the feelings of beauty, poetry and music; but also on the systems of taxation, agriculture, and government. By far, however, the greatest and most persistent emphasis is on man himself, whose growth in moral excellence is the ultimate condition to having an ideal society.

The Citv-State of Athens (between 1023 and 347 B.C.)27

The construction of a definitive history of the early period of the city-state of Athens has been and still is a tantalizing dream for scholars. However, the following account of the period should sum up the findings of modern scholarship. The formation of the Athenian state was a direct result of the movement of the lonians from the north into in late Mycenean days beginning around 1023 B.C. These Ionian Greeks were successful in absorbing the numerous independent villages and towns of Attica into a central state called Athens under a powerful monarchy.28 The Greeks, now establishing themselves in

Attica, were composed of many different families or clans, and they seem to have shared the newly conquered territory among themselves. The problem of the division of the land among themselves in a mutually satisfying way was not an easy one to solve. Moreover, settling in a land already inhabited by people with their own customs and heritage presented yet another problem and

required of the Athenian leaders some active thinking and a willingness to

experiment with various forms of government. Athenian aristocrats, politically

ambitious and innovative, began to try their varied devices in the hope of

realizing political unity and economic prosperity for the entire state.

In the years between 1000 and 687 B.C., which will be called the archaic

period hereafter and approximately coincides with the first three centuries of the

Chou dynasty known as the Western Chou (1027 to 771 B.C.), the Athenian

monarchy was supplanted by the members of hereditary aristocratic families,

Eupatridae, to whom all power was appropriated, while the native population of

Attica were left to live in their own villages and towns, with virtually no political

rights. According to A.R. Burn, the election by the aristocrats of a separate War-

Chief, Polemarch, at a time when the king was not a great fighting man, and the

appointment of the Archon over the king were two decisive blows to the royal

power. The king was kept, as in China during the Eastern Chou period, as the

city-state's chief priest, but the real power was in the hands of the Archon.

For religious purposes, the king was kept even in classical, democratic

Athens, but he was only the second man in the state.29 The real governing

power rested in the office of the Archon, and the War-Chief was the third many

in the Athenian political hierarchy. Later in the archaic period, as population and judicial workload increased, six Judges, thesmothetai, were added, and they were collectively called the Nine Archons or Rulers. They together controlled every aspect of the political and judicial life of the Athenian population. All archons had to be from the Eupatridae, and their term of office was one year. The Eupatridae also became powerful economically by appointing themselves sole owners of the land, thus reducing the native and the rest of the population to the position of serfs.

Their scheme to assert Athenian sovereignty over the entire population of the state beyond the city of Athens was to be challenged later by rival

Eupatridae and the people connected with them in one way or another in their respective regions. In Sealey's words,

In many parts of Attica there were local traditions, local cults and locally powerful families, and factors of this kind commanded the primary loyalty of the locality. In terms of political power, local ties had the effect that different families predominated in different parts of Attica and had the first claim on the devotion of humbler families and persons in their several regions.30

With this system of government, the city-state of Athens was destined to be

plagued with politico-economic rivalry and struggles among the Eupatridae of

different regions from the beginning of its formation.

The first recorded rebellion against the establishment was led by Cylon

in or near the year 632 B.C., and it ended in a bloody massacre of his besieged

followers on the Acropolis by the Nine Archons. Although the motives of his

rebellion are nowhere documented, it is clear that it was a radical expression of

the resentment of his and other leading families in the same region toward the

other regional families then in power.31

About a decade later in 621 B.C., Dracon introduced a set of homicide

laws. The surviving text, which was reinscribed in 409/8 B.C., indicates the

need for laws harsh and exact enough to discourage homicidal crimes,

1 3 probably occurring too frequently for the state to ignore. The promulgation of the laws also implies the social unrest of the time.32

In spite of the severity of the Draconian laws, maybe because of it, the social, economic, and political injustice continued to distress the people. In particular, the agricultural population of Attica, whose land and political rights had been steadily taken away since the unification, was profoundly agitated.

The people were also paying dearly for the protracted war with the neighboring

Megarians for the possession of Salamis. Beyond doubt, the Athenian state was in deep trouble with domestic and inter-state problems as it entered the sixth century B.C.

The war with the Megarians ended with the capture of Salamis under the command of Solon, and in 594 or 592 B.C., Solon was elected Archon. In electing him to the state's highest political office, the Council of Areopagus gave him exclusive and almost dictatorial powers to correct the problems of the

States, and Solon used them most productively without wasting time.

His first legislative act was to put the Athenian economy on a sounder agricultural footing by introducing an economic reform known as the

seisachtheia, meaning "the shaking off of burdens," which freed the debtors and their land by cancelling all debts. This radical measure liberated the enslaved

Athenian farmers from their creditors, the Eupatridae. He also forbade the

export of corn to ease the life of the many and stimulated the cultivation of the

vine and the olive for export, thus laying the foundation of Athens' material

prosperity. He is also known to have encouraged commercial enterprises,

especially the manufacture and export of Attic black-figure vases, to supplement

the source of wealth, which had depended almost totally on the land.

His next major work was the codification of a constitution aimed to

safeguard the civil rights of the people. The new constitution outlawed contracts

1 4 in which a person's liberty might be pledged, thus putting an end to serfdom in

Attica. It then divided the Athenians into four classes on the basis of property.

This made property the qualification for political privilege and office, which had been granted exclusively to the members of hereditary aristocracy, the

Eupatridae.33

Solon then made the Assembly of the People, Ecclesia, open to all freemen and founded the Council of Four Hundred, drawing a hundred men from each class. Although no detailed information about the Council's structure and activity is available, one of its main tasks appears to have been that of preparing the agenda for the Assembly.34 Understandably, there was civil strife between 589 and 580 B.C. as a result of these radical reforms, but his reforms remained the basis of the Athenian state from then on. At any rate, there is no question that Solon attempted to make Athens a more democratic state while he was in power, and the Athenians enjoyed comparative peace for the next two decades.

The next major political upheaval was caused by a friend of Solon,

Peisistratus, who was also a war hero for leading his men to capture Nisaea in

the wars with the Megarians. Being a native of Brauron, which is in eastern

Attica and is separated from the city of Athens by hills, he became the leader of

the party of "the men from beyond the hills." His party was in a power struggle

with two other parties, one representing "the men of the plains" and the other

representing "the men of the shore."35

It appears that the people "from beyond the hills" or of the outlying plains

were not totally satisfied with the reforms introduced by Solon. The regional

rivalries, compounded by economic inequalities, seem to have generated the

political struggles led by the personally ambitious heads of different groups for ultimate power. What exactly these separate parties wanted is still debated among scholars.36

In 561 or 560 B.C., Peisistratus moved first. He led his followers "from beyond the hills" to Athens; occupied the Acropolis, the seat of political power and the home of the kings, by force; and installed himself as tyrant. His rivals rallied, and he was driven out of Athens after a few months. Within five years, he tried again at tyranny, but his second attempt to power, too, failed.

Thereupon, he withdrew from Attica and settled in Thrace to prepare for his next move. It took him almost ten years to raise necessary funds, organize a well- supported army, and hire mercenaries. In 546 B.C., he brought down his army to Athens, captured the Acropolis without much bloodshed, and established lasting tyranny in Athens.

According Jean Hatzfeld, the term "tyranny" by which the reign of

Peisistratus and his sons had been identified

...carried no implication of arbitrary or oppressive rule but simply meant that power was wielded by one man, not according to principles of divine right and heredity as had been the case with the old monarchy, but based on personal prestige, the favour of the lower orders, and a strong military organisation.37

Peisistratus, who had support from the rising non-aristocratic class of the

wealthy and the increasing city population of merchants and artisans besides

his own men "from beyond the hills," did not abolish Solon’s laws and

constitution. He followed the economic policy introduced by Solon by

promoting agricultural productivity and commercial activities both at home and

abroad through his friendly and expansive foreign policy.

He brought some decisive changes for the future of Athens, such as the

introduction of uniform taxation, the building of temples, and the fostering of

national festivals. The Athenians seem to have enjoyed peace and prosperity

1 6 through his despotic implementation of the Solonian constitution. Throughout his reign, his extraordinary powers were confirmed without murmur from either the Council of Areopagus or the Assembly of the People, and he was able to place his friends and relatives among the Nine Archons each year in order to maintain his political power.

His policies brought the people of Attica toward a more perfect union.

After his death in around 527 B.C., his two sons, Hipparchus and Hippias, carried on his established order for more than fifteen years. However, they were unable to handle the two problems troubling them almost simultaneously during the reign. One was the mounting Persian military threat in the Aegean: the other was the old enmity of the exiled aristocrats often supported by anti-

Athenian Greek states. Suspicions, plots, and counterplots ensued among the powerful aristocrats both in and out of Athens after the death of Peisistratus.

The tyranny ended with the assassination of Hipparchus in 514 B.C. and the expulsion of Hippias in 510 B.C.

After a short period of civil war, the Athenians saw the rise of Cleisthenes as the most powerful political figure in the state in 508 B.C. Though an aristocrat himself, Cleisthenes was for more democracy and against both tyranny and oligarchy. His most important contribution was the administrative

reorganization of Attica into the demes which he grouped together into ten tribes or phylaie. Each tribe was composed of three sections of territory, one- third city dwellers, one-third inhabitants of the coastal regions, and one-third

peasants living in the interior. In this way, every Athenian now belonged only to

the deme where he was domiciled and to the tribe to which the deme belonged.

Four objectives for the reorganization were: first, to make each phylae

comparatively equal in population; second, to make each phylae to a great

extent equal in geographical representation of the people; third, to make

1 7 possible a more equal distribution of civic burdens, such as military service, among all ten phylaie; and fourth, to do away with the regional spirit that had made the powerful regional aristocrats conspire for their regional supremacy and their prejudicial laws.38

His next contribution to Athenian democracy was the introduction of the

Council of Five Hundred, drawing fifty men of thirty years of age or above from each of the ten tribes. They were chosen by lot to serve in the Council for a year or, at most, two annual terms. How this Council actually functioned, with those who had no particular administrative talent or training serving such short terms, is questionable. It was not the supreme decision-making body. Its primary function was to prepare laws and decrees to be ratified by the Assembly of the

People, which was now given the real legislative power. This whole system, though very complex and confusing, obviously worked somehow and gave a greater number of Athenian citizens a political education and experience.39

Another measure introduced by Cleisthenes to protect his scheme of

democracy from tyranny and oligarchy was that of the law of ostracism. By this

law, individuals with excessive political power, so judged by the Assembly,

were sent into exile for ten years without losing either their citizenship or their

property.40 Through these new devices, the progress for more democracy for

Athens was positively made under Cleisthenes over Solon's constitutional

reforms of a century earlier. Yet, it must be remembered that the most powerful

civil and military offices of the state were still reserved for the members of the

most powerful and old aristocratic families. Though their social prestige,

political power and wealth, too, were reduced somewhat over the many

decades since Solon, the Athenian aristocracy did not fade away from the

political stage. They kept their social and political inheritance with pride and asserted themselves whenever they had a chance, as we shall see in more detail in this chapter.

With the beginning of all-out Persian expeditions against Greek states, the history of Athens cannot be separated from the general history of Greece.

Two of the most powerful Greek states, Athens and , came together with their allied states and were successful in defending not only their own city- states, but the whole of Greece from the two Persian assaults between 492 and

479 B.C.

The Greek land force under the Spartan command and the naval force under the Athenian command, the allied Greek states successfully destroyed the Persian forces both on land and sea. Once the "barbarians" were repulsed,

intrastate jealousies and competition for dominant leadership positions for the whole of Greece ensued. In spite of the heroic and brilliant roles the Athenians

played in the GrecoPersian wars, Athens was not free from domestic power

struggles among its leading political leaders. Two of its most outstanding

wartime heroes, Themistocles and Cimon, were ostracized from their ruling

posts, and one of their political rivals, Ephialtes, who took Cimon's seat, was

murdered.41

Having played an important role with her navy in the wars with Persia, $ Athens proposed an all-Greek defense alliance composed of the coastal cities

in the Aegean under her leadership. The proposal was accepted, the Delian

League was organized in 478/7 B.C., and an empire was born. The Athenian

hegemony over the member states was absolute, and the Athenian leaders

demanded and received almost absolute loyalty from them, as well as funds

which the member states paid as their membership obligation. The funds so

collected were used to enlarge and strengthen the Athenian navy, to expand the Athenian sphere of dominance by military conquest if necessary, and to provide the Athenians with more jobs and markets abroad.

The Athenian empire was spectacular in power, wealth, cultural splendor, and arrogance, especially under Pericles between 461 and 429 B C

Its domestic policy gave Athenians more democracy than ever before, but its policy toward the member states of the Delian League and other Greek states and neighboring nations was imperialistic and ruthlessly exploitative. Its tyrannical foreign policy, which humiliated and threatened the security and independence of many, later drew the accumulated wrath not only of the member states of the Delian League, but also of other Greek states, especially

Sparta and its allies, and caused its own downfall in 404 B.C.

To be more specific, soon after the Persian War, the wartime alliance between Athens and Sparta dissolved, and armed conflicts between the two and their allies became frequent and massive, starting around 460 B.C. The

First , which broke out that year, dragged on without any decisive result to either camp for almost fifteen years. The intensity of the war mounted radically when the treasury of the Delian League was transferred from the island of Delos to Athens in 454/3 B.C. Pericles, who took over the Athenian leadership after the death of his friend Ephialtes and the ostracism of their political rival Cimon in 461 B.C., proposed a truce and the Thirty Years' Peace was agreed upon by the contending parties, thus ending the first round of war in

445 B.C.

Between 445 and 431 B.C., the Athenians were left in relative peace at

home, enjoying unprecedented prosperity and a sense of cultural superiority

having made the city of Athens the cultural center of the world with

mathematicians, astronomers, philosophers, poets, architects, sculptors, and

painters of their own and from abroad.

20 In spite of the Thirty Years' Peace, the Athenian interference with the city- state of Corinth and its colony Corcyra resulted in the outbreak of the Second

Peloponnesian War in 431 B.C. The Spartans with their allies began their almost annual invasion of Attica by land, devastating the crops and forcing the people to flee from their homes for safety. In retaliation, Athens ravaged the

Peloponnesian coast with her fleet, also annually, and cut off Spartan commerce.

This second round of fratricidal war, too, dragged on inconclusively for almost ten years until 421 B.C., when the Peace of for fifty years was agreed on. But fighting recommenced within three years, and continued on and off for another fourteen years, during which the Athenians lost the mighty fleet, which had been the source and guardian of their imperial splendor, and the empire itself in 404 B.C.

During this seemingly endless war, the Athenians experienced joy when their men won and grief when they lost in countless battles on land and sea.

They saw great military leaders rise and perish with their men. They despaired when the ill-conceived and ill-fated expeditions, one to Egypt between 459 and

454 B.C. and another to Sicily between 415 and 413 B.C., ended in total

disaster. Although the city of Athens was spared from the direct blow of the war,

in early summer of 430 B.C., soon after the Peloponnesians began their all-out

attack on Attica, a deadly plague broke out in the city, killing terrified people by

the thousands, including one-third of Athens' first-line troops and Pericles, the

Athenians' most illustrious leader, whom they could not afford to lose at such a

critical time.42

Even after the death of Pericles, democracy was kept in the hands of the

leaders, though their vision of democracy and dedication to it were of uncertain

quality. In conducting the war, the Athenians were cruel and savage, lacking

21 even elementary human compassion towards their armed and unarmed opponents, as so graphically reported.** In spite of their efforts, the empire began to dissolve rapidly, as more and more League members defected. They were winning some, but losing gradually more battles until the humiliating end had to be arranged in 404 B.C.

By the terms of the peace of 404 B.C., the Delian League was dissolved, and the Athenians were ordered to pull down the walls and forts which had protected the city all these years and to acknowledge the leadership of Sparta on land and sea in the Greek world. With the end of the war, the Athenians lost their democracy, too, for a brief time as the Rule of the Thirty put them under a reign of terror; however, they regained democracy the following year.

Although the major contest between Athens and Sparta was now over, the weakened city-states, including Athens, continued to war among themselves until all of them fell easy prey to the Macedonian invaders in 338

B.C.

Socrates was born in 470/69 B.C., about nine years after the end of the

Persian War. During the first forty years of his life, he witnessed the

transformation of Athens from a city-state to an empire and saw the rise of

literary and artistic achievements, as well as material prosperity, especially

during the reign of Pericles. Many of classical Greece's eminent intellectuals,

with whom Pericles surrounded himself, were Socrates' contemporaries, and

he knew many of them in person. Without any doubt, the intellectual

atmosphere in the time of Cimon and Pericles had provided abundant stimuli for

the development of Socrates as a thinker of unique dimension and depth.

At thirty, Socrates was already an independent thinker, having acquired

full knowledge of the science of the age and also full mastery of its humanistic

22 culture. Among his circle of friends or associates were many important political and intellectual luminaries of his generation and the future.44

When he was about forty, the Peloponnesian War broke out, and he was away from the city of Athens, serving the state as a hopliti, a fully armed infantryman, once in 432 B.C., and again in 424 B.C. He performed his share of civic responsibilities conscientiously whenever he was given the chance to make the Athenian democracy work, but he did not take an active part in politics. However, in 406 B.C., he tried to overturn the unjust conviction of the commanders impeached after the sea battle at Arginusae, and in 404 B.C. he disobeyed an order from the Thirty to arrest a certain Leon of Salamis, who had been unjustly selected for proscription. Throughout his life, Socrates remained a good, law-abiding citizen. This does not mean, however, that he was content with the way his beloved state was evolving.

Athens’ endless experimentation with various forms of government

following the time of Solon, the endless feuding among political parties within the state and equally endless warring with other states both Greek and foreign,

must have disturbed Socrates profoundly. In his view, the quality of Athenian

life was far below what it could be, and for the love of his state and the

Athenians he wanted to render his best service to raise it to its attainable

excellence by committing his life to teaching and seeking the highest moral

values which, he firmly believed, would surely bring positive results. For

Socrates, the dedication of his life to teaching did not owe to his love of it as a

profession, but rather it was a divine call45

His pedagogical mission by the method of questions and answering

which compelled men to think was deeply affecting, and the state of Athens

clearly felt its existing socio-political order threatened. Socrates was convicted

and sentenced to death primarily for "corrupting the youth of Athens." He died

23 for his mission, teaching to the last moment of his life in 339 B.C. Plato recorded the words of Socrates in the Apology to show us how seriously Socrates took his vocation.

Men of Athens, I respect and love you, but I shall obey the god rather than you, and while I live and am able to continue, I shall never give up philosophy or stop exhorting you and pointing out the truth to any one of you whom I may meet, saying in my accustomed way: "Most excellent man, are you who are a citizen of Athens, the greatest of cities and the most famous for wisdom and power, not ashamed to care for the acquisition of wealth and for reputation and honour, when you neither care nor take thought for wisdom and truth and the perfection of your soul?" And if any of you argue the point, and says he does care, I shall not let him go at once, nor shall I go away, but I shall question and examine and cross-examine him, and if I find that he does not possess virtue, but says he does, I shall rebuke him for scorning the things that are of most importance and caring more for what is of less worth. This I shall do to whomever I meet, young and old, foreigner and citizen, but most to the citizens, inasmuch as you are more nearly related to me... If by saying these things I corrupt the youth, these things must be injurious; but if anyone asserts that I say other things than these, he says what is untrue. Therefore I say to you, men of Athens, either do as Anytus tells you, or not, and either acquit me, or not, knowing that I shall not change my conduct even if I am to die many times over. (29 D - 30 B: Fowler)

In the age of so many self-serving teachers of wisdom, the sophists, Socrates wanted to be the true and the best teacher, and he paid with his life for that commitment.

Plato, the most important heir to the spirit and philosophy of Socrates, was born in 427 B.C. of great aristocratic families, prominent in Athenian politics for many decades. According to his Seventh Epistle, he was interested in political affairs from his earliest youth and seriously wished a political career. In

404 B.C., when he was twenty-three or four years of age, his first political

opportunity came with the reign of the Thirty, in which two of his relatives,

Charmides and Critias, were involved. He was actually invited by them, but

declined, shocked at their terrifying excesses and ruthless despotism. With the

return of democracy in the following year, Plato's political ambition revived, but

24 he abandoned it totally when his revered teacher Socrates was tried and put to death by the reigning democrats. These events might have caused him to turn to question, as Socrates had done all along, what "justice" really was. After the execution of Socrates, Plato committed himself to two important tasks as his lifetime mission. One was to preserve the teachings of Socrates in writing, and the other was to develop his own philosophy, in accordance with the spirit and teachings of his mentor, also in writing for posterity.

Socrates and Plato were among the most brilliant and broadly cultivated

minds the classical Greek world has ever had, and they were responsible for

initiating a new approach to human problems by designating the moral

education of man as the key to their solution. Having lost faith in varied forms of

government, which were supported and run by ambitious and determined but

morally blind men, both Socrates and Plato concluded that as long as the

people in ruling positions remained ignorant of the fundamental knowledge of

"justice," the universal and immutable moral principle, there could be no just

and happy state. The question raised by Socrates and Plato was simple and

fundamental: How could a just way of life be achieved by those who had no

clear conception of what justice is?

From Homeric times, the Athenian youth had received their values and

education through association with the elders in their family. In the course of

this association, a certain set of moral qualities for good citizenship were

transmitted orally and by imitative practices. This method of education was first

challenged by Socrates, who questioned repeatedly whether or not fathers and

elders could, indeed, transmit moral qualities to the young.46 Plato, then,

intensified the challenge by establishing an academy of his own to do the work

of moral training more systematically with a curriculum assisted by a well-

defined pedagogical method.

25 Plato carried out his share of the mission started by Socrates to the end of his life, teaching at his Academy and constructing in writing his system of moral education, which, he believed, would almost automatically result in an ideal and just republic.

In summary

It is interesting to note that the two distinctly different groups of people, one in China and the other in Greece, separated by thousands of miles from each other and isolated by forbidding natural barriers, began to move from their original habitats to better places for permanent settlement at just about the same time some three thousand years ago, and eventually produced two of the most enduring civilizations in the history of mankind.

In 1027 B.C., the Chou Chinese conquered the Shang King in the

Central Plain, moving eastward from their northwest homeland and founded their own kingdom. The new kingdom was then divided up by the kings and given to their relatives and powerful supporters of their dynasty to lord over and rule their city-state like domains for the Chou. For the approximately 250 years, known as the Western Chou Period (1027-771 B.C.), the kingdom is recorded to

have enjoyed unity, peace, and prosperity among its people under the

enlightened ruler of moral excellence.

In 771 B.C., the reigning king and his government were found internally

corrupt and incapable of commanding loyal services from the feudal lords to

protect the kingdom from foreign invaders. A military alliance of powerful lords

forced the king to relocate his capitol, and he and his successors were allowed

to keep the royal title and perform their ceremonial duties that only the members

of the Chou house could perform, but without political power. The unifying and

26 controlling authority of the royal government being gone, Chou China became a

battleground among the feudal lords. For the next 500 years known as the

Eastern Chou Period (771-221 B.C.), each fought for his own survival, glory,

and power, under the pretenses of restoring unity, peace, and prosperity to the kingdom.

In the Greek world, the builders of the future Athenian empire, the Ionian

Greeks, began to move from the north into Attica around 1023 B.C., absorbing

the native Greeks of Attica in numerous villages and towns scattered in three or

four plains separated by hills into the state of Athens under the kings whose

government was in the city of Athens. The city-state Athens with Attica as its

territory, was huge and fated to have problems in claiming its sovereignty over

the whole of Attica.

Unlike the China of the Western Chou Period, the Archaic Period in

Greek history (1000-687 B.C.) is filled with reports of endless politico-economic

conflicts and wars between the native Greeks in different regions of Attica and

the ruling Athenians. Although a few legendary kings are said to have

succeeded in uniting all Greeks, the unifications lasted only for very short spans

of time.

Beginning in the year 632 B.C., some powerful aristocrats representing

various regional interest groups began to challenge and even rebel against the

established order of the state. To preserve the city-state of Athens, a train of

innovative and determined leaders rose to experiment with one new form of

government after another, including democracy. But none of them satisfied all

parties. While the domestic factionalism was becoming increasingly vicious

and bloody, with plots and counterplots, the mighty Persians invaded the

mainland of Greece in two great waves between 492 and 479 B.C. All Greek

states joined in a united effort to repel the invaders and their effort was

27 successful. But the victory over the Persians made two of the mightiest defenders of Greece, the Athenians and the Spartans, arrogant, uncompromising, and aggressive empire builders after the war and their old rivalry erupted again in 431 B.C. The costly and tragic Peloponnesian wars continued for almost thirty years and by 404 B.C., the great Athenian empire was no more.

The ancient Greece of the fifth century B.C. was just like the China of the fifth and fourth centuries B.C. The people and their leaders alike would have found themselves in a hopelessly messed up situation, not knowing exactly what was happening, what they were doing or ought to be doing. It was during these two centuries that a great many reform-minded philosophers of enormous importance made their appearance both in China and Athens. The most prominent of them all, whose ideas are still refreshing and inspiring to this day, lived and taught during these centuries: Confucius (551-479 B.C.) and Mencius

(372-289 B.C.) in China, and Socrates (470-399 B.C.) and Plato (427-347 B.C.) in Athens. Amazingly, both groups of thinkers concluded that the moral education of future rulers was the only way to make the world an orderly, humane, and happy place for human beings. And they all became teachers, not only in their own times, but ever since to this day.

28 CHAPTER II

THE NATURE OF MAN

In the Four Books

The opening sentence of the Doctrine of the Mean declares that "What

Heaven has conferred is called nature or sheng (')•£)." (I. i: Legge) When

Kao Tzu said to Mencius that "Appetite for food and sex is nature," Mencius agreed with him. He said: "For the mouth to desire sweet tastes, the eye to desire beautiful colours, the ear to desire pleasant sounds, the nose to desire fragrant odours, and the four limbs to desire ease and rest - these are natural."

(M: VII. B. 24: Legge) Confucius, too, noted man’s powerful sexual instinct as natural.1 Both Confucius and Mencius acknowledged not only the desires of man’s sensual appetites as natural, but also the expectation of a reward of "joy" or "ease," when man fulfills his desires.

They assert, however, that man is not born for the joy and ease that comes from the fulfillment of the appetitive desires in his nature alone, but to enjoy the supreme "joy” or "ease" that rewards man in fully exercising his mind, which is innately jen (

A man cares about all parts of his body without discrimination, and so he nurtures all parts equally. There is not a square inch of skin that he does not care about, and so he tends all of his skin equally... But he who gives preferential treatment to the lesser parts of the body becomes a lesser man. He who gives preferential treatment to the great parts becomes a greater man... Man despises one who lives only to eat and drink, because he develops the lesser function of his body and neglects the greater. (M: VI. A. 14: Dobson)

29 The classical Confucians held the view that both man and animals are endowed with functionally identical senses and organs for the survival and preservation of their species, and the "difference between a man and an animal is slight." (M: IV. B. 19: Legge) What distinguishes man from animals is his mind {hsin/\s) that thinks {ssu $L) and is inherently good. Mencius said:

The organs of hearing and seeing cannot think and can be misled by external things... To the mind belongs the function of thinking. By thinking, it gets the right view of things; by neglecting to think, it fails to do this. And the organs and the mind are what Heaven has given to us. (M: VI. A. 15: Legge alt.)

The mind, which is innately good and which every human being comes with at birth, is further explained by Mencius as follows.

It is of the essence of man's nature that he do good. That is what I mean by good. If a man does what is evil he is guilty of the sin of denying his natural endowment. Every man has a sense of pity, a sense of shame, a sense of respect, a sense of right and wrong. From his sense of pity comes i£H (Humanity^); from his sense of shame comes yi (Justice 'j^)\ from his sense of respect, li (the observance of rites^); from ms sense of right and wrong, chih (Wisdom ). Jsn, yi, li, and chih do not soak in from without; we have them within ourselves. It is simply that we are not always consciously thinking about them. So I say, "Seek them and you have them. Disregard them and you lose them." Men differ, some by twice, some by five times, and some by an incalculable amount, in their ability to exploit this endowment. (M: VI. A. 6: Dobson)

To prove the innate goodness of the human mind, Mencius said:

It is a feeling common to all mankind that they cannot bear to see others suffer... I say that all men have such feelings because, on seeing a child about to fall into a well, everyone has a feeling of horror and distress... Not to feel distress would be contrary to all human feelings. Just as not to feel shame and disgrace and not to defer to others and not to have a sense of right and wrong are contrary to all human feeling. This feeling of distress is the first sign of Humanity, ien. This feeling of shame and disgrace is the first sign of Justice, yi. This feeling of deference to others is the first sign of Propriety, \\. This sense of right and wrong is the first sign of Wisdom, £hih. Men have these four innate feelings just as they have four limbs... Since all have these four capacities within themselves, they should know how to develop and to fulfill them. They are like a fire about to burst into flame, or spring about to gush forth from the ground. (M: II. A: Dobson)

30 Lau’s translation of the same passages makes Mencius' points even clearer.

No man is devoid of a heart Oisin *&) sensitive to the sufferinq of others... My reason for saying that no man is devoid of a heart sensitive to the suffering of others is this. Suppose a man were, all of a sudden to see a young child on the verge of falling into a well. He would certainiv be moved to compassion... From this it can be seen that whoever is devoid of the heart of compassion is not human, whoever is devoid of the heart of shame is not human, whoever is devoid of the heart of courtesy and modesty is not human, and whoever is devoid of the heart of right and wrong is not human. The heart of compassion is the germ of benevolence, jsn; the heart of shame, of dutifulness, yi; the heart of courtesy and modesty, of observance of the rites, Ji; the heart of right and wrong, of wisdom, chih. Man has these four germs just as he has four limbs. For a man possessing these four germs to deny his own potentialities is for him to cripple himself... If a man is able to develop all these four germs that he possesses, it will be like a fire starting up or a spring coming through.3

The term hsin (/u'), which I translate as "mind," is rendered by others as "feelings" (Legge and Dobson) and as "heart" (Lau). The term was used in early China to denote many things, including "intentions," "feelings," "the location of the desires, cognitive activity, evaluative activity," and also referred to

"tendencies" or "potential behavior."4

When Mencius spoke about the four "minds" or "feelings" inherent in all men in the passages quoted above, he was speaking of two essentially different sets of things. Jen-mind, which "cannot bear to see others suffer" or is

"compassionate," and //-mind, which is courteous, modest, and proper in conduct, describe the mind's innate moral qualities. The remaining two, namely y/-mind, which is capable of feeling "shame and dislike" based on man's innate sense of yi (Justice) and can take action as man's innate moral nature dictates, and c/7/77-mind, which evaluates and discriminates between right and wrong, together make up the evaluating function of the mind.

The four "minds" are not, therefore, separable from each other, for they are only four parts or aspects of each man's single mind. Man's unique mind -

31 which is yen, meaning "humanhearted," "benevolent," "compassionate,"

"commiserate"; and //, meaning "proper," "moderate," "courteous in conduct" in quality - can fully express itself if the mind’s yi and chih elements, which discriminate and evaluate, are there to guide it. The possession of this four- elemented mind is what makes man different from other creatures, according to

Mencius.

Besides man's appetitive instincts of the senses and his inherently alert and virtuous mind, Mencius introduces yet a third element as also innately present in man's nature. He calls is "hao jan chih chT

This phrase is translated variously as "vast passion-nature or spirit" (Legge),

"the flood-like chT (Lau), and "greater physical vigor" (Dobson). The word ch'i

(®/) alone means "air," "temper," "breath," "steam," "force," "lifegiving

principle," or "energy."5 I would render it as an "expansive energy."

According to Mencius, it is this "expansive energy" in man's nature that

carries out what the mind has decided. It is a kind of energy which, if untamed,

can be destructive to man's moral well-being, but if nourished and guided by

the jen-yi mind as naturally as the trees of the Niu mountains,6 it will assuredly

make man achieve his moral excellence. Mencius said:

The mind gives order to the chi and the ch!i is that which fills our physical frame. The mind is in charge, the ctQ its subordinate. For this reason I say, 'He who has firm grip in his mind should do no harm to his ch'i.' I am adept in the cultivation of the hao ian chih ch'i. (M: II. A. 2. ix)

When asked what he meant by the hao jan chih ch'i, Mencius said:

It is difficult to explain. This is a ctQ which is, in the highest degree, vast and unyielding. Nourish it with integrity and place no obstacle in its path and it will fill the space between Heaven and Earth. It is a ctQ which unites rightness and the Way. Deprive it of these falls below the standard set in one's mind, it will collapse... You must work at it and never let it out

32 of your mind. At the same time, while you must never let it out of vour mind, you must not forcibly help it grow either. (M: II. A. 2. xii-xvi: Lau)

Although Confucius implicitly and Mencius explicitly agree that all men are equally endowed with the jen-yi mind or moral tendencies in their nature, they both note that not all men are equally successful in nourishing them to their fullest manifestation in actual life. Confucius said, "By nature men are nearly alike; by practice, they get to be wide apart." (A: XVII. 2: Legge) Mencius said,

"Jen, yi, //, and chih are not infused into us from without. We are certainly furnished with them... Men differ, some by twice, some by five times, and some by an incalculable amount, in their ability to exploit this endowment." (M: VI. A.

6: Legge & Dobson)

Moreover, Confucius had something more to say about the varied capacity in individuals in cultivating the moral seed to its fullest fruition as follows. He said,

Those who are born with the possession of knowledge are the highest class of men. Those who learn, and so, readily, get possession of knowledge, are the next. Those who are dull and stupid, and yet compass the learning, are another class next to these. As to those who are dull and stupid and yet do not learn - they are the lowest of the people. (A: xvi. 9: Legge)

Mencius pointed out that some are great and some are mediocre in achieving moral excellence by their own choice.

Kung-tu said, "All are equally men, but some are great men, and some are little men; how is this?" Mencius replied, "Those who follow that part of themselves which is great are great men; those who follow that part which is little are little men." (M: VI. A. 15: Legge)

The meaning of this statement is clear. The man who takes care of his innately

moral mind to its fullest natural growth is the great man.

It is interesting to note that Hsun Tzu (born ca. 312 B.C.), the most

prominent Confucian thinker of the third century B.C., differed with Mencius by

asserting that the nature of man is evil. He devoted an entire chapter entitled

33 "Man's Evil Nature" to prove his point. At any rate, he, too, like Confucius and Mencius, put his faith in education which alone can transform man’s evil nature to a moral nature. The following excerpts from the chapter represent his view.

Man's nature is evil; goodness is the result of conscious activity The nature of man is such that he is born with a fondness for profit. If he indulges this fondness, it will lead him into wrangling and strife and all sense of courtesy and humility will disappear. He is born with the feelings of envy and hate, and if he indulges these, they will lead him into violence and crime, and all sense of loyalty and good faith with disappear. Man is born with the desires of the eyes and ears, with a fondness for beautiful sights and sounds. If he indulges these, they will lead him into license and wantonness, and all ritual principles and correct forms will be lost. Hence, any man who follows his nature and indulges his emotions will inevitably become involved in wrangling and strife, will violate the forms and rules of society, and will end as a criminal. Therefore, man must first be transformed by the instruction of a teacher and guided by ritual principles, and only then will he be able to observe the dictates of courtesy and humility, obey the forms and rules of society, and achieve order. It is obvious from this, then, that man's nature is evil, and that his goodness is the result of conscious activity.7

Mencius states that man is capable of learning because his nature is good, but I say that this is wrong. It indicates that he has not really understood man's nature nor distinguished properly between the basic nature and conscious activity. The nature is that which is given by Heaven; you cannot learn it, you cannot acquire it by effort. Ritual principles, on the other hand, are created by sages; you can learn to apply them, you can work to bring them to completion. That part of man which cannot be learned or acquired by effort is called the nature; that part of him which can be acquired by learning and brought to completion by effort is called conscious activity. This is the difference between nature and conscious activity.8

The man in the street can become a Yu. What does this mean? What made the sage emperor Yu a Yu, I would reply, was the fact that he practiced benevolence and righteousness and abided by the proper rules and standards. If this is so, then benevolence, righteousness, and proper standards must be based upon principles which can be known and practiced. Any man in the street has the essential faculties needed to understand benevolence, righteousness, and proper standards, and the potential ability to put them into practice. Therefore, it is clear that he can become a Yu.

34 If the man in the street applies himself to training and study, concentrates his mind and will, and considers and examines thinas carefully, continuing his efforts over a long period of time and accumulating good acts without stop, then he can achieve a godlike understanding and form a triad with Heaven and earth. The sage is a man who has arrived where he has through the accumulation of qood acts.9

Whether or not man's nature is innately good or evil as disputed among the classical Confucians, they all agreed that his nature could be guided to attain its moral excellence.

They also agreed on the importance of the socio-political, economic, and cultural environment and conditions for the proper education of man. Mencius was particularly aware of the vulnerability of man's nature to negative circumstantial conditions, especially economic hardship. He said:

In good years the children of the people are most of them good, while in bad years the most of them abandon themselves to evil. It is not owing to any difference of their natural powers conferred by Heaven that they are thus different. The abandonment is owing to the circumstances through which they allow their minds to be ensnared and drowned in evil. (M: VI. A. 7: Legge)

To the hungry all food is sweet; to the thirsty all water is sweet. Such cannot judge when food and drink is as it should be. Their hunger and thirst blunt their palate. And it is not surely only the mouth and belly that are affected by hunger and thirst; they affect the minds of men. (M: VII. A. 27: Dobson)

Hsun Tzu concluded the chapter on "Man's Evil Nature" with the following

words.

...a man, no matter how fine his nature or how keen his mind, must seek a worthy teacher to study under and good companions to associate with. If he studies under a worthy teacher, he will be able to hear about the ways of Yao, Shun, Yu, and T’ang, and if he associates with good companions, he will be able to observe conduct that is loyal and respectful. Then, although he is not aware of it, he will day by day progress in the practice of benevolence and righteousness, for the environment he is subjected to will cause him to progress. But if a man associates with men who are not good, then he will hear only deceit and lies and will see only conduct that is marked by wantonness, evil, and greed. Then, although he is not aware of it, he himself will soon be in danger of severe punishment for the environment he is subjected to will cause him to be in danger. An old

35 text says, "If you do not know a man, look at his friends; if you do not know a ruler, look at his attendants." Environment is the important thina' Environment is the important thing!™ K y

As to the question of why some men are incapable of becoming moral, the classical Confucians imply that some men are outside of the tenet that all men can be brought to follow the right and moral way through training and the examples set by the sages.11 Although some passages in the Four Bonks cause us to question the Confucians as to why men come with different degrees of will and why Heaven produces inferior and superior men, despite their consistent assertion of the natural goodness of all men and "all are equally men," there is no clear answer given by either Confucius or Mencius, except the explanations that only a lack of will and adverse circumstances can be the causes for the wrong way taken by many.12

In the Dialogues

In Plato's view, man shares with other animals both the appetitive and

spirited parts of his nature, but he is different from other animals in one respect:

he possesses the philosophic or calculating part which enables him to reason.

In the creation myth in the Timaeus. Plato alludes that the human race

was created by the Demiurge, who was "Good" and desired "that all things

should come as near as possible to being like himself." (29 E: Cornford) The

Demiurge further thought that:

Among things that are by nature visible, no work that is without intelligence will ever be better than one that has intelligence, when each is taken as a whole, and moreover that intelligence cannot be present in anything apart from soul. In virtue of this reasoning, when he framed the universe, he fashioned reason within soul and soul within body, to the end that the work he accomplished might be by nature as excellent and perfect as possible. This, then, is how we must say, according to the likely account, that this world came to be, by the god’s providence, in very truth a living creature with soul and reason. (30B: Cornford)

36 In the same dialogue, Plato also points out that at the creation all souls were equal in quality, having been created with the same ingredients, but that since then there has been a steady evolution in the qualities of the souls into three classes - gold, silver," and "brass," thus implying that, though all men were created by the same god identically with the same ingredients and methods, the original men's descendants are no longer equal in the quality of their souls. In fact, he even suggested that the immoral men were created by the lesser gods.13

Plato explains the "appetitive" element of the soul as that part "with which it feels hunger and thirst and is distracted by sexual passion and all the other desires, we will call irrational, associated with pleasure in the replenishment of certain wants." (R: IV. 439: Cornford) Explaining this element further, Plato said:

[This element was] so multifarious that we could find no single appropriate name; we called it after its chief and most powerful characteristic, "appetite," because of the intensity of all the appetites connected with eating and drinking and sex and so on. We also called it money-loving, because money is the principal means of satisfying desires of this kind. Gain is the source of its pleasures and the object of its affection; so "money-loving" or "gain-loving" might be the best single expression to sum up the nature of this part of the soul for the purpose of our discussion. (R: 580 E - 581 A: Cornford)

This element in the soul is so powerful that, if uncontrolled, it easily deprives a man of his humanness. "The appetites, which form the greater part of each man’s soul and are by nature insatiably covetous," therefore, must be watched by the other two parts of the soul,

...lest this part, by battening on the pleasures that are called bodily, should grow so great and powerful that it will no longer keep to its own work, but will try to enslave the others and usurp a dominion to which it has no right, thus turning the whole of life upside down. (R: 422 A - B: Cornford)

37 In Plato s view, there are desires or appetites which are necessary and good, and desires or appetites which are unnecessary and bad. He defines the necessary and the unnecessary appetites in the following passages.

There are appetites which cannot be got rid of, and there are also those which it does us good to fulfill. Our nature cannot help seeking to satisfy both these kinds, so they rnay fairly be described as necessary. On the other hand, "unnecessary" would be the right name for all appetites which can be got rid of by early training and which do us no good and in some cases do harm. (R: 588 D: Cornford)

The appetites for food and sex, though important for man's survival and the preservation of his species, if fed immoderately as the insatiable appetites demand, would become "unnecessary" appetites. In his words:

The desire to eat enough plain food - just bread and meat - to keep in health and good condition may be called necessary. In the case of bread the necessity is twofold, since it not only does us good but is indispensable to life; whereas meat is only necessary in so far as it helps to keep us in good condition. Beyond these simple needs the desire for a whole variety of luxuries is unnecessary... Further, these unnecessary appetites might be called expensive, whereas the necessary ones are rather profitable, as helping a man to do his work. The same distinctions could be drawn in the case of sexual appetite and all the rest. (R: 599 A - B: Cornford)

One of the reasons for Plato’s condemnation of democracy is that it has limitless tolerance for man's unnecessary appetites in the pursuit of insatiable and self-destructive ends. He described the typical young man without much moral training, growing up in a democratic state in the following passages of the

Republic.

When he is told that some pleasures should be sought and valued as arising from desires of a higher order, others chastised and enslaved because the desires are base, he will shut the gates of the citadel against the messengers of truth, shaking his head and declaring that one appetite is as good as another and all must have their equal rights. So he spends his days indulging the pleasure of the moment, now intoxicated with wine and music, and then taking to a spare diet and drinking nothing but water; one day in hard training, the next doing nothing at all, the third apparently immersed in study. Every now and then he takes a part in politics, leaping to his feet to say or do whatever

38 c°mes into his head. Or he will set out to rival someone he admires a sokJier it may be, or, if the fancy takes him, a man of business His life is subject to no order or restraint, and he has no wish to change an existence which he calls pleasant, free, and happy. That well describes the life of one whose motto is liberty and eoualitv (R: 561 A - C: Cornford) H y>

Plato also described how uncontrolled appetites could make men in governing positions tyrannical and possessive by taking away from their fellow men anything by deceit or force to satisfy their appetites. And the most tyrannic will even punish his parents and the state, if they do not offer the things to satisfy his appetites. The man who is dominated by the unnecessary appetites is necessarily always poverty-ridden and is maddened by desires and loves.14 In sum, a man whose unnecessary appetites in his soul are not controlled through moral training can be likened to a tyrant,

...even if he doesn't seem so to someone, in truth a real slave... and with his desires getting no kind of satisfaction, he shows that he is most in need of the most things and poor in truth, if one knows how to look at a soul as a whole. Throughout his entire life he is full of fear, overflowing with convulsions and pains. (R: 579 E: Bloom)

The second part of man's nature or soul is "spirited." This part can make man, like a well-bred watchdog, having "quick senses to detect an enemy, swiftness in pursuing him, and strength, if they have to fight when they have caught him." (R: 375 A: Cornford) Courage has its source in this part of the soul, and the "spirited" soul is fearless and invincible. This element is not exclusively in man's nature alone, but in other animals' nature also. Plato talks about well-bred dogs and horses, too, as possessing this quality in their nature.

This is the part in every man's soul which is most clearly observable from the time of his birth. "For, even in little children, one could see that they are full of

spirit straight from birth." (R: 411 A: Bloom)

This element makes man competitive, ambitious, passionate, and loving

of "victory and honour.Through or from this part of man s nature, anger,

39 too, makes its appearance, waging war against the appetitive part in his nature and sometimes against himself for not following the commands of the rational or philosophic part of the soul.16 In Plato’s words:

The savage stems from the spirited part of their nature, which if rightly trained, would be courageous; but, if raised to a higher pitch than it ouqht to have, would be likely to become cruel and harsh. (R: 410 D: Bloom)

This is the part of the soul which needs to be controlled so that its quick temperament, irritability, crudeness, and cowardice will not dominate one’s life.

This part of the soul, if uncultivated by certain softening and harmonizing influences, makes man a misologist and "he no longer makes any use of persuasion by means of speech but goes about everything with force and savageness, like a wild beast; and he lives ignorantly and awkwardly without rhythm or grace." (R: 411 E: Bloom)

If a man is driven by this part of the soul alone, the true pleasures of life will be lost. Plato wrote:

Take, again, the satisfaction of the spirited element in our nature. Must not that be no less illusory, when a man seeks, at all costs, to gratify his ambition by envy, his love of victory by violence, and his ill-temper by outbursts of passion, without sense of reason? What then? May we boldly assert that all the desires both of the gain-loving and of the ambitious part of our nature will win the truest pleasures of which they are capable, if they accept the guidance of knowledge and reason and pursue only those pleasures which wisdom approves? Such pleasures will be true, because truth is their guide, and will also be proper to their nature, if it is fact that a thing always finds in what is best for it something akin to its real self. (R: 586 C - D: Cornford)

Plato warned that the "spirited" part of man's nature could be lost altogether if he let the part which is "gain-loving" or money-loving invade and dominate his soul. He wrote: "Humbled by poverty, he thrusts love of honour

and spiritedness headlong out of the throne of his soul, he turns greedily to

money-making," and makes the philosophic and spirited parts the slaves of the

appetitive part of his soul. This is not difficult to see, according to Plato, for most

40 of us are lovers of gain and money.17 But the spirited part, which is "by nature an auxiliary to the philosophic part, if it is not corrupted by bad reading," can make the whole soul come to the knowledge of the Good and do what the Good dictates.18

The last but the most important part of the soul is "whereby it reflects or calculates, therefore, rational." (R: 439 D: Bloom) It possesses within it the knowledge of that which is beneficial for each of the three parts and for the whole soul. Moreover, it is this part of the soul which desires to know wisdom,

"not of one part and not another, but of all of it.” (R: 475 B: Bloom) It is this element in the soul which cannot only grasp "what is always the same in all respects" but also loves to learn of the eternal and unchanging things. The philosophic part of the soul is what makes man different from and superior to other animals, for it alone can command and guide the other parts of the soul to work in harmony and cooperation for the happiness of his existence as an individual and as a member of his society. Plato wrote:

"Then," said I [Socrates], "may we not confidently declare that in both the gain-loving and the contentious part of our nature all the desires that wait upon knowledge and reason, and, pursuing their pleasures in conjunction with them, take only those pleasures which reason approves, will, since they follow truth, enjoy the truest pleasures, so far as that is possible for them. Then, when the entire soul accepts the guidance of the wisdom- loving part and is not filled with inner dissension, the result for each part is that it in all other respects keeps to its own task and is just, and likewise that each enjoys its own proper pleasures and the best pleasures and, so far as such a thing is possible, the truest." (R: 586 D - 587 A: Shorey)

This is the best and most important part among the three parts that make up the

human soul and can be ruined if it is not properly taken care of and instructed.

Although every man has the philosophic part in his soul, Plato thought that not

all men are able to develop it to its full capacity for the following reasons.

41 Our account of the true lover of knowledge is one born to strive towards reality, who cannot linger among the multiplicity of things which men believe to be real, but holds on his way with a passion that will not faint or fail until he has laid hold upon the essential nature of each thing with that part of his soul which can apprehend reality because of its affinity therewith; and when he has by that means approached real being and entered into union with it, the offspring of this marriage is intelligence and truth, so that at least, having found knowledge and true life and nourishment, he is at rest from his travail... Nor is there any need to prove once more that a whole array of other qualities must go with the philosophic nature: you will remember how it entailed courage, magnanimity, quickness to learn, and a good memory. (R: 490 B - C- Cornford)

This part is ordained to strive entirely toward knowing the highest knowledge which will lead man to his moral excellence; therefore, the other two parts of his nature must be made to cooperate with it by sheer determination and dedication. Plato was certain that man is capable of making all parts of his soul cooperate to make his whole being just and excellent. In the Timaeus. we read the following.

This is not true, for it is to the heavens, whence the soul first came to birth, that the divine part attaches the head or root of us and keeps the whole body upright. Now if a man is engrossed in appetites and ambitions and spends all his pains upon these, all his thoughts must needs be mortal... But if his heart has been set on the love of learning and true wisdom and he has exercised that part of himself above all, he is surely bound to have thoughts immortal and divine... By learning to know the harmonies and revolutions of the world, he should bring the intelligent part, according to its pristine nature, into the likeness of that which intelligence discerns, and thereby win the fulfillment of the best life set by the gods before mankind both for this present time and for the time to come. (90 A - D: Cornford)19

Although Plato maintains that all wrongdoing is involuntary, because all men will do the good and also no man who knows the right will do wrong, he does not ignore the importance of environment for man's education, indicating how an unhealthy and decadent socio-cultural environment and economic conditions can blind man's philosophic soul and even damage it permanently.

To Plato, the human nature or soul is something living that requires the right

42 conditions and environment to grow to its expected excellence. The

meanin9 "rearing,” "nursing," "nourishing," "bringing up," or

"tending," which Plato uses to express his idea of education, implies it.20

Having pronounced then the existing socio-political and cultural conditions and

environment as unsuitable for the nurturing of man's soul, Plato gave himself

the task of constructing his visionary utopian state, the Republic, which would

control and create, if necessary by force, the conditions and atmosphere

suitable for the natural and healthy growth of man's soul, especially its

philosophic or rational part. In the Goraias. Plato wrote:

People do say they have made the city great; but that it is with the swelling of an imposthume due to those men of the former time, this they do not perceive. For with no regard for temperance and justice they have stuffed the city with harbours and arsenals and walls and tribute and suchlike trash; and so whenever that access of debility comes they will lay the blame on the advisers who are with them at the time, and belaud Themistocles and Cimon and Pericles, who caused all the trouble; and belike they will lay hold of you, if you are not on your guard, and my good friend Alcibiades, when they are losing what they had originally as well as what they have acquired, though you are not the authors, except perhaps part-authors, of the mischief. And indeed there is a senseless thing which I see happening now, and hear of, in connexion with the men of former times. For I observe that whenever the state proceeds against one of her statesmen as a wrongdoer, they are indignant and protest loudly against such monstrous treatment: after all their long and valuable services to the state they are unjustly ruined at her hands, so they protest. But the whole thing is a lie; since there is not a single case in which a ruler of a city could ever be unjustly ruined by the very city that he rules. For it is very much the same with pretenders to statesmanship as with professors of sophistry. The sophists, in fact, with all their other accomplishments, act absurdly in one point: claiming to be teachers of virtue, they often accuse their pupils of doing them an injury by cheating them of their fees and otherwise showing no recognition of the good they have done them. Now what can be more unreasonable than this plea? That men, after they have been made good and just, after all their injustice has been rooted out by their teacher and replaced by justice, should be unjust through something that they have not! Does not this seem to you absurd, my dear friend! (518 E - 519 D: Lamb)

Plato explains this point more in the Republic. Everyone, I think, would agree that a nature with all the qualities we required to make the perfect philosopher is a rare growth, seldom seen among men Consider, how many grave dangers threaten to destrov these few. Strangest of all, every one of those qualities we approved - courage, temperance, and all the rest - tends to ruin its possessor and to wrest his mind away from philosophy... And, besides this, all the good things of like, as they are called, corrupt and distract the soul: beauty wealth, strength, powerful connexions, and so forth - ...The matter will be clear enough, and what I have just said will not seem so strange, when you have grasped the underlying principle. We know it to be true of any seed or growing thing, whether plant or animal, that if it fails to find its proper nourishment or climate or soil then the more vigorous it is, the more it will lack the qualities it should possess. Evil is a worse enemy to the good than to the indifferent; so it is natural that bad conditions of nurture should be peculiarly uncongenial to the finest nature and that it should come off worse under them than natures of an insignificant order... Is not the same principle true of the mind, Adeimantus: if their early training is bad, the most gifted turn out the worst. Great crimes and unalloyed wickedness are the outcome of a nature full of generous promise, ruined by bad upbringing; no great harm, or great good either, will ever come of a slight or feeble disposition... Or do you hold the popular belief that, here and there, certain young men are demoralized by the private instructions of some individual sophist? Does that sort of influence amount to much? Is not the public itself the greatest of all sophists, training up young and old, men and women alike, into the most accomplished specimens of the character it desires to produce? Whenever the populace crowds together at any public gathering, in the Assembly, the law-courts, the theatre, or the camp, and sits there clamouring its approval or disapproval, both alike excessive, of whatever is being said or done; booing and clapping till the rocks ring and the whole place redoubles the noise of their applause and outcries. In such a scene what do you suppose will be a young man's state of mind? What sort of private instruction will have given him the strength to hold out against the force of such a torrent, or will save him from being swept away down the stream, until he accepts all their notions of right and wrong, does as they do, and comes to be just such a man as they are? (R: 491 B - 492 C: Cornford)

Then the nature which we assumed in the philosopher, if it receives the proper teaching, must needs grow and attain to consummate excellence, but, if it be sown and planted and grown in the wrong environment, the outcome will be quite the contrary unless some god comes to the rescue. (R: 492 A: Shorey)

There are passages in the dialogues which suggest Plato's assessment of men as incapable of ruling themselves21 and his suspicion of an irrational

44 and potentially evil secondary soul 22 but his fundamental faith in man’s power to develop his inherently good and philosophic nature in his soul to its highest excellence predominates throughout his works. Through a proper training, the triumph of man’s philosophic soul over all other human desires and appetites is firmly expected by Plato, thus convincing his readers of the definite possibility of having the philosopher-kings, who will perform their duties reflecting the knowledge of the Good they have acquired.

In summary

The purpose of this chapter is to answer the following two questions: first, "How did our thinkers of China and Athens understand human nature?" and second, "What did they say about man's capacity to learn to be good?"

To answer the first, both groups agree that man’s nature is comprised of three parts: the reasoning, the appetitive, and the spirited, and the reasoning part is what distinguishes man from all animals. To the second question, too, they agree that man can learn to be good because he is endowed not only with the reasoning part that also comprehends, remembers, compares, judges, and above all desires for the Good, but also with the seed of goodness or innate goodness. For man is of the Good and by the Good. In their view, however, the acquisition of full knowledge of the Good is difficult, requiring many years of study. Therefore, it is not for everyone. It is for an exceptional few whose power of reasoning is far above ordinary men's with the love and determination to pursue the Good, and it is they who should be rulers.

They also agree that the appetitive and the spirited parts are natural and indispensable to make man whole, but that they must be guided by the

reasoning part to be good and human. If these parts are unattended by the

45 reasoning part, man is not much different from other animals. The spirited part, if it is in tune with the reasoning part that seeks the Good, provides man with energy and courage to do what is good and controls the appetitive part, which is the strongest and the most demanding of the three parts of man. Therefore although the primary task of education is to help develop man's reasoning mind to obtain full knowledge of the Good, it must also help him develop simultaneously the other two parts, so that all three parts can function in perfect

harmony and coordination to make him wholly of the Good or morally excellent.

Lastly, both groups point out the fragility of man’s nature, which is pliant

and susceptible especially in man’s infancy and youth to all sorts of influences the world presents. Therefore, they emphasize the importance of right

endowment, right teachers and friends, right courses of study, and right

methods in the education of man.

46 CHAPTER III

THE AIM OF EDUCATION

In the Four Books

The broad aim of the Confucian education system is twofold. One aim is to help the student cultivate his innate virtue or jen-yi mind to its fullest and the other is to qualify him to serve the people by applying his jen-yi mind so cultivated in real life as an official of state. Mencius said:

J&n is man’s mind and yi is man's path. How lamentable is it to neglect the path and not pursue it, to lose the mind and not know to see it again! The whole purpose of education is nothing else but to seek for the lost mind. (M: VI. A. 11: Legge)

He further said:

Now men possess a moral nature, but if they are well fed, warmly clad, and comfortably lodged, without being taught at the same time, they become almost like the beast.

These statements indicate that helping man recover his "lost mind," and

cultivate his mind's innate jen-yi, is one part of the twofold aim of education, and

the following statements explain the other part.1 Confucius said: "Though a

man might have learned extensively, if he cannot serve the people, what good

is his learning?" (A: XIII. 5.: Legge) Tsze Hsia, one of his disciples, agreed

with him and said: "Having completed his studies, the learner should apply

himself to be an officer." (A: XIX. 13: Legge) Mencius, after investigating all

the types of schools known to him in his days, stated that the aim of all such

schools was to make the student understand human relations so that those who

had been educated in them could rule the people better.2

47 Having diagnosed the loss of the jen-yi mind in men of the ruling class as the cause of all the woes in the world, the classical Confucian teachers set out to educate the future officials to recover the lost mind fully in order to perform their public duties in jen-yi.

Although all men possess the jen-yi mind, not all of them are endowed

equally with certain intellectual and mental qualities necessary to make it

develop to its fullest and applicable capacity. Moreover, in their view, most men

are not intellectually ambitious enough to want to know the root and meaning of

everything in the world. Mencius said: "To act without understanding, and to do

so habitually without examination, pursuing the proper path all the life without

knowing its nature - thus is the way of multitudes." (M: VII. A. 5: Legge)

Therefore, neither Confucius nor Mencius felt it necessary to educate everyone

to have an ideal state. They were realists enough to know that a state must

necessarily be composed of groups of men with different occupational

preferences to make it function. However, they never considered the people,

who were not getting the kind of education they were giving, unimportant.

Mencius said:

There are affairs of great men, and there are affairs of small men. Moreover, it is necessary for each man to use the products of all the hundred crafts. If everyone must make everything he uses, the Empire will be led along the path of incessant toil. Hence it is said, "There are those who use their minds and there are those who use their muscles. The former rule; the latter are ruled. Those who rule are supported by those who are ruled." This is a principle accepted by the whole Empire. (M: III. A. 6: Lau)

Accordingly, the Confucian education was for the future members of the ruling

class, and the Confucian teachers were convinced that if they could help those

men who were after the knowledge and cultivation of jen-yi in their persons and

who would use their enlightened minds when called to perform their public

duties, the realization of a virtuous state was a definite possibility.

48 The students so educated would be the possessors of the knowledge of jen-yi and were called chun-tzu (%, J-). The term has been translated as

"the men of outstanding virtue," "gentlemen," "superior men," Princely men," and

so on; and the Confucian teachers identified some essential things that they

must let these men learn know while educating them.3 First, they let them know

that the goal of making the world jen-yi or virtuous was dependent totally on

them and must be pursued in a correct order. In the Great Learning we read-

Things have their root and their branches. Affairs have their end and their beginning. To know what is first and what is last will lead near to what is taught in the Great Learning. The ancients who wished to illustrate illustrious virtue throughout the kingdom, first ordered well their own States. Wishing to order well their States, they first regulated their families. Wishing to regulate their families, they first cultivated their person... From the Son of Heaven down to the mass of the people, all must consider the cultivation of the person the root of everything besides. (GL: 3, 4, & 6: Legge)4

They taught them also the importance of making their commitment to the

cultivation of jen-yi in their persons true and sincere and their desire to know

Heaven and earth and everything in between extensive and thorough. We

further read in the Great Learning:

...Wishing to cultivate their persons, they first rectified their hearts. Wishing to rectify their hearts, they first sought to be sincere in their thoughts. Wishing to be sincere in their thoughts, they first extended to the utmost their knowledge. Such extension of knowledge lay in the investigation of things. (GL: 4: Legge)

Things being investigated, knowledge became complete. Their knowledge being complete, their thoughts were sincere. Their thoughts being sincere, their hearts were then rectified. Their hearts being rectified, their persons were cultivated. Their persons being cultivated, their families were regulated. Their families being regulated, their States were rightly governed. Their States being rightly governed, the whole kingdom was made tranquil and happy. (GL: 4 & 5: Legge)

In the following quotes from the Four Books we read how Confucius and

Mencius described the character of chun-tzu and at the same time how they

49 taught by example some essential intellectual skills of observation, discrimination, analysis, and comparison in learning from Nature, people, and books, to grasp the jen-yi principle in the universe. In the Book of Mencius we read:

...The disciple Hsu said, 'Chung-ni [Confucius] often praised water, saying, O water! O water!" What did he find in water to praise?' Mencius replied, There is a spring of water; how it gushes out! It rests not day nor night. It fills up every hole, and then advances, flowing on to the four seas. Such is water having a spring! It was this which he found in it to praise. But suppose that the water has no spring. In the seventh and eighth months when the rain falls abundantly, the channels in the fields are filled, but their being dried up again may be expected in a short time. So a superior man is ashamed of a reputation beyond his merits!' (M: IV. B. 18: Legge)

Confucius said:

I am able to discourse on the rites of the Hsia, but the state of Ch’i does not furnish sufficient supporting evidence; I am able to discourse on the rites of the Yin, but the state of Sung does not furnish sufficient supporting evidence. This is because there are not enough records and men of erudition. Otherwise I would be able to support what I say with evidence. (A: III. 9: Lau)

See what a man does. Mark his motives. Examine in what things he rests. How can a man conceal his character! (A: 11.10: Legge)

There may be those who act without knowing why. I do not do so. Hearing much and selecting what is good and following it; Seeing much and keeping it in memory: - this is the second style of knowledge. (A: VII. 27: Legge)

When I walk along with two others, they may serve me as my teachers. I will select their good qualities and follow them, their bad qualities and avoid them. (A: VII. 21: Legge)

Learning from direct contact with men and things, too, requires the

discriminating use of one's mind in order to gain, for example, the knowledge of

human relationships correctly and unbiased. The following lines from the

Mencius show the way Mencius exercised his inquisitive and discerning mind to

get the truth out of a situation.

50 Kao Tzu said, The music of Yu surpassed that of Kinq Wen ’ 'What makes you say that?' said Mencius. 'It is the bell-rope. It is almost worn through.’ 'That is not sufficient as evidence. Do you imagine that the rut through the city gates was made by a single pair of horses'?’ (M- VII R 22: Lau) ' v

Another thing they urged their students was to be intellectually honest and courageous. Confucius said, ’’Yu, shall I tell you what it is to know? To say you know when you know, and to say you do not know when you do not, that is knowledge." (A: 11.7: Lau) Again, he said, "When you have faults, do not fear to rectify or abandon them.” (A: I. 8. IX. 24: Legge) He said also that "to see what is right and not to do it is want of courage." (A: II. 24. ii: Legge) Confucius was certain that intellectual honesty would reward the learner with peace of mind and the respect of others. We read in the Analects the following conversation.

Ssu-ma Niu asked about the gentleman. The Master said, 'The gentleman is free from worries and fears.' 'In that case, can a man be said to be a gentleman simply because he is free from worries and fears?' The Master said, 'If, on examining himself, a man finds nothing to reproach himself for, what worries and fears can he have?’ (A: XII. 5: Lau)

The Confucian teachers also let the student know that his education was not for his own moral improvement alone, but for the well-being of the state as well. Therefore, learning and practicing what one came to know to be jen-yi were the two things inseparable throughout the life of chun-tzu. Mencius identified the sage king Shun as one of the model rulers who had people's affection for his understanding of human relations. He said: "Shun understood the way of things and had keen insight into human relationships. He followed the path of morality, jen-yi. He did not just put morality into practice." (M: IV. B.

19: Lau) Mencius explains further what exactly the king Shun did with his

subjects.

51 ■ Hc\UA,?hi t£?ught the people how t0 cu|t'vate land and the five kinds of grain. When these ripened, the people multiplied. This is the wav of the common people: once they have a full belly and warm clothes on their back they degenerate to the level of animals if they are allowed to lead idle lives, without education and discipline. They gave the sage King further cause for concern, and so he appointed Hsieh as the Minister of Education whose duty was to teach the people human relationships: love between father and son duty between ruler and subject, distinction between husband and wife, precedence of the old over the young, and faith between friends (M- III A. 4. viii: Lau)

Confucius, too, asked of his students to attain correct understanding and handling of human relationships based on the principles of jen-yi. He said:

When one cultivates to the utmost the principles of his nature, and exercises them on the principle of reciprocity, he is not far from the path. What you do not like when done to yourself, do not do to others. In the way of the superior man there are four things, to not one of which have I as yet attained. To serve my father, as I would require my son to serve me: to this I have not attained; to serve my prince, as I would require my minister to serve me: to this I have not attained; to serve my elder brother, as I would require my younger brother to serve me: to this I have not attained; to set example in behaving to a friend, as I would require him to behave to me: to this I have not attained... (DM: XIII. 3 - 4: Legge)

The important moral qualities the Confucian teachers wanted their future

chun-tzu to cultivate in their persons are described abundantly in the Four

Books. The following select quotes will show us what sort of men were to be

chun-tzu and why an ideal and virtuous state was totally dependent on chun-

tzu.

Chi Kang asked Confucius about government. Confucius replied, To govern means to rectify. If you lead on the people with correctness, who will dare not to be correct?’ Chi Kang, distressed about a number of thieves in the state inquired of Confucius how to do away with them, Confucius said, 'If you, sir, were not covetous, although you should reward them to do it, they would not steal.' Chi Kang asked Confucius about government, saying, 'What do you say to killing the unprincipled for the good of the principled?' Confucius replied, 'Sir, in carrying on your government, why should you use killing at all? Let your evinced desires be for what is good, and the people will

52 be good. The relation between superiors and interiors, is like that between the wind and the grass. The grass bends, when the wind blows across it.' (A: XVII, XVIII, & XIX: Legge)

Tsze-kung asked about government. The Master said The requisites of government are that there be sufficiency of food, sufficiency of military equipment, and the confidence of the people in their ruler ’ Tsze-kung said, 'If it cannot be helped, and one of these must be dispensed with, which of the three should be foregone first'?' The military equipment,' said the Master. Tsze-kung again asked, 'If it cannot be helped, and one of the remaining two must be dispensed with, which of them should be foregone?' The Master answered, 'Part with the food. From of old, death has been the lot of all men; but if the people have no faith in their rulers there is no standing for the State.’ (A: XII. 7: Legge)

Some more characteristic qualities of chun-tzu worthy of people's faith in them are described in the following ways.

The Master said of Tsze-chan that he had four of the characteristics of a superior man: - in his conduct of himself, he was humble; in serving his superiors, he was respectful; in nourishing the people, he was kind; in ordering the people, he was just. (A: V. 15: Legge)

The Master said, 'Now the man of perfect virtue, wishing to be established himself, seeks also to establish others; wishing to enlarge himself, he seeks also to enlarge others.' (A: VI. 28. ii: Legge)

The Master said, 'He who speaks without modesty will find it difficult to make his words good.' (A: XIV. 21: Legge)

The Master said, 'The superior man is modest in his speech but exceeds in his actions.' (A: XIV. 29: Legge)

Describing a distinguished gentleman - officer - The Master said, 'Now the man of distinction is solid and straightforward, and loves righteousness. He examines people's words, and looks at their countenances. He is anxious to humble himself to others. Such a man will be distinguished in the country; he will be distinguished in his clan. (A: XII. 20. v: Legge)

Remembering the exemplary chun-tzu of the past Mencius said:

The Great Shun had a still greater delight in what was good. He regarded virtue as the common property of himself and others, giving up his own way to follow that of others, and delighting to learn from others to practise what was good.

53 ,rt :T ,he ,iIn? when he p|0u9hed and sowed, exercised the potter's rnntfr,l^a? 3 flsher

Quoting Confucius, the Doctrine of the Mean has the following passages.

The Master said, There was Shun: - He indeed was greatly wise! Shun quGStlon othe[f ■ and t0 study their words, though they might be shallow He concealed what was bad in them, and displayed what was good. He took hold of their two extremes, determined the Mean and employed it 'n his government of the people. It was by this that he was Shun! (DM: VI: Legge)

A chun-tzu in dealing with the problems in the world, "does not set his mind either for anything or against anything; what is right he will follow." (A: IV

10: Legge) Mencius said: "A great man need not keep his word nor does he necessarily see his action through to the end. He aims only at what is right."

(M: IV. B. 11: Lau) Confucius said:

There are nine things the gentleman turns his thought to: to seeing clearly when he uses his eyes, to hearing acutely when he uses his ears, to looking cordial when it comes to his countenance, to appearing respectful when it comes to his demeanour, to being conscientious when he speaks, to being reverent when he performs his duties, to seeking advice when he is in doubt, to the consequences when he is enraged, and to what is right at the sight of gain. (A: XVI. 10: Lau)

Moreover, chun-tzu is not a man of pleasure and the easy life and does not seek unearned fame and wealth. He is a man who seeks to cultivate his inherent jen-yi, the cause of all other virtues, for a lasting pleasure for himself and others.

With the production of chun-tzu the aim of the Confucian education would be finally fulfilled and a virtuous state would become a definite possibility.

Confucius said, "Is virtue a thing remote? I wish to be virtuous and lo! virtue is at hand."5 He further said:

When one cultivates to the utmost the principles of his nature, and exercises them on the principle of reciprocity, he is not far from the path.

54 Xin^'Legge1)0' Whe" d°ne'° y0urself’ do not do 10 °

"We seek the things that are in ourselves," said Mencius.6

In the Dialogues

In the Plato describes his broad two-fold aim of education through the protagonist of the dialogue, the Athenian, as follows:

Mi. But we must not allow our description of education to remain indefinite. For at present, when censuring or commending a man's upbringing, we describe one man as educated and another as uneducated, though the latter may often be uncommonly well educated in the trade of a pedlar or a skipper, or some other similar occupation But, we, naturally, in our present discourse are not taking the view that such things as these make up education^ the education we speak of is training from childhood in goodness, which makes a man eagerly desirous of becoming a perfect citizen, understanding both how to rule and be ruled righteously.; This is the special form of nurture to which, as I suppose, our present argument would confine the term "education"; whereas an upbringing which aims only at money-making or physical strength, or even some mental accomplishment devoid of reason and justice, it would term vulgar and illiberal and utterly unworthy of the name "education." Let us not, however, quarrel over a name, but let us abide by the statement we agreed upon just now,'that those who are rightly educated become, as a rule, good, and that one should in no case disparage education, since it stands first among the finest gifts that are given to the best men; and if ever it errs from the right path, but can be put straight again, to this task every man, so long as he lives, must address himself with all his might. (643 D - 644 B: Bury)

In short, the aim of education is to instruct all children, both boys and girls, from their childhood up in goodness, so that they will become perfect citizens capable of leading their lives in justice whether as ruler or the ruled.

Accordingly, the system of education Plato sketches in the Republic and the

Laws is geared to attain its twofold aim: one is to help all future citizens to become just as far as they can, and the other is to help build a just state where the rulers and the ruled would do their separate and defined works justly for the common happiness and welfare of the state. Realizing that not all citizens are born to rule, Plato divides his system into two divisions: one is for all citizens,

55 and the other, for the special education of those select citizens who would be guardians or auxiliaries and rulers of the state.

Education of men and women begins from their time in their mothers’ wombs7 through their infancy, childhood, youth, and adulthood, subjecting them to carefully selected physical and fine arts courses according to their degrees of maturity for the sole purpose of making them good citizens. All children of the citizens, both boys and girls, are made to receive the common education between the ages of three and twenty in music and gymnastics, which includes story telling, singing, dancing, reciting epic and dramatic poetry, lyre playing, and rudiments of arithmetic and geometry, besides learning to read and write for three years between the ages of ten and thirteen. It is important to note that the emphasis placed on these two traditional subjects is no longer "music for

the soul and gymnastics for the body," but they are both for the soul.8

At the age of twenty, students are evaluated through tests for the purpose

of selecting those with the qualifications necessary for higher education, and

those who fail to pass the tests are guided to pursue other vocations most suited

to their natural talents. Now, the vastly diminished number of those who pass

the tests would receive higher education for the guardianship for ten years in

advanced branches of arithmetic, plane and solid geometry, astronomy and

harmonics, which are not to be pursued in a scientific spirit or for utility only, but

for the sole purpose of developing the reasoning faculty of the soul, which alone

would enable them to discern wisdom from ignorance, courage from cowardice,

temperance from licentiousness, justice from injustice, and good from evil.

At the conclusion of higher education a further selection of men and

women is conducted to give to those selected the "first of the finest gifts," the

highest education that will make them rulers, "the best men" and women of all

citizens. And those who are not selected, for they are proven to be more

56 spirited than thoroughly rational, would be assigned to be the guardians of auxiliary status.9

The first duty of men and women, especially those who would be rulers, is to be good and they must first of all examine their own souls to see how much they know about good and evil. Then, they must proceed to pursue the knowledge of the Good using vigorously the art of dialectic until they grasp it.

According to Plato's doctrine of reminiscence, man possesses a special capacity for the search after the knowledge of the Good and there is in his soul a certain power that will see the Good if only it is turned in the right direction. In the Republic, Socrates tells us how man is capable of rising from the darkness of the world of phenomena and the uncertainties of opinion into the radiant land of knowledge. He says:

Education is now what it is said to be by some, who profess to put knowledge into a soul which does not possess it, as if they could put sight into blind eyes. On the contrary, the soul of every man does possess the power of learning the truth and the organ to see it with; and that, just as one might have to turn the whole body round in order that the eye can bear to contemplate reality and that supreme splendor which we have called the Good. Hence there may well be an art whose aim would be to effect this very thing, the conversion of the soul, in the readiest way; not to put the power of sight into the soul's eye, which already has it, but to ensure that, instead of looking in the wrong direction, it is turned the way it ought to be. (518 B - D: Cornford)

In the Meno we read:

The soul is immortal and has been born many times and beheld all things both in this world and in the nether realms, so she has acquired knowledge of all and everything; so that it is no wonder that she be able to recollect all that she knew before about virtue and other things. For as all nature is akin, and the soul has learned all things, there is no reason why we should not, by remembering but one single thing - an act which men call learning - discover everything else, if we have courage and faint not in the search; since, it would seem, research and learning are wholly recollection. (81 C - D: Lamb)

Also in the Timaeus we read:

57 As concerning the most sovereign form of soul in us we must conceive that heaven has given it to each man as a guiding genius - that part which we say dwells in the summit of our body and lifts us from earth toward our celestial affinity, like a plant whose roots are not in earth but in the heavens. And this is most true, for it is to the heavens, whence the soul first came to birth, that the divine part attaches the head’or root of us and keeps the whole body upright. Now if a man is engrossed in appetites and ambitions and spends all his pains upon these all his thoughts must needs be mortal and, so far as that is possible ’ he cannot fall short of becoming mortal altogether, since he has nourished the growth of his mortality. But if his heart has been set on the love of learning and true wisdom and he has exercised that part of himself above all, he is surely bound to have thoughts immortal and divine, if he shall lay hold upon truth, nor can he fail to possess immortality in the fullest measure that human nature admits; and because he is always devoutly cherishing the divine part and maintaining the guardian genius that dwells with him in good estate, he must needs be happy above all. (90 A - C: Cornford)

As the above quotes clearly indicate, each human soul, coming from the immortal Good, already has the knowledge of the Good. And what education can do is help facilitate the soul to recollect it through the art of dialectical search for its own sake and for the good of the state. But, the search for the

Good is not for everyone. Although every human soul is endowed with intelligence, only a very few men and women are capable of developing it fully to apprehend the Good, which dwells in the metaphysical domain, and become philosopher-rulers.

Then, there are passages, such as the one quoted below, which warns those who would have the knowledge, not to relinquish their duties as rulers in the face of the seemingly impossible task of making their state just, and not to be driven by their own self interest. In the Republic we read:

One who has joined this small company and tasted the happiness that is their portion; who has watched the frenzy of the multitude and seen that there is no soundness in the conduct of public life, nowhere an ally at whose side a champion of justice could hope to escape destruction; but that, like a man fallen among wild beasts, if he should refuse to take part in their misdeeds and could not hold out alone against the fury of all, he would be destined, before he could be of any service to his country or his friends, to perish, having done no good to himself or to anyone else - one

58 who has weighed all this keeps quiet and goes his own way like the traveler who takes shelter under a wall from a driving storm of dust and hail; and seeing lawlessness spreading on all sides, is content if he can keep his hands clean from iniquity while his life lasts, and when the end comes take his departure, with good hopes, in serenity and peace (496 C - E: Cornford) '

Traditionally, the primary task of the guardians was to protect their state from enemies.10 But the guardians of Plato's ideal state must be able to make their state wise, courageous, temperate, just and good, as they themselves are, besides protecting it from enemies. They must make sure that the division of labor according to each citizen’s natural inclinations is adhered to strictly to give all citizens economic security, social justice, and unity;11 supervise the selection and education of citizens for various works that need to be performed;12 and

above all, examine themselves constantly to make sure that their own task of

guardianship is properly carried out. Having received the special education to

rule their state with the knowledge of the Good, they are not to allow themselves

to indulge in the bliss the attainment of that knowledge would certainly award,

but must engage themselves willingly in the task of establishing a just and good

state for the happiness of all citizens. After the parable of the cave, Socrates

exhorts:

...[t]hat the law is not concerned to make any one class specially happy, but to ensure the welfare of the commonwealth as a whole. By persuasion or constraint it will unite the citizens in harmony, making them share whatever benefits each class can contribute to common good; and its purpose in forming men of that spirit was not that each man should be left to go his own way, but that they should be instrumental in binding the community into one. (519 E- 520 A: Cornford)

A few lines later he gives additional reasons why the possessors of the

knowledge of the Good must also be rulers. He says:

We have brought you into existence for your country's sake as well as for your own, to be like leaders and king-bees in a hive; you have been better and more thoroughly educated than those others and hence you are more capable of playing your part both as men of thought and as men of action. You must go down, then, each in his turn, to live with the

59 rest and let your eyes grow accustomed to the darkness. You will then see a thousand times better than those who live there always' you will recognize every image for what it is and know what it represents because you have seen justice, beauty, and goodness in their reality and so you and we shall find life in our commonwealth no mere dream as it is in most existing states, where men live fighting one another about shadows and quarrelling for power, as if that were a great prize- whereas in truth government can be at its best and free from dissension only where the destined rulers are least desirous of holding office. (520 B - D-

Having attained the knowledge of the Good in that "purer world" and also having experienced the happiness and satisfaction that come with it, Socrates thinks that the philosophers "will assuredly approach office as an unavoidable necessity," but they must not refuse to share in the labours of state each in his turn and rule, because they "are really rich, not in gold, but in the wealth that makes happiness - a good and wise life."13

In short, the ultimate task of the philosopher-rulers is to make all citizens have the blessings of the Good. Therefore, the personal bliss they would have from the attainment of the knowledge of the Good must not be overindulged in order to fulfill the twofold aim of their special education, because the possibility of an ideal state is fully dependent on their application of the knowledge which they have finally attained.

In summary

The twofold aim of education of the Confucian and the Athenian thinkers is identical, that is, to help the future rulers of their respective states have the knowledge of the Good or the principle of moral excellence so that their states, too, will be good and morally excellent.

60 Each of the subjects of study and pedagogical methods they chose had its own specific aim, but they were all to fulfill the ultimate twofold aim of their education.

Theirs was a special education for a special class of men and women, because the full knowledge of the Good could not be grasped by everyone, but was reserved for those few with higher intellectual capacity than most people, and also because not all people are born to be rulers. As human individuals are differently and unequally endowed in their mental capacities, talents, and desires, only those with the desire and capacity necessary to be the seekers of the knowledge of the Good and the rulers of the state should receive their special education.

61 CHAPTER IV

METHODS OF EDUCATION

In the Four Books

Before discussing the methods of education Confucius and Mencius used, the specific qualifications and abilities they expected both teachers and students to possess deserve our attention. Confucius said, "If a man keeps cherishing his old knowledge, so as continually to be acquiring new, he may be a teacher of others." (A: 11.11: Legge) Speaking about himself as a teacher he said, "I have listened in silence and noted what was said. I have never grown tired of learning nor wearied of teaching others what I have learned. These at

least are merits which I can continually claim.” (A: VII. 2: Waley) Expressing

his feeling toward the youth he said, "Respect the young. How do you know that they will not one day be all that you are now?" (A: IX. 22: Waley)

As a teacher, Confucius was open and honest with his students. He said,

"Do you think, my disciples, that I have any concealments? I conceal nothing

from you. There is nothing that is not shown to you, my disciples - that is my

way." (A: VII. 23: Legge) Disclaiming himself to be "one of those who have

innate knowledge," Confucius placed himself as one who had to work hard to

acquire it with his discriminating mind. He said, "There may be those who act

without knowing why. I do not do so. Hearing much and selecting what is good

and following it; seeing much and keeping it in memory - that is my way." (A:

VII. 27: Legge)1

62 Mencius said, "If you do not practice the Way yourself, you cannot expect it to be practiced even by your own wife and children." (VII. B. 9: Lau) He also said, "A good and wise man helps others to understand clearly by his own clear understanding.” (VII. B. 20: Lau) Confucius said, "Do I regard myself as a possessor of knowledge? Far from it. But if even a simple peasant comes in all sincerity and asks me a question, I am ready to thrash the matter out, with all its

pros and cons, to the very end." (A: IX. 7: Waley)

Confucius as a teacher did not treat his students uniformly. His

instruction was according to the students' temperaments, intellectual readiness,

and cognitive aptitude levels or cognitive susceptibility. "To men above the

average one may discourse on higher things; but to those who are below the

average one may not discourse on higher things," said Confucius.2 For

example, when Confucius gave two different answers to the same inquiry, one

of his students Kung-hsi Hua was confused. Kung-hsi said, "When Yu asked,

'When one hears a maxim, should one at once put it into practice?' you said,

'You have a father and elder brother alive.' But when Ch'iu asked, 'When one

hears a maxim, should one at once put it into practice?’ you said, 'When you

hear it, put it into practice.' I am perplexed, and would venture to ask how this

was." The Master said, "Ch'iu is backward; so I urged him on. Yu is fanatical

about Goodness; so I held him back." (A: XI. 21: Waley) One of the students of

Confucius who was also a teacher expressed this way of handling students as

follows:

If it be transmitted to him before he is ripe By the time he is ripe, he will be weary of it.

Disciples may indeed be compared to plants and trees. They have to be

separately treated according to their kinds. (A: XIX. 12: Waley)

63 To sum up, the ideal Confucian teacher must love to learn himself, must love to teach, must practice what he learned to be right in his life, must be honest and respectful in his dealings with the student, and must be sensitive and flexible in meeting the psychological and intellectual needs of his student.

The role the teacher plays in the development of the student's discriminating mind and his inherent moral tendency is important in two vital respects; first, as the model for his student to emulate; second, as the partner of discussion, which is the chief channel through which the cognition and application of moral knowledge are achieved. Ideally, the teacher must also possess a perfect knowledge of what to know and how to behave, but neither Confucius nor

Mencius admitted to having it. They themselves were humble and dedicated seekers of the perfect virtue, the jen-yi.3

To implement their educational plan, how Confucius and Mencius gathered their students and where the students came to them for instruction are not clear.4 The opening two sentences of the Analects describe the master's pleasure in learning together with friends who came from distant places.5 From the same book, we also learn that Confucius accepted men as his students regardless of their socio-economic background as long as they were sincere and desirous of learning from him.6 For Mencius, too, education was for all who sincerely wanted the pursue the knowledge of ultimate importance and to improve the quality of the lives of all men. Mencius, after turning down a man named Keng of Teng to be his student said,

I do not answer him who questions me presuming on his nobility, nor him who presumes on his talents, nor him who presumes on his age, nor him who presumes on services performed to the state, nor him who presumes on old acquaintance. Two of those things were chargeable on Keng. (VII: A. 43: Legge)

64 Confucius and Mencius expected a prospective student, in order to be a successful learner, to have the following qualities in him. He must be intellectually ambitious. Confucius said:

Do you be a scholar after the style of the superior man, and not after that of the ordinary man. (A: VI. 11)

I do not open up the truth to one who is not eager to get knowledge, nor help out any one who is not anxious to explain himself. When I have presented one corner of a subject to any one, and he cannot from it learn the other three, I do not repeat my lesson. (A: VII. 8: Legge)

He must be broad-minded in learning, "willing to learn both from the worthy and

unworthy men." (A: IV. 23: Legge)7 He is expected to be inquisitive.

Confucius said, "When a man is not in the habit of saying - ’What shall I think of

this? What shall I think of this?'I can indeed do nothing with him!" (A: IV. 23:

Legge) Praising an honored scholar of former days, Confucius said, "He was of

an active nature and yet fond of learning, and he was not ashamed to ask and

learn from his inferiors." (A: V. 14: Legge)

The learner must keep himself alert in study to measure his own

progress. Confucius said,

He, who from day to day recognizes what he has not yet, and from month to month does not forget what he has attained to, may be said indeed to love to learn. There are learning extensively, and having a firm and sincere aim; inquiring with earnestness, and reflecting with self¬ application: jen is in such a course. (A: XIX. 5 - 6: Legge)

He must also be persistent in his study until he understands, his inquiry until he

knows, his reflection until he apprehends, his discrimination until it becomes

clear, his practices until it succeeds. "If a man succeed by one effort, he will use

a hundred efforts. If a man succeed by ten efforts, he will use a thousand." (DM:

XX. 20: Legge)8 The following two passages also list a few more qualities

expected of the student. Confucius said:

65 If the scholar be not grave, he will not call forth any veneration and his learning will not be solid. Hold faithfulness and sincerity as first principles. Have no friends not equal to yourself. When you have faults do not fear to abandon them. (A: 1.8: Legge)

He who aims to be a man of complete virtue in his food does not seek to gratify his appetite, nor in his dwelling-place does he seek the appliances of ease; he frequents the company of men of principle that he may be rectified; such a person may be said indeed to love to learn (A- I. 14: Legge) ' v '

In short, Confucius said, The scholar who cherished the love of comfort is not fit to be deemed a scholar." (A: XIV. 3: Legge) And Mencius said, "In the nourishing of the mind, there is nothing better than to make the desires few." (VII: B. 35: Legge)

It is obvious that only a gifted few had the qualities expected of them in their search for the ultimate knowledge of jen-yi upon which to base their public service. "The purpose of learning is to know the essence of things,"9 and the educational standards set up by the early Confucians were not easy to follow for everyone. Someone said to Mencius:

As far as your teaching is concerned, it is lofty and admirable; indeed, it is like an ascent to Heaven - something one cannot quite attain to. Why not make it a little more attainable by daily unremitting effort?

Mencius replied:

The Master Craftsman does not accommodate the inept workman by tampering with the measuring line. Yi the Archer did not accommodate an inept pupil by changing the target or the rules. The true gentleman leads. He does not turn aside. He leaps forward as it were, placing himself squarely in the center of the Way. Those who can, follow him. (VII. 4. 41: Dobson)

Confucius advised his students by saying, "The Way of the Superior man may be compared to what takes place in traveling, when to go to a distance we must first traverse the space that is near, and in ascending a height, we must begin from the lower ground." (DM: XV. 1: Legge)

66 Concerning the methods of education Mencius said, "There are more ways than one of instructing others. My disdain to instruct a man is itself one way of instructing him." (VI. B. 616: Legge) To be more specific, he said:

?m*an tefches m five ways- The first is by a transforming influence hke that of timely rain. The second is by helping the student to realize his virtue to the full. The third is by helping him to develop his talent The fourth is by answering his questions. And the fifth is by setting an example others not in contact with him can emulate. These five are the ways in which a gentleman teachers. (VII. A. 40: Lau)

Both the Analects and the Book of Mencius show that Confucius and Mencius used any number of the "five ways" to create an informal yet very personal learning atmosphere. The "five ways" were not fixed or programmed methods applicable to all students in a uniform manner. In their view, the whole purpose of all educational methods was to help the student cultivate his innate goodness himself to its fullest possible capacity, and the role of the teacher was to point the student towards a direction he could use as his guide. Mencius said, "The way of truth is like a great road. It is not difficult to know it. The evil is only that men will not seek it. Do you go home and search for it, and you will have abundance of teachers." (VI. B. 2. iii: Legge) He also said, "A master carpenter or carriage maker may give a circle and square, but cannot make his apprentice skillful in the use of them.” (VII. B. 5) The real attainment must be made by the learner for himself.

Even so, for the student to succeed in self-cultivation, the guidance of the teacher was invaluable. A Confucian teacher, who was ideally a "gentleman"

(chun-tzu or "superior man" himself and had trodden the path of

learning to attain jen-yi before his student, could certainly help the young with

his own experience; indeed, it was his obligation.10

Though the "five ways" of instruction are not extensively explained, it is

clear that they were designed to meet the needs of the students whose

67 individual educational levels and capacities were understandably varied. The first of the "five ways" is the method of unforced instruction with comments, suggestions, and encouragement to bring about the student's progress to moral knowledge and behavioral maturity as naturally as possible. This method by implication requires patience and human care on the part of the teacher, for hastening the process in learning may spoil the expected result. Confucius said, "Flowing water is a thing which does not proceed till it has filled the hollows in its course. The student who has set his mind on the Way, does not advance to them but by completing one lesson after another." (VII. A. 24:

Legge-Dobson)

The second method is that of helping the student to sharpen his inner eye or discriminating mind to see the innate virtue he already has and consciously cultivate it to base his social conduct and relationship with others.

The third method needs no extensive exposition. It is simply that of helping the student to develop his talent to its fullest capacity. Mencius did not indicate any particular talent over others as needing the teacher's special attention and guidance.

The fourth method is that of a dialectic method most evident in the

Analects and the Book of Mencius. The Chinese title Lun Yu for the Analects means the record of discourses or dialogues. Both Confucius and

Mencius held sessions with one or a few of their students at a time to converse or carry on a dialogue with questions and answers. This method was highly effective not only in stimulating the mind of the student to think, but also in making him aware of his ignorance or understanding of the issue under investigation. Although there is no detailed description on the procedure of this method in the Four Books, its objective was, too, to help the student to acquire the knowledge of moral principles for himself through serious and free

68 exchange of his opinions and ideas with his teacher. Each session was purposefully directed and conducted in an open, positive, and relaxed atmosphere, and the method as a whole was successful.

Many passages in the Book of Mencius prove that Mencius was an avid disputant using the method of analogy, but not always convincing in the judgment of his critics.11

Kung-tu Tzu said, "Outside of our circle, men say that you, Sir, simply like to argue. May I ask what you yourself say to this?” Mencius replied, "It surely cannot be thought that I like to argue! I do so because I have no other recourse... I too, wish to set aright the minds of men, to put an end to pernicious teaching, to stand opposed to wicked deeds, and to banish evil talk, and thus to continue with the work of these three Sages. It surely cannot be said that I ’like to argue.' I do so because I have no other recourse." (III. B. 9. i & xiii: Dobson)

The last of the "five ways" is the method of emulation designed for the

student who is unable to study with the teacher in person. The teacher, though

separated from the student by time and space, can still teach him, granted that the teacher has maintained his intellectual and moral integrity as a model

worthy to be emulated by the student. This method was the one Mencius said

he had used to learn from Confucius.12 Aware of man's natural inclination to

imitate either a good or bad model, both Confucius and Mencius advised their

students to choose their friends and neighbors wisely, lest they might be led

away from the Way.13

The models Confucius and Mencius selected for their students to

emulate were not only exemplary men of their own days, but also those of the

highest moral reputation of the past, such as the legendary sage kings, Yao and

Shun, of the earlier dynasties and the Duke of Chou.14 In their observation,

man sometimes learns unconsciously, imitating models around him, and

sometimes consciously, imitating the models of his choice made by his

discriminating mind. They believed that man in his right mind almost always

69 would choose to emulate the models of the highest moral excellence Confucius said:

If the people be led by laws, and uniformity sought to be given them bv punishments, they will try to avoid the punishment, but have no sense of shame. If they be led by virtue, and the uniformity sought to be qiven them by the rules of propriety, they will have the sense of shame and moreover will become good. (A: 11.3: Legge)

Mencius, too, agreed in his own words:

When one by force subdues men, they do not submit to him in heart. They submit, because their strength is not adequate to resist. When one subdues men by virtue, in their hearts' core they are pleased and sincerely submit, as was the case with the seventy disciples in their submission to Confucius. What is said in the Book of Poetry, "From the west, from the east, From the south, from the north, There was not one who thought of refusing submission," is an illustration of this. (II. A. 4. ii: Legge)

Confucius said, "When we see men of worth, we should think of equalling them; when we see men of a contrary character, we should turn inwards and examine ourselves." (IV. 17: Legge)

The last quoted statement of Confucius introduces yet another method of learning the early Confucians recommended to their students. This method is that of "to turn inwards," read in Chinese as nei sheng (^^ ), renderable in English as self-examination or introspection, enabling the student to measure critically his own progress in self-cultivation, so that his social action and behavior will not contradict his knowledge of jen-yi.

According to Confucius and Mencius, self-examination is the best method by which the student can come to know himself, his ability, and his level of progress in moral training. It is the best way to prevent him from self- deception, inhuman attitude and behavior towards other human beings, and

making the same mistakes repeatedly. Statements such as those quoted below

stress the importance of self-examination in no uncertain terms.

70 The philosopher Tsang said, "I daily examine myself on three points- whether, in transacting business for others, I may have been not faithful- whether, in intercourse with friends, I may have been not sincere- whether, I may have not mastered and practiced the instruction of mv teacher." (A: I. 4: Legge)

What the superior man seeks is in himself, what the mean man seeks is in others. (A: XV. 20: Legge)

Here is a man who treats me in a perverse and unreasonable manner. The superior man in such a case will turn round upon himself - ”1 must have been wanting in benevolence: I must have been wanting in propriety: how should this have happened to me" (MEN IV. B. 28. iv Legge)

The Master said, "In archery we have something like the way of the superior man. When the archer misses the centre of the target, he turns round and seeks for the cause of his failure in himself." (DM: XV. 5: Legge)

When internal examination discovers nothing wrong, what is there to be anxious about, what is there to fear? (A: XII. 4. iii: Legge)

In the Dialogues

Socrates the Teacher - His Role and Method: Socrates, who was immortalized by Plato as the greatest teacher of all times, had different views of himself. He did not pretend to know everything, insisting that his only advantage over others was the knowledge of his own ignorance. (Meno: 71 B)

He was declared the wisest of men by the Delphic oracle that "no man living was wiser than Socrates," (Apol: 21 A ft.) but insisted that he was, in fact, without the knowledge of even "what justice or virtue was." (Meno: 71 B; Rg£.:

354 C) Confessing his ignorance, he proposed to learn from anyone or any school the knowledge he was seeking in order to carry on his search for truth with others. (Theaet: 143 D) He said he was a seeker himself and would seek for it to the end of his life as his service to god and his people. In the Apology, we read:

71 Men of Athens, I respect and love you, but I shall obey the qod rather than you and while I live and am able to continue, I shall never qive ud philosophy or stop exhorting you and pointing out the truth to any one of you whom I may meet... And if any of you argues the point, and says he does care, I shall not let him go at once, nor shall I go away but I shall question and examine and cross-examine him, and if I find that he does not possess virtue, but says he does, I shall rebuke him for scorninq the things that are of most importance and caring more for what is of less worth. This I shall do to whomever I meet, young and old, foreigner and citizen, but most to the citizens, inasmuch as you are more nearly related to me. For I know that the god commands me to do this, and I believe that no greater good ever came to pass in the city than my service to the ood (29 D - 30 A) y

Socrates had no fixed place to give his instruction and no formalized curriculum to offer. His students, whom he called his "associates,"15 were mostly adults with traditional education and culture, some old and some young, and they were free to come and go. Among them were prominent thinkers of his day, including some Sophists of great eminence from far and near, noted political figures of Athens, and even those who later accused him as the corrupter of the youth of Athens and a religious heretic, thus sending him to his death in 399 B.C. he accommodated everyone who came to hear him, argue with him, learn from him, and seek the truth of all things with him. (Apol: 23 C)

His method of teaching and learning with this circle of "associates" was conversational, as Plato’s dialogues so clearly demonstrate. Socrates encouraged everyone present to take part in the informal, but intellectually stimulating atmosphere his pedagogical method inevitably created. The method was called "dialectic," and how it actually worked will be discussed toward the end of this chapter. Simply put, dialectic aimed to make the participants in the session exercise their minds to their maximum capacity in a philosophical discourse to acquire the knowledge of the highest virtue.

In the Theaetetus. Socrates compares his role as a teacher with that of a midwife saying:

72 Have y°u not heard that I am the son of a noble and burly Phaenarete? And have you not also heard that I practice the same art?Y (149 A)

I am not at all a wise person myself, nor have I any wise invention the offspring born of my own soul; but those who associate with me althouqh at first some of them seem very ignorant, yet, as our acquaintance 9 advances, all of them to whom the god is gracious make wonderful progress, not only in their opinion, but in that of others as well And it is clear that they do this, not because they have ever learned anythinq from me, but because they have found in themselves many fair thinos and have brought them forth. (150 C-D)

Now those who associate with me are in this matter also like women in childbirth... (151 B)

I suspect that you, as you yourself believe, are in pain because you are pregnant with something within you. Apply, then, to me, remembering that I am the son of a midwife and have myself a midwife's gifts, and do your best to answer the questions I ask as I ask them. (151 B-C)

You forget, my friend, that I myself know nothing about such things, and claim none of them as mine, but am incapable of bearing them and am merely acting as a midwife to you, and for that reason am uttering incantations and giving you a taste of each of the philosophical theories, until I may help to bring your own opinion to light. (157 C-D)

You are truly fond of argument, Theodorus, and a very good fellow to think that I am a sort of bag full of arguments... I myself know nothing, except just a little, enough to extract an argument from another man who is wise and to receive it fairly. And now I will try to extract this thought from Theaetetus, but not to say anything myself. (151 A-B)

Such a terrible love of this kind of exercise has taken hold on me. So, now that it is your turn, do not refuse to try a bout with me; it will be good for both of us. (169 B-C)

These passages show how Socrates challenged his friends or students to philosophical discussions and what role he played to make them become active thinkers themselves. This was the method with which he wished to assist the learner, through rigorous questioning and answering, to turn the eye of his reasoning soul to the source of the cosmic order, the Good.

In his more formalized educational system, Socrates proposed in the

Republic and the Laws that the type of philosophical sessions he conducted with mostly adult students belonged to the stage of higher education. And at

73 this stage of advanced education, Socrates demands certain specific mental qualities and intellectual aptitudes in his students, for "Philosophy, the love of wisdom, is impossible for the multitude." (Be* 494 A) The students at this level

of education must possess the following innate qualities: "the spirit of truthfulness, reluctance to admit falsehood in any form, the hatred of it and love

of truth" (585 C); "Then the true lover of knowledge must, from childhood up, be

most of all a striver after the truth in every form" (Ibid.: 485 D); "Such a man

will be temperate and by no means greedy for wealth." (Ibid.: 485 E) He who

seeks for the ultimate truth which is eternal and universal "will not suppose

death to be terrible." (jl?id-: 486 A-B) "The forgetful soul, we must not list in the

roll of competent lovers of wisdom, but we require a good memory." (ibid.: 486

D) He must have "youthful spirit with a disposition to live an orderly, quiet, and

stable life." (Ibid.: 503 C) "There is a close affinity between proportion and

truth," says Socrates, "hence, besides our other requirements, we shall look for

a mind endowed with measure and grace, which will be instinctively drawn to

see every reality in its true light." (Ibid.: 486 D-E) In brief, the student must be

"by nature of good memory, quick apprehension, magnificent, gracious, friendly

and akin to truth, justice, bravery and sobriety." (Ibid.: 487 A)

The entire curriculum of the Socratic education, which will be discussed

in the following chapter, was simply to produce qualified candidates capable of

philosophical conversation in their final stage of moral education. The

dialectical method was, therefore, naturally for the intellectually mature students

who had been trained in abstract thinking.

In the Republic and the Laws. Socrates proposes that all children of the

citizens must be educated. He proposes state-controlled and state-supported

schools and compulsory education for all children, both boys and girls, of the

citizens. It was important to impose universal education on the children in order

74 to select the best and the brightest for the higher level of education for the posts of leadership and responsibility.

Although Plato mentions the importance of prenatal education in the

Laws,16 the formal education of children begins at the age of three. According to the BfiPUfrliC, children between the ages of three and nine or ten are taken away from home and spend their time in music for the mind and gymnastics for the body. The program in music for the children of this age group included story-telling, singing, dancing, reciting epic and dramatic poetry, lyre-playing, and the rudiments of arithmetic and geometry.

Between the ages of ten and twenty, the teens are given a more intense instruction in all above-mentioned subjects and in the skills of reading and writing. Plato wrote in the Laws: "About three years will be a reasonable time for a child of ten to spend on literature, and a further three years, beginning at the age of thirteen, should be spent on learning the lyre.” (810) Then three years of intense physical and military training will follow to conclude the preliminary education. "These times," Plato insisted, "must be neither shortened

nor lengthened; neither the child nor its father must be allowed to extend or curtail these periods of study out of enthusiasm for, or distaste of, the curriculum; that will be against the law." (Ibid.l

In dealing with children in their early stages of education, Socrates emphasizes the importance of play as an educational method and warns of the futility of coercion, In the Republic, we read:

All this study of reckoning and geometry and all the preliminary studies that are indispensable preparation for dialectics must be presented to them while still young, not in the form of compulsory instruction... Because, a free soul ought not to pursue any study slavishly; for... nothing that is learned under compulsion stays with the mind... Do not, then, my friend, keep children to their studies by compulsion but by play. That will also better enable you to discern the natural capacities of each. (536 E - 537 A)

75 At the age of twenty, all the students go through tests and examinations for the purpose of selection of those who qualify for higher education and those whose qualifications are fit for other vocational pursuits. Those selected twenty year-olds begin their higher education by spending the next ten years studying advanced branches of arithmetic, geometry, astronomy, and harmony, "which are not to be pursued in a scientific spirit or for utility only, but rather with a view to their combination by means of dialectic into an ideal of all knowledge."17

At the age of thirty, a further selection is made, and those selected will spend the next five years studying philosophy or dialectic and the ultimate moral principles.

From thirty-five to fifty years of age, they are sent into active public life, manning those posts most suited to their training and qualifications.

At fifty, they return to philosophical study and enjoy life to the end of their days, but when their turn comes they will, in rotation, turn to the weary business of politics and, for the sake of society, do their duty as Rulers, not for the honour they get by it but as a matter of necessity." (Rep.: 540 A-B)

Socrates considered dialectic as the best possible method of acquiring the ultimate knowledge of the Good which future philosopher-kings must acquire. In his view, there would be no knowledge of the Good without dialectic, and without the knowledge of the Good, there would be no good rulers and good government. Dialectic was inseparable from Socrates; indeed, it was

Socrates.

As the speech quoted on page 127 exemplifies, dialectic was employed to obtain the most complete answer possible to a moral question under investigation through persistent questioning and answering until it is found.

Whether or not the perfect answer to every moral question is possible through dialectic is another question. At any rate, the entire work of Plato which

76 involves Socrates is constructed with endless cross-examinations showing

Socrates' indefatigable attempts to find the universally verifiable concept or definition underlying a separate moral precept, such as "justice" or "courage."

The simple form of the question "What is courage?" requests definitions to start the quest for the complete meaning of "courage."

The way dialectic worked with Socrates is best described by Werner Jaeger as follows.

The purpose of the Socratic dialogue is, by discussion with other men on a subject which is of incomparable interest to all concerned - namely, the highest values in human life - to reach an agreement which must be recognized as valid by everyone. In order to reach this result, Socrates always starts with what is admitted, either by his interlocutor, or by people in general. This admission is used as the "hypothesis," the foundation. Then the discussion works out what follows from the hypothesis, and tests those findings by other facts which we know to be established. Therefore an essential factor in a dialectic advance is the discovery of the contradictions which confront us when we base arguments on certain definite statements. These contradictions compel us to re-examine the correctness of the judgments we had laid down as true, and sometimes to revise them or abandon them. The aim of all this process is to bring separate phenomena in the realm of moral standards under one supreme general standard. But in his investigations Socrates does not start by looking for this "good in itself." He starts with some "virtue" denoted by the name of a particular moral quality - for instance, the quality we call bravery or justice. Thus, in Laches, there are a number of attempts to find out what "courage" is; but the statements made about it must be dropped, one after another, because each of them describes the nature of courage too narrowly or too broadly...18

Dialectic as a curricula in the final stage of education for the future philosopher- rulers will be discussed further in the following chapter.

In summary

This chapter aims at answering the following questions: first, according

to our thinkers of China and Athens, "What specific qualities must one have to

be the teacher of moral education?"; second, "What specific qualities must one

77 have to receive moral education?-; and lastly, "What are the methods of moral education?"

To answer the first question, both groups agree that ideally speaking, only the chun-tzu and the Guardians, who have the knowledge of the Good and

practice the Good, should do the teaching. But, in the absence of those, anyone with certain specific qualities may be the teacher. The essential qualities both groups list are virtually identical. By implication the teacher is expected to have the same qualities which Confucius and Socrates had. Therefore, like

Confucius and Socrates, he must love to learn tirelessly in order to get to the

heart of the knowledge most worthy and of the highest value and, at the same time, love to teach tirelessly those who are eager to learn. He must be totally

honest and sincere about his knowledge, admitting his ignorance if he does not

know. He must love his students, knowing them individually so that he can give

most appropriate instruction when needed, treating them as his equals, for he

too is a life-long student and seeker of wisdom, and must listen to them carefully

and critically to carry on their philosophic conversation about the knowledge

they must find. He must also put into practice what he knows and teachers to be

true consistently and as best as possible.

Now about the student, Confucius and Socrates appear to have

welcomed anyone who wanted to learn with and from them, especially

Confucius, irrespective of one's social and economic status. It must be

remembered that the students Confucius and Socrates had were not recruited

and were all adults, including established thinkers in their own right. For these

students, both Confucius and Socrates chose the dialectical method as the best

and used it exclusively. Plato's school in the Republic, however, would accept

all children of the citizens when they reached the age of three, but would screen

and select them as they grew older, and only those judged qualified would be

78 promoted to the next higher level of education. When the students reach the age of thirty, they are again screened for the final time and an elite few are permitted to receive the highest and the last level of education, the education in dialectic.

The intellectual capacities and other human qualities expected in their elite group of students are understandably the same as those expected in their teachers. A few more qualities mentioned by both groups are: the love of knowledge or wisdom more than anything else in the world including life; an alert, inquisitive, and perceptive mind with a good memory; persistent and disciplined study habits; a simple and ordered lifestyle; and the desire to improve others as one improves oneself.

Before discussing the various methods both groups used, the underlying supposition they held in justifying their methods needs to be reiterated. In their view, the knowledge of the Good cannot be taught, because it is in man already.

To put it another way, man can only acquire knowledge by recollecting, discovering, or searching out what is in him already. Therefore, education is only valuable if it can assist him in becoming an autonomous seeker of knowledge and all its substance by developing his reasoning faculty to its fullest extent. To use a Socratic metaphor, education is like a midwife, who assists in the birth of a new class of men and women. Based on this supposition, each group chose various courses of study and methods judged effective to develop and train the appetitive, the spirited, and above all, the reasoning parts of man harmoniously and fully to help students become men of excellence.

The methods used by the Confucian and the Athenian thinkers are many.

Some methods are for the teacher, some are for the student, and still others are for both the teacher and the student. For example, the method of not transplanting the knowledge of someone else into the student is for the teacher;

79 the method of learning through self-examination is for the student alone, and the method of emulation is both for the teacher and the student, because the teacher must present a model for the student to imitate and the student must imitate the model passively. All these methods are considered by both groups valuable, if used flexibly and wisely according to the needs of various age groups or individual students.

In Plato s school, some courses of study, such as arithmetic, geometry, astronomy, and harmonics are required not for their practical application, but solely for their methodological values to aid the development of the student's

reasoning power so that they will become able to deal with abstract concepts such as the Ideas or Forms of the Good or the Beautiful before entering the

highest stage of education in dialectic.

Although both groups had many and various methods to use, if they were

able to find new and better methods, they welcomed them, too, as long as the

methods did not obstruct or retard an orderly and natural progress towards

wholesome maturity of the future chun-tzu or Guardians in moral excellence.

In concluding the summary of this chapter, two quotations from the Book

of Mencius and one from the Republic will be useful to prove the above point,

which is of great importance and underlies all their methods. Mencius said:

You must not be like the man from Sung. There was a man from Sung who pulled at his rice plants because he was worried about their failure to grow... There are few in this world who can resist the urge to help their rice plants grow. There are some who leave the plants unattended, thinking that nothing they can do will be of any use. They are the people who do not even bother to weed. There are others who help the plants grow. They are the people who pull at them. Not only do they fail to help them but they do the plants positive harm. (M: II. A. 2. xvi: Lau)

There are more ways than one of instructing others. My disdain to instruct a man is itself one way of instructing him. (M: VI. B. 16: Lau)

80 In the Republic. Socrates said:

QtMHioc'thof stLJdy °f reckon'ng and geometry and all the preliminary studies that are indispensable preparation for dialectics must be presented to them while still young, not in the form of compulsory

fnr\rLlviIOK'■^•PeiCuUSe a free soul ought not to Pursue any study slavishly for while bodily labours performed under constraint do not harm the V’ body nothmg that is learned under compulsion stays with the mind Do play (R:' 53*60-1: 1^7™ *°,heir StUdi6S by COmpulsi°" bu' *

81 CHAPTER V

CURRICULUM

In the Four Books

A passage in the Analects says, "The Master taught four things, wen (jt). hsing ), chung (&), and hsin (H).n (VII. 24) What exactly these four things Confucius taught were was not clear. Legge translated them as "letters, ethics, devotion of soul, and truthfulness"; Soothill as "culture, conscientiousness, and good faith"; Waley as "culture, conduct of affairs, loyalty to superior, and keeping of promise"; and Lau as "culture, moral conduct, doing one's best and being trustworthy in what one says."1 Wen as a curricula is easier to identify, though not simple, than the other three things. Whether hsing, chung, and hsin, which have something to do with three different expressions of moral conduct, were three separate subjects of study or not, is also unclear.

What these "three things" are will be discussed in more detail later. First, we shall discuss what wen was and what studies were involved in it according to the Four Books.

In the days of Confucius and Mencius, wen, literature or culture, involved not only literary studies, but some other studies also, such as music, ceremonies or rites, archery, horsemanship, writing, and numbers.2 According to Waley, "Wen denotes arts of peace (music, dancing, literature) as opposed to those of war. The arts of peace, however, everything that we should call culture, have a te that is useful for offensive purposes.”3 Confucius said in the Angels

XVI. 1. xi:

82 attract 'therrfhu onh ?'lds stl" do not submit’,hen ruler must “thT by ®nbancm9 the prestige (is.) of his culture (went- and when bf®a duly attracted, he contents them. And whSere is contentment there will be no upheavals. (Waley) And also in IX. 5:

When the Master was trapped in K'uang, he said, When King Wen perished did that mean that culture (wen) ceased to exist? If Heaven had really intended that such culture (wan) as his should disappear a latter-day mortal would never have been able to link himself to it as i have done And if Heaven does not intend to destroy such culture (wen) what have I to fear from the people of K’uang? (Waley) ’

In these two passages, the character wen is clearly used to mean culture or civilization. However, the word wen is most often used in a narrower sense in the Analects to mean literature or literary studies, especially when Confucius was said to have taught "four things."4

Wen as a curricula involved the study of poetry shih), history

shu), the art of ceremony or rite (*£//), and music yueh)

Poetry

Neither Confucius nor Mencius wrote any poetry as far as we know, but both of them quoted freely, almost too freely, from the Book of Poetry in their teaching. For centuries, in fact, Chinese scholars credited Confucius as either the editor or compiler of the Book of Poetry, but most recent scholarship discounts such claims.5 There is a passage in the Analects which indicates

Confucius' rearranging some pieces of the Book of Poetry, but nothing more.6

At any rate, Confucius used it in his teaching for the following values as stated in the Analects. He said, "In the Book of Poetry are three hundred pieces, but the design of them all may be embraced in one sentence - 'Having no depraved thoughts."' (II. 2: Legge) In XVII. 9 he said:

1. My children, why do you not study the Book of Poetry?

83 2. The Odes serve to stimulate the mind. 3. They may be used for purposes of self-contemplation 4. They teach the art of sociability. 5. They show how to regulate feelings of resentment. 6. From them you learn the more immediate duty of serving one's father and the remoter one of serving one's prince. 7. From them we become largely acquainted with the names of birds beasts, and plants. (Legge) ’

The Master said to Po-yu, "do you give yourself to the Chau-nan and the Shao-nan? The man who has not studied the Chau-nan and the Shao- nan, is like one who stands with his face right against a wall Is he not so? (XVII. 10: Legge)7

One of the disciples asked the son of Confucius:

As his son you must after all sure have heard something different from what the rest of us hear. Po-yu replied saying, No. Once when he was standing alone and I was hurrying past him across the courtyard, he said, Have you studied the Songs? I replied saying, No. [He said] If you do not study the Songs, you will find yourself at a loss in conversation So I retired and studied the Songs. (XVI. 13: Waley)

Confucius urged his students to study Poetry for the positive benefits it rewards. In his view, the study of Poetry serves to stimulate the mind with imagination and makes it sensitive to human feelings. It also improves interpersonal relations and helps one to express one's feeling of resentment when confronted with injustice. It cultivates the correct attitude toward one's own father in serving him at home and toward one's superiors in his service to the state away from home. It also increases the knowledge of Nature's other living things, such as birds, animals, plants, and trees with their correct names. Even a quick sampling of some of the pieces in the Book of Poetry is enough to make one see that the poems in it poignantly describe the depth of man's varied experiences of joys and sorrows, triumphs and defeats, dreams and realities, and other emotional ups and downs. They also inform us of general human conditions that existed under various rulers of the past and how they affected the lives and feelings of the people.

84 In the training of the chun-tzu, who must know his people to be their benevolent ruler, Confucius must have felt the study of Poetry was essential to his curriculum not only for enhancing knowledge of man's complex nature, but as a practical tool for improving the communicative abilities of future officials of government. Although a thorough acquaintance with the Book of Pnptry to the point of memorizing the whole book, could be considered a commendable achievement, Confucius warned his students that such an achievement was useless unless they could use what they had acquired in actual life. He said,

Though a man may be able to recite the three hundred odes, yet if when intrusted with a governmental charge, he knows not how to act, or if, when sent to any quarter on a mission, he cannot give his replies unassisted, notwithstanding the extent of his learning, of what practical use is it? (LY. XIII. 5: Legge)

History

The study of history as a curriculum was as important as that of poetry to

both Confucius and Mencius. For it is through history that one learns about the

men who were directly tied to the success or failure of the past dynasties. It is

through history that one can acquire the knowledge of moral and immoral rulers

and the effects of their rules upon the people.

In the eyes of both Confucius and Mencius, the legendary dynasties of

Hsia and Shang and the Western (or Earlier) Chou (about 1050 - 770 B.C.) had

been blessed with virtuous and moral rulers, and under their governments, the

people prospered and were happy in peace.8 Confucius saw the culture of the

Western Chou, when founded and ruled by Kings Wen and Wu and the Duke of

Chou, as the model of the highest moral culture, which all future rulers should

admire and emulate. The virtuous rulers of the early Chou, according to

Confucius, were wise and moral because they did not neglect learning from the

85 history of the preceding dynasties and their Sage Kings, Yao, Shun, and Yu.9

The names of these three Sage Kings and their moral examples are mentioned

by both Confucius and Mencius throughout the Eour Books numerous times, but for Confucius, the single outstanding model of the superior moral man of all time was the Duke of Chou. For Mencius, it was Confucius, the "unseptered or uncrowned Sage King."™

Confucius, who described himself as an indefatigable and devoted

student of history and a transmitter of the wisdom of the past,11 considered the

culture of the Western Chou the worthiest of all past wisdoms to transmit as a

teacher. To him, the history of the Western Chou was not at all so remote as

Wolfgang Bauer points out:

It is important to realize that from the perspective of the sixth century B.C., this meant that it was not situated in remotest antiquity but still stood in the brightest light of history, having ended little more than two hundred years earlier.12

Mencius had an increased number of historical exemplars besides the

Sage Kings of antiquity and installed Confucius, the "unseptered Sage King,"

as the ultimate model of man for his students to emulate. Mencius chose

Confucius as his most respected teacher although he missed being his disciple

in person by a little over a hundred years.13 As only a keen student could, he

mastered the teachings of Confucius through others and the study of historical

sources to become the most eminent Confucian after Confucius.14 The Book of

Mencius is virtually filled with discourses in which the moral and immoral

governments of the remote and recent past are contrasted and discussed, and

Mencius shows his students the beneficial efficacy of a government ruled by

moral men.

To both Confucius and Mencius, the knowledge of history was, just as

"the square and compass" were to the craftsman, the standard by which to

86 measure and chart the path for future rulers to take. Although both Confucius and Mencius were profoundly disappointed by the morally sunken state of their rulers, as insightful readers of history they were not pessimists. In Confucius' view, history repeated itself and, at the same time, moved on straight from primordial perfection through temporary degeneration to final perfection. The word tao (5^ : way) as used in the Analects meant the Way of the

Ancients, which was the perfect way. Confucius firmly believed that the restoration of the perfect state in the future, if not in his lifetime, was a definite possibility only if the future rulers would seek and follow the Way.

To Mencius as well, history was "the progress in cycles"1* and the record of the rise and fall of political morality of the past rulers that repeated every five hundred years. He too was firm in believing that if men of his own days would strive hard to seek and follow the Way of the Ancients, the restoration of the ideal state was a definite possibility in his lifetime. In the Book of Mencius, he said:

A little more than five hundred years passed from the times of Yao and Shun until the times of Tang the Successful. Men like Yu the Great and Kao Yao knew Yao and Shun at first hand, but Tang knew them only by hearsay. A little more than five hundred years elapsed from the times of T'ang until King Wen. Men like Yi Yin and Lai Chu knew T'ang at first hand, but King Wen knew him only by hearsay. A little more than five hundred years elapsed from King Wen to Confucius. Men like T’ai Kung Wang and San Yi-sheng knew King Wen at first hand, but Confucius knew him only by hearsay. A little over a hundred years have elapsed from the time of Confucius until the present. Today we are not so far removed from the times of the Sage, and, more seriously, are close by the place where he lived. But there is no Sage! Is there not to be one? (VII. B. 38: Dobson)

In reading history, just as in reading all other ancient literature, Confucius and Mencius instructed their students to be persistent and critical. Confucius said:

87 The superior man may not engage in studying, but once he does he does not relax until he can understand all that he studies. He may not SlSS*h-n mqK,ry’ but 0nce he does- he does not relax unt'l he knows everything about which he inquires. He may not reflect, but once he does he does not relax until he apprehends everything on which he ref ects. He may not discriminate, but once he does, he does not relax until he is clear in his discrimination. He may not practice, but once he does, he does not relax until he is earnest in his practice. If another man succeeds by one effort, he will use a hundred efforts. If another man succeeds by ten efforts, he will use a thousand. Let a man proceed in this way, and, though dull, he will surely become intelligent; though weak, he will surely become strong. (DM- XX. 20 - 21 )1b

Confucius' intellectual honesty and his critical approach to the things of the past are evident in the following passage from the Analects. He said:

I am able to discourse on the rites of the Hsia, but the state of Ch'i does not furnish sufficient supporting evidence; I am able to discourse on the rites of the Yon, but the state of Sung does not furnish sufficient supporting evidence. This is because there are not enough records and men of erudition. Otherwise I would be able to support what I say with evidence. (III. 9: Lau)

Mencius said, "If one believed everything in the Book of History, it would have been better for the Book not to have existed at all. In the Wen Chieng chapter I accept only two and three strips.17 (VII. B. 3: Lau) In correcting an erroneous interpretation of a poem in the Book of Poetry. Mencius said:

...Hence in explaining an ode, one should not allow the words to obscure the sentence, nor the sentence to obscure the intended meaning. The right way is to meet the intention of the poet with sympathetic understanding. (V. A. 4. ii: Lau)

In concluding this section of study, the following passages from the Book of Mencius will fortify the importance placed by the early Confucians on the study of history in their education of chun-tzu. Mencius said:

The sage is teacher to a hundred generations. Such were Po Yi and Liu Hsia Hui. Hence hearing of the way of Po Yi, a covetous man will be purged of his covetousness and a weak man will become resolute; hearing of the way of Liu Hsia Hui, a mean man will become generous and a narrow-minded man tolerant. Can these two, if they were not sages, have inspired by their example all those who come a hundred generations after them? How much more inspiring they must have been

88 t/?/.t.hoSe^h? were fortunate enough to have known (vii. B. 15: Lau) them personally!

When a scholar feels that his friendship with all the virtuous scholars of a kingdom is not sufficient to satisfy him, he goes back in time and communes with the ancients. When one reads the poems and writinqs of Hfn^1Clent^, Carlrt be .nght not t0 know somethin9 about them as men? Hence one tries to understand the age in which they lived. This can be described as "looking for friends in history." (V. B 8- Legge-Lau)

With eyes as sharp as those of Li Lou or with hands as skilled as those of Kung-shu one could still not draw a perfect circle without the aid of compasses, or a perfect square without the aid of a set square There are princes with Humane hearts, or with a reputation for Humanity, but whose people gain no benefit therefrom, and whose example will not bear emulation by generations to come. This is because they do not put into practice the Way of the Former Kings... The Sages passed on to us the compass, the square, the level, and the line... so that we can make things square or round, level or straight. The usefulness of these thinqs is incommensurable. (IV. A. 1: Dobson)

The perfect square and the perfect circle come only from the set square and compasses. The perfect exemplars of man's relation to man come from the Sages. Both he who, as a prince, wishes to follow fully the way of princes, and he who, as a subject, wishes to follow fully the way of subjects, should take Yao and Shun as his model... (IV. A. 2: Dobson)

It is important to note that in teaching history, Confucius and Mencius were not expecting professional historians out of their students, but those who would apply the highest moral standards they have acquired from study in their real life as government officials. Confucius said, "To study and when the occasion arises to put what one has learned into practice - is this not deeply satisfying?"

(A: I. I.i)

Li: The Art of Ceremony or Rite

Confucius said, "When a man is not virtuous or jen (<-), of what

account are his knowledge of proper manners of li (f§)? When a man is not

virtuous, of what account is his music?" (A. III. 3) In other words, if a man is

devoid of inner virtue or genuine humane nature, though he may be able to

89 perform all religious ceremonies and social etiquette meticulously and perform

music with all the notes expertly played, what he does will be empty and

artificial. For the li and yeuh ( % music) to be genuine, it must come from a man's genuine nature, jen.

The term li, originally meaning "sacrifice or to sacrifice" and later acquiring the meanings of "order" and "arrangement," cannot be rendered in one English word. It has been translated as "propriety," "ritual," "ceremony,"

moral and religious institutions," "the laws and usages of social life," "code of proper conduct," "rules of social conduct," "observance of rites," "holy ritual," "sacred ceremony."

In pre-Confucian China, the term li, understood as "rules of proper conduct," had both religious and social implications. It governed the ceremonial

procedures and behavior in performing memorial services for the departed or at

royal court, meetings between diplomatic representatives, or proper manners at

archery competitions among aristocratic warriors and at banquets usually

following such meets. By the time of Confucius, it came to cover not only

religious and social rituals and manners, but also all the essential decorum in

establishing and maintaining interpersonal relationships. And it was Confucius

and his followers who gave the li an ethical significance by making it essential

to bringing order into the individual's life and to society.18

According to Confucius, each man is born with jen (4— human¬

heartedness), yi (sense of justice), and chih "basic stuff"),19

and these innate moral qualities must be nurtured and put into practice

according to the rules of li. Confucius said:

The chun-tzu has the sense of justice (yi) as his basic stuff and by observing the rules of Ji puts it into practice, by being modest gives it expression, and by being trustworthy in word brings it to completion. Such is a chun-tzu. (A: XV. 17)

90 In the following passages, Confucius explains the importance of learning, which, of course, includes the study of li.

Love of human-heartedness without the love of learning leads to a foolish simplicity. Love of wisdom without the love of learning leads to dfssipahon of mmd. Love of sincerity without the love of learning leads to a harmful behavior. Love of straightforwardness without the love of earning leads to rudeness. Love of courage without the love of learninq eads to insubordination. Love of firmness without the love of learninq leads to reckless conduct. (A: XVII. 8) 9

He also said, "Respectfulness without li becomes tiresome. Carefulness without

li becomes timidity. Courage without li becomes insubordination.

Straightforwardness without //becomes rudeness." (A: VIII. 2)

Intellectual refinement through the study of li, among other studies such as of poetry, history, and music, is essential for the future chun-tzu, but excessive and uncontrolled refinement must be watchfully avoided, lest it may obstruct his "basic stuff" or natural moral substance chih from free and spontaneous expression. Confucius said:

When there is a preponderance of native substance over acquired refinement, the result will be churlishness. When there is a preponderance of acquired refinement over native substance, the result will be pedantry. Only a well-balanced admixture of these two will result in gentlemanliness. (A: VI. 18: Lau)

When a man acquires the knowledge of li, he will be able to balance his acquired refinement {wen jC) with his inherent moral substance {chih% ).

Yen Yuan asked about perfect virtue. The Master said, "To subdue one's self and return to propriety, is perfect virtue..." Yen Yuan said, "I beg to ask the steps of that process." The Master replied, "Look not at what is contrary to li (propriety); listen not to what is contrary to li, speak not what is contrary to li; make no movement which is contrary to li." (A: XII. 1: Legge)

Confucius said, "Without knowing the rules of propriety, it is impossible for the character to be established." (A: XX. 3: Lau)

91 To Confucius, the proper performance of religious rites was important, and he himself expressed a love for it and observed the rules correctly as prescribed.20 What he cared about most in //, however, were not the details of ritual rules, which were numerous and fascinating, but the reverent mood and the genuinely humane and ordered relationships between a man and his living and departed fellow men which it would generate. Li to him was more than an act of formality, but an active force that made man's relationship with everything above and under Heaven proper and correct. In the Book of Mencius there is a dialogue which makes clear exactly this point:

A man of Jen asked Wu-lu which of the two, eating itself or the rules we obey when eating, was the more important. He answered "The rules we obey when eating." The man asked, "Which of the two, sex itself or the rules which govern the enjoyment of sex, is the more important?" He answered again, "The rules which govern its enjoyment." The man continued, "Would you still insist on this, if I could only save my life by eating in disregard of the rules, but would die by insisting on them? Would you insist on the rule that a man must go personally to receive his bride if, being unable to do so, he could not then get married?" To this Wu-lu could not answer. On the next day he went to Tsou and reported this to Mencius. Mencius said, "What is so difficult about answering a question like that?... If your questioner wants to deduce from the cases he adduces that eating and sex are always more important than the rules we obey in enjoying them, then why does he stop there? Why not go and ask him, "If you * could get food to eat only by twisting your older brother's arm and forcibly taking it from him, would you do so? Or if you could only get a bride by climbing a wall of the house next door and abducting your neighbour’s virgin daughter, would you do so?" (VI. B. 1: Dobson)

Li, translated as "rules of conduct" or "the code of right manners," sounds rigid and inflexible, but it is not. According to Confucius, all specific moral conduct or virtues such as loyalty, honesty, kindness, courage, etc., are encompassed in jen or the Perfect Virtue in its broad sense, which is above all

"love of all men." (A: XII. 22)21 Li, which is born of or in the spirit of jen, cannot be inflexible. Mencius makes this point quite clear in the following dialogue.

92 Ch un-yu k un said. Is it prescribed by the Ji that, in giving and receiving, man and woman should not touch each other?" 9 "It is," said Mencius. help her?" °nG'S sister‘in‘law is drowning, does one stretch out a hand to Not to help a sister-in-law who is drowning is to be a brute It k prescribed by the li that in giving and receiving, man and woman should no touch each other, but in stretching out a helping hand To a drowninl sister-in-law one uses one's discretion." (M: IV. A. 17: Lau) 9 Confucius said:

There are some with whom one can associate in study, but who are not yet able to make common advance toward the Way; there are others with whom one can make common advance toward the Way, but who are not yet able to take with you a like firm stand; and there are others with whom one can take such a firm stand, but with whom one cannot make emergency decisions. (A: IX: 29)22

To Confucius, a man who can be firm with the prescribed li under all circumstances is not yet a man of jen, because such a man cannot handle unexpected human problems that do take us by surprise. In dealing with human problems, therefore, one must act according to the li that expresses man's genuine nature or feelings toward other human beings, which is jen.

This means one must be able to make "emergency decisions" or be adept "in the exercise of moral discretion."23 Then, even the following definition of chih

( 4 uprightness) by Confucius is not beyond our comprehension.

The Duke of She observed to Confucius: "In my part of the country there is a man so upright (chih) that when his father appropriated a sheep he bore witness to it." Confucius said: "The upright people in my part of the country are different from that for father will screen his son, and a son his father. In that there lies uprightness." (A: XIII. 18)

In the Analects we read, "There are four things the Master refused to have anything to do with: he refused to entertain conjectures or insist on certainty; he refused to be inflexible or to be egotistical." (IX. 4: Lau)

In educating men who would be rulers of more perfect humane states,

Confucius and Mencius stressed the correct understanding of the spirit or heart of li to be infinitely more important than the correct learning of specific rules of

93 conduct. The Master said, "Ritual, ritual! Does it mean no more than presents of jade and silk?" (A: XVII. 11: Waley) In the words of Mencius, the heart of li is

"the feeling of modesty and complaisance" (Legge) or "deference to others"

(Dobson).24 Li is not a set of dead and mechanical rules.

Confucius and Mencius adopted the study of li as a curricula on account

of the effective transforming influence the power li can exert on men and

society. In their view, the ruler's moral power was mightier than all the other

powers gained through military means, threats, or punishments. The Master said:

Govern the people by laws, keep order by punishment, and they will flee from you, and lose all their self-respect. Govern them by Jen and keep order by \\, and they will keep their self-respect and come to you of their own accord. (A: II. 3)

Yen Hui asked about Goodness (jenT The Master said, "He who can himself submit to ritual (li) is Good. If [a ruler] could for one day himself submit to ritual, everyone under Heaven would respond to his Goodness." (A: XII. 1: Waley)

The Master said, "When a prince's personal conduct is correct, his government is effective without the issuing of orders. If his personal conduct is not correct, he may issue orders, but they will not be followed." (A: XIII. 6: Legge)

The Master said, "When rulers love to observe the rules of propriety, the people respond readily to the calls on them for service." (A: XIV. 44: Legge)

Music

James Legge, in his introduction to Li Chi: Book of Rites, wrote:

As one of the Six Arts cultivated by the Chou aristocracy, music had an important position in the classical curriculum, but in the post-Chou periods it degenerated even among the Confucian scholars. The Chou classic of music, one of the six Chou canons, is lost to posterity, and it is only in the works of Hsun Tzu that we can understand the part played by music as a ritual experience and a communal entertainment in ancient times. He also gave a good description of the various instruments used

94 in ancient China, as written in Chapter 20 of the Hsun Tzu Chantprc yiy and XLV of LLQhi, dealing with music and drinking festivity were taken from this chapter in the Hsun Tzu 25 y were taken

Therefore, for the study of this section, this writer felt strongly the need to quote some revealing passages from the twentieth chapter of the Hsun Tzu which explain the reasons for considering music as an indispensable subject of study for the future chun tzu by Confucius and his followers. Hsun Tzu (c340 c245

B.C.), a contemporary of Mencius and the most prominent Confucian thinker next to Mencius, wrote:

Music is joy, an emotion which man cannot help but feel at times Since man cannot help feeling joy, his joy must find an outlet in voice and an expression in movement. The outcries and movements, and the inner emotional changes which occasion them, must be given full expression in accordance with the way of man. Man must have his joy, and joy must have its expression, but if that expression is not guided by the principles of the Way, then it will inevitably become disordered. The former kings hated such disorder, and therefore they created the musical forms of the odes and hymns in order to guide it. In this way they made certain that the voice would fully express the feelings of joy without becoming wild and abandoned, that the form would be well ordered but not unduly restrictive, that the directness, complexity, intensity, and tempo of the musical performance would be of the proper degree to arouse the best in man's nature, and that evil and improper sentiments would find no opening to enter by. It was on this basis that the former kings created their music.

When music is performed in the ancestral temple of the ruler... When it is performed within the household... And when it is performed in the community... [it] brings about complete unity and induces harmony... It is sufficient to lead men in the single Way or to bring order to ten thousand changes.

Music enters deeply into men and transforms them rapidly. Therefore, the former kings were careful to give it the proper form. When music is moderate and tranquil, the people become harmonious and shun excess. When music is stern and majestic, the people become well behaved and shun disorder... Then the fame of the state will become known abroad, its glory will shine forth greatly, and all people within the four seas will long to become its subjects.

But if music is seductive and depraved, then the people will become abandoned and mean-mannered. Those who are abandoned will fall into disorder; those who are mean-mannered will fall into quarreling; and

95 where there is disorder and quarreling, the troops will be weak the cities will revolt, and the state will be menaced by foreign enemies In such a he common people will find no safety in their dwellings and no delight in their communities, and they will feel only dissatisfaction toward heir superiors. Hence, to turn away from the proper rites and music and to allow evil music to spread is the source of danger and disgrace For this reason the former kings honored the proper rites and music and despised evil music... It is the duty of the chief director of music to enforce the ordinances and commands, to examine songs and writinas and to abolish licentious music, attending to all matters at the appropriate time, so that strange and barbaric music is not allowed to confuse the elegant classical modes.

...Music is something which the sage kings found joy in, for it has the power to make good the hearts of the people, to influence men deeply and to reform their ways and customs with facility. Therefore, the former kings guided the people with rites and music, and the people became harmonious. If the people have emotions of love and hatred, but no ways in which to express their joys or anger, then they will become disordered...

The gentleman utilizes bells and drums to guide his will, and lutes and zithers to gladden his heart... Therefore, the purity of his music is modeled after Heaven, its breadth is modeled after the earth, and its posturings and turnings imitate the four seasons. Hence, through the performance of music the will is made pure, and through the practice of rites the conduct is brought to perfection, the eyes and ears become keen, the temper becomes harmonious and calm, and customs and manners are easily reformed. All the world becomes peaceful and joins together in the joy of beauty and goodness... The gentleman takes joy in carrying out the Way; the petty man takes joy in gratifying his desires. He who curbs his desires in accordance with the Way will be joyful and free from disorder, but he who forgets the Way in the pursuit of desire will fall into delusion and joylessness. Therefore, music is the means of guiding virtue. When music is performed, the people will set their faces toward the true direction. Hence, music is the most effective means to govern men...26

In the Four Books and the Hsun Tzu. // and music are said to have been formulated by the ancient sage kings in order to have their kingdoms perfectly ordered, happy, and harmonious. Professor H. G. Creel, however, points out that the elaborate systems of metaphysical ideas, such as "linking music with numerology, magic, and government," "does not appear in the books of the period before 600 B.C." He says further that,

96 It was said that the morals and even the future of a state could be known by examining its music, so that the king might use this means of learni^n whether his vassals ruled their territories well or ill. But all this appears to be the philosophical elaboration of a later day.27 PP 0

If this is the case, then, it was Confucius and his followers who made music a pedagogically valuable agent in their moral training of the future chun tzu.

Confucius loved music and knew how to play certain instruments. Music was important in his life in letting out his swollen feelings of happiness and sadness, satisfaction and despair in a cultivated way. A passage in the

Analects reports how the notes Confucius was playing one day on the stone chimes, expressing his disappointment at his failure to get public employment and be understood, sounded pathetic and frustrated to the ears of a discerning listener, 28 It reads:

While the Master was playing the stone chimes in Wei, a man who passed in front of the door, carrying a basket, said, "The way he plays the stone chimes is fraught with frustrated purpose.” Presently he added, "How squalid this stubborn sound is. If no one understands him, then he should give up, that is all. When the water is deep, go across by wading; When it is shallow, lift your hem and cross." The Master said, "That is indeed an easy way out."29 (XIV. 42: Lau- Waley)

In another passage, the Analects reports how Confucius loved good songs and to sing them along with others. "When in the Master's presence anyone sang a song that he liked, he did not join in at once, but asked for it to be repeated and then joined in." (VII. 31: Waley)

Widely versed in various musical forms of his time and keenly aware of what music could do to man's soul and his development of character in particular, Confucius contrasted the good and the bad music, honestly showing his personal preference to the former. For example, about the musical pieces known as Shao and Wu, he made the following statements.30

97 The Master said of the Shao that it was perfectly beautiful and also peS good. (A: T£: ‘SiSP* “ “ P8rteC"y b6aUti,Ul but Yen Yuan asked how the government of a country should be administered. The Master said, "...Let the music be the Shao with its pantomimes. Banish the songs of Chang, and keep far from specioLs talkers. The songs of Chang are licentious; specious talkers are dangerous." (A: XV. 10. v. vi: Legge) 6

Of the piece of music called the Kwan Tseu, which accompanied the singing of the first song or poem in the Book of Poetry Confucius said:

The Kwan Tseu is expressive of enjoyment without being licentious and of grief without being hurtfully excessive. (A: III. 20: Legge)

When the Music-Master Chin begins to play and when the Kwan Tseu comes to its end, how the sound fills the ear! (A: VIII. 15: Lau)

While convening with the Music-Masters of Lu, Confucius said:

Their music [the music of the ancients] in so far as one can find out about it began with a strict unison. Soon the musicians were given more liberty [to improvise]; but the tone remained harmonious, brilliant, consistent right on till the close. (A: III. 23: Waley)

Confucius, expressing his preference for the classical to the modern music,

said:

The men of former times, in the matter of ceremonies and music, were rustics, meaning whose music was purer without excessive ornamentation, while the men of these latter times, in ceremonies and music, are accomplished gentlemen. If I have occasion to use those things, I follow the men of former times. (A: XI. 1: Legge)

Mencius, too, according to a tradition, loved music as much as Confucius

did and valued it for its pedagogical effects on man as Confucius had, and

expressed his preference for the classical music to the modern in a

conversation with the king of Ch'i.

When Mencius was received by the King, he said, "Is it true that Your Majesty told Chuang Tzu that you were fond of music?" The King blushed and said, "It is not the music of the Former Kings that I am capable of appreciating. I am merely fond of today's popular music."

98 antiquitymakes SffiS&T ** °' °f 'he ™SiC °< Can I hear more about this9"

the cornpanj?ofrnSny?8ni0yment in the C°mpany °'3 ,ew or e"i™ "In the company of many.” "Let me tell you about enjoyment. Now suppose you were havinn * hel|kCaanHPrirf0rmanCw tJere' and When the pe°p|e h®ard ,he sound of your arhfnn h dH ms !he n0tes of your pipes and ,lu,es they all with V aching heads and knitted brows said to one another, 'In being fond of ™isic' why does our King bring such straits that fathers and sons do not see each other, and brothers, wives and children are parted and scattered. ... On the other hand, suppose you were having a musical performance here, and when the people heard the sound of your bells and drums and the notes of your pipes and flutes they all looked pleased and said to one another, 'Our King must be in good health, otherwise how could he have music performed?' Now if you shared your enjoyment with the people, you would be a true King." (M: I. B. 1: Lau)

In this dialogue, Mencius was clearly implying that the ruler's love of popular, mundane music was one of the causes of the people's suffering and unhappiness, thus Mencius' belief that "Through its music one can know the moral quality of its ruler.” (M: II. A. 2. xxvii) Confucius also said, "If a man be without the virtues proper to humanity or jen, what has he to do with music?"

(A: III. 3: Legge)

Confucius and his followers studied music not only for the means it provided to express in a cultivated way their inner feelings, but also for the harmonious, ordered, and virtuous character worthy of chun tzu it could nurture in them.

The Study of Moral Principles

In discussing the remaining three "things" mentioned in VII. 24 in the

Analects, it is only logical to discuss them along with other specific virtues mentioned in the Four Books, because in teaching specific virtues Confucius and Mencius did not take up one virtue after another in a systematic way, but

99 several virtues at once, thus indicating that all specific moral acts are generated by the single moral reservoir or source called yen «=.) in its broad sense.

At any rate, hsing (ft), the first of the three remaining things Confucius is said to have taught, cannot be considered as a specific virtue like the other two things, namely chung (&), and hsin

Therefore, Legge's rendition of the word as "ethics" and Lau's as "moral conduct" are acceptable. Then, hsing must be considered as a course which investigates the philosophical principles of all virtues and the methods of application of those virtues in actual life.

The other two things - chung, which means faithfulness, devotion, honesty, loyalty, etc., and hsin, which means good faith, truthfulness, trustworthiness, etc. - are only two of the many other social virtues and need to be discussed along with others for their fuller meaning as this section of the study progresses.

According to Confucius, the task of attaining moral excellence of jen is a difficult one because jen cannot be given by others, but can only be attained by the individual who seeks it through self-cultivation. It is a heavy burden to acquire and carry jen,32 but not an impossible task. He said, "Is jen indeed far off? I crave for jen and lo! Jen is right here." (A: VII. 29) Even so, its difficulty is increased, for jen requires the knowledge of all other virtues and the wisdom to know the ways to practice virtues comfortably in actual human situations.

Indiscriminate and inflexible application of any one of these virtues may well produce negative results. Therefore, one must know the fundamental spirit or principles of Perfect Virtue or jen, so that his moral actions may be in harmony with jen.

100 The Chinese character for yen is formed by adding to the character for man (A.) the character for two (i.), making it clear that the concept of yen is a relationship between man and man or two men. Therefore, the man of yen

«=) is one who can relate himself as a human being to another human being or other human beings with all their innate and distinct human qualities according to //. What is yen according to the early Confucians in the Eggr Books? In the Analects, we read:

When Chung Kung asked the meaning of jen, the Master said, "When abroad behave as though you were receiving an important guest. When employing the services of the common people behave as though you were officiating at an important ceremony. Do not impose on others what you yourself do not desire. In this way you will be free from ill will whether in a state or in a family." (XII. 2: Lau-Shin)

Tzu Kung asked, "Is there a single word which can be a guide to conduct throughout one's life?" The Master said, "It is perhaps the word 'shu' fiS)- Do not impose on others what you yourself do not desire " (XV 24: Lau) '

The Master said, "Ts'an! There is one single thread binding my way together." Tseng Tzu assented. After the Master had gone out, the disciples asked, "What did he mean?" Tseng Tzu said, "The way of the Master consists in doing one's best (chung) and in using oneself as a measure to gauge others (shu). That is all." (IV. 15: Lau)

The Master said, "As for jen - you yourself desire rank and standing; then help others to get rank and standing. You want to turn your own merits to account; then help others to turn theirs to account - in fact, the ability to take one's own feelings as a guide - that is the sort of thing that lies in the direction of i£n-" (VI. 28: Waley)

In the Book of Mencius, we read:

Mencius said, "There is no greater joy for me than to find, on self- examination, that I am true to myself. Try your best to treat others as you would wish to be treated yourself (or try your best to be shu). and you will find that this is the shortest way to benevolence (or to jan)." (VII. A. 4: Lau-Shin)

101 Sa‘d’ "!! 'S °f the essence of man’s nature that he do good That Honwinn h™3" ?00cl ,f 3 man does what is evil he is guiltvof the sin of of I!" 31 endowment. Every man has a sense of pity a sense of shame, a sense of respect, a sense of right and wrong. From his sense of pity comes jen (Humanity); from his sense of shame comes vi (Justice); from his sense of respect, H (the observance of rites)- from Ns

fnefnrnm 58* ^ T"9’ ^ - JfllL 1L and dull do not soak in from without, we have them within ourselves... So I say 'Seek them and you have them. Disregard them and you lose them (VI A fi- Dobson) * v •

Mencius said, "It is a feeling common to all mankind that they cannot bear to see others suffer... I say that all men have such feelings because on seeing a child about to fall into a well, everyone has a feeling of horror or distress... Not to feel distress (at the suffering of others) would be contrary to all human feelings... This feeling of distress is the first siqn of m” (II. A. 6: Dobson) y

Shu, translated as "consideration" (Waley) and as "reciprocity" (Dobson) meaning "Never do to others what you would not like them to do to you,” clearly means that the practice of jen consists of putting oneself into the position of others. If personally ambitious to succeed in life, to be aware of the same in others is shu. The virtue of chung is explained as faithfulness or devotion to others, in that desiring to be successful oneself, one also helps others to be successful. Therefore to practice shu and chung is to practice jen.

As we can see in the excerpts from the Book of Mencius cited above,

Mencius identified jen with man's innate "sense of pity" (Dobson) and "the feelings that cannot bear to see others suffer." (Dobson) Mencius coined two phrases to explain this distinct moral quality in man: tse yin chih hsin

( T§'i /^') and Jan ren chih hsin ( )• Legge rendered both phrases as "the feeling of commiseration" and Lau rendered the first phrase as "the heart of compassion" and the second as "a heart sensitive to the suffering of others." At any rate, to Mencius, this feeling of compassion, pity, commiseration, distress at or sensitivity to the suffering of others pertains to jen and is jen. "This feeling, which is jen, is the mind of man,”

102 said Mencius, and "The whole purport of learning is nothing more than this: to regain the mind that has strayed." (VI. A. 11: Dobson)

In cultivating yen or Perfect Virtue, the early Confucians taught the virtue of sincerity, truthfulness, or trustworthiness as extremely important, using the two characters \h{hsin) and i^{cheng). It is interesting to note that both characters are formed by combining the character for "word or words" {\ ) with the character for "man or men" (A-) for hsin (4t), and for cheng

(t$) the character for "word or words" with another character for "to complete or perfect, thus denoting that hsin and cheng have something to do with what one speaks to man or men and completing or perfecting what one has spoken.

About hsin, which is the last of the "four things" Confucius taught according to VII. 24 in the Analects, the Master said, "If a man lacks sincerity or hsin, I do not know how he can get on, any more than a wagon could without a yoke for attaching the horse." (A: II. 23: Creel)33 One of his followers, the philosopher Tsang, said, "I daily examine myself on three points: whether, in transacting business for others, I may have been not faithful (chung); whether in intercourse with friends, I may have been not sincere {hsin)\ whether I may have not mastered and practised the instructions of my teacher." (A: I. 4: Legge)

When asked by Tzu-chang what yen was, Confucius included sincerity [hsin) among the five qualities essential to Perfect Virtue, saying, "Gravity, magnanimity, sincerity {hsin), earnestness, and kindness." (A: XII. 6: Legge)34

However, in the Great Learning and the Doctrine of the Mean, the principle of sincerity, using the character cheng (f$), is expounded as being of paramount importance in cultivating Perfect Virtue. "What the Great Learning

1 03 teaches, is - to illustrate illustrious virtue; to love the people?* and to rest in the highest Good." (G.L.: text 1: Legge-Shin) Then the same text says:

Th*ngs have root and tha'r branches. Affairs have their end and their beginning. To know what is first and what is last will lead near to d what is taught in the Great Learning. 4. The ancients who wished to illustrate illustrious virtue throuqhout the kingdom, first ordered well their own states. Wishing to order well their states, they first regulated their families. Wising to regulate their families they first cultivated their persons. Wishing to cultivate9their persons they first rectified their hearts. Wishing to rectify their hearts, they first souqht to be sincere in their thoughts. Wishing to be sincere in their thouqhts they first extended to the utmost their knowledge. Such extension lav in the investigation of things. y 5. Things being investigated, knowledge became complete Their knowledge being complete, their thoughts were sincere. Their thoughts being sincere, their hearts were then rectified. Their hearts being rectified, their persons were cultivated. Their persons being cultivated, their families were regulated. Their families being regulated, their states were rightly governed. Their states being rightly governed, the whole kingdom was made tranquil and happy. 6. From the Son of Heaven down to the mass of the people, all must consider cultivation of the person the root of everything besides. (Legge)

In short, the above passages clearly mean that a man's wish to be truly sincere by extending his knowledge through investigation of things is the beginning of his moral self-cultivation. In the Doctrine of the Mean, the virtue of cheng is further discussed in the following passages.

Sincerity is the end and the beginning of all things; without sincerity, there is nothing. Therefore, the superior man regards the attainment of sincerity the highest excellence. (XXV. 2)

He who attains to sincerity, is he who chooses what is good, and firmly holds it fast. To this attainment there are requisite the extensive study of what is good, accurate inquiry about it, careful reflection on it, the clear discrimination of it, and the earnest practice of it. (XX. 19: Legge)

The possessor of sincerity develops not himself only; with it, he also develops others. To develop himself completely is to be truly virtuous (or jSQ). (XXV. 3)

It is only he who is possessed of the most complete sincerity that can exist under Heaven, who can give full development to his nature. Able to

104 give its full development to his own nature he can do to same to the nature of other men. (XXII: Legge)

He who has sincerity without effort hits what is right and discerns with™,. Wayn0(XXth108:9LeSgghee) 'S 3 ^ Wh° naturally and readily <°"°ws the

In the Analects. Confucius once said,

The leaving of virtue without proper cultivation; the not thorouqhlv discussing what is learned; not being able to move towards righteousness of which a knowledge is gained; and not being able to change what is not good: these are the things which occasion me solicitude. (A: VII. 3: Legge)

The Dggtrine qf fllfl Mean says the man of sincerity "can assist the transforming and nourishing powers of Heaven and Earth." (XXII: Legge) Then it says, "It is only he who is possessed of the most complete sincerity that can exist under heaven, who can transform others." (XXIII) Sincerity is an active and powerful moral force which 'without display, it becomes manifested; without any movement, it produces changes; and without any effect, it accomplishes its ends." (XXVI. 6: Legge)

To attain sincerity, which can radiate such transforming influence, one must make "a hundred" or even "a thousand efforts"36 until he knows what is good. In the text, it is said:

The superior man, while there is anything he has not studied, or while in what he has studied there is anything he cannot understand, will not intermit his labour. While there is anything he has not inquired about, or anything in what he has inquired about which he does not know, he will not intermit his labour. While there is anything which he has not reflected on, or anything in what he has reflected on which he does not apprehend, he will not intermit his labour. While there is anything which he has not discriminated, or his discrimination is not clear, he will not intermit his labour. If there be anything which he has not practised, or his practise fails in earnestness, he will not intermit his labour. (D.M.: XX. 20: Legge)

Let a man proceed in this way, and, though dull, he will surely become intelligent; though weak, he will surely become strong. (D.M.: XX. 21: Legge)

105 Therefore, to be cheng or sincere is, like to be jen or perfectly virtuous, difficult and burdensome, because it requires the persistent searching for the knowledge of Good. It is clear that in the early Confucian usage, the terms cheng and jen were the same aspiration of the chun-tzu-to-be, and it was to attain perfect moral excellence.

Moreover, as jen comprehends a multitude of other social virtues, so does cheng. When Fan Chih asked about yen, Confucius said, "It is in retreat, to be grave or kung (^); in the management of business, to be reverently attentive or ching ($0; in intercourse with others, to be strictly sincere or chung {&)” (A: XIII. 19: Legge) When Tsze-chang asked about jen, he said, "To be able to practice five things everywhere and under heaven constitutes yen," and they are, "gravity or kung generosity or kwan

(%)> sincerity or hsin (>fe), earnestness or min (4afc), and kindness or hui

(A: XVII. 6: Legge) Confucius also said, "The superior man in everything considers justice or yi (jfc) to be essential. He performs it according to //. He brings it forth in humility or sun He completes it with sincerity or hsin (A: XV. 17: Legge)

In the Four Books, there are numerous other specific social virtues discussed besides the ones cited above, and all of them are treated as practical moral acts to be put into practice in the pervasive principle of Perfect Virtue of jen or cheng or jen-yi in the Mencius, as one confronts specific human problems either as a private individual or as a public official.37

Confucius said, "There are three things constantly on the lips of the gentleman none of which I have succeeded in following: 'A man of benevolence never worries about the future; a man of wisdom is never in two minds about right and wrong; a man of courage is never afraid.’" (A: XIV. 30:

Lau) "Wisdom, benevolence, and courage, these three are the virtues

106 universally binding," says the Doctrine of thn Mean (XX. 8) What is wisdom of chih {*§)?

In cultivating moral excellence, all early Confucians stressed the importance of using man's unique faculty of reason because, in their view, man alone can observe, compare, examine, contemplate, choose, and act according to the dictates of his reason. The purpose of reasoning, therefore, is to know, and the purpose of knowing is to attain wisdom. Man needs to develop the inherent "beginnings of tuan 0$) or yen, yi, //, and chih” in himself, because he is born to be human and in his heart he longs to be truly human and prefers the rational and just to the irrational and unjust, when he uses his reason, which distinguishes him from all other creatures. Mencius said:

He who lacks the feeling of commiseration is not a man; that he who lacks a feeling of shame and dislike is not a man; that he who lacks a feeling of modesty and of yielding is not a man; and that he who lacks a sense of right and wrong is not a man. The feeling of commiseration is the beginning of jgn. The feeling of shame and dislike is the beginning of yi. The feeling of modesty and yielding is the beginning of li. The sense of right and wrong is the beginning of chih or wisdom. Since all men have these four beginnings in themselves, let them know to give them their full development and completion, and the result will be like fire that begins to burn, or of a spring which has begun to vent. Let them have their complete development, and they will suffice to protect all within the four seas. (M: II. A. 6: Bodde)38

Indiscriminate accumulation of knowledge would not give a man his wisdom. He must learn to distinguish between right and wrong, human and inhuman, proper and improper. In the words of Mencius: "The wise embrace all knowledge, but they are most earnest about what is of the greatest importance."

(M: VII. B. 46: Legge)

Fan Chih asked what constituted wisdom. Confucius said, "To give one's self earnestly to the duties due to men, and, while respecting spiritual beings, to keep aloof from them, may be called wisdom." (A: VI. 20: Legge)

107 The man of wisdom to Confucius is he who knows his obligation to his fellowmen to be more important than his obligation to supernatural beings.

The next virtue to be studied is that of courage or yung (j|). Yung is free from fear as Confucius said, "The man of courage is never afraid," (A: IX.

28) but not reckless as the following passages reveal.

Tzu-lu said, "If you were leading the Three Armies, whom would you take with you? 1 The Master said, "I would not take with me anyone who would try to fight a tiger with his bare hands or to walk across the river and die in the process without regrets. If I took anyone it would have to be a man who when faced with a task, was fearful of failure and who, while fond of making plans, was capable of successful execution." (A: VII. 10: Lau)

Tzu-lu said, "does the gentleman consider couraqe a suDreme quality?" The Master said, "For the gentleman it is morality (yi) that is supreme. Possessed of courage but devoid of morality, a gentleman will make trouble while a small man will be a brigand. (A: XVII. 23: Lau)

Tzu-kung said, "Does even the gentleman have dislikes?" The Master said, "Yes... The gentleman has his dislikes... He dislikes those who, while possessing courage, lack the spirit of ]L. The Master asked, "Do you, Ssu, have your dislikes as well?" "I dislike those in whom insolence passes for courage..." (A: XVII. 24: Lau)

To Confucius, "to see which is right (yi) and not to do it is want of courage" (A: II.

24: Legge); therefore, "the man of jen must necessarily have courage." (A: XIV.

5) "For Gentlemen of purpose and men of jen while it is inconceivable that they should seek to stay alive at the expense of jen, it may happen that they have to accept death in order to have jen accomplished." (A: XV. 8: Lau)

Mencius had his own phrase, pu tung hsin which means "the mind that does not waver" or "the mind that remains unmoved," to explain courage. Asked about the way to develop the mind that cannot be moved or stirred, he said:

108 „ Jh.? W'^S commander over the cm,40 while the chi is that which lilk the b°dy. The halts where the will arrives. HencTii is said “Take hold of your will and do not abuse your ch'i" As you have already said that the chi rests where the will arrives what is the point of going on to say, "Take hold of your will and do not abuse your chi?"... May I ask what your strong points are? I have an insight into words. I am good at cultivating my "flood-like May I ask what this "flood-like sM" is? It is difficult to explain. This is a qM which is, in the highest degree T* >ny,n n,n£- Uou"shJx with inte9rity and place no obstacle in its path and it will fill the space between Heaven and Earth. It is a chi which unites rightness and the Way. Deprive it of these and it will collapse. It is born of accumulated rightness and cannot be appropriated by anyone through a sporadic show of rightness. Whenever one acts in a way that falls below the standard set in one's heart, it will collapse... You must work at it and never let it out of your mind. At the same time, while you must never let it out of your mind, you must not forcibly help it grow either... (M: II. A. 2. ix-xvi: Lau)

In short, according to Mencius, true courage or pu tung hsin is possible when a man’s whole being is flooded with the ch'i called hao ran chih ch'i

tjfL). which is born of principles of Perfect Virtue and nourished constantly by them. In the words of Tseng Tzu, courage is "When, on self-examination, I find that I am upright, I will go forward against thousands and tens of thousands." (M: II. A. 2. vii: Lau) The man of courage in the Confucian ideal has moral courage, and physical courage, however thoughtfully executed, is an inferior sort.

Another moral precept extensively discussed in the Analects and the

Book of Mencius is that of hsiau $f) of "filial piety." About the virtue of filial piety, the Analects has the following passages:

Meng I Tzu asked about the treatment of parents. The Master said, "Never disobey!" Fan Chih (who was driving his carriage for him) said, "In what sense did you mean it?" The Master said, "While they are alive, serve them according to li. When they die, bury them according to li and sacrifice to them according to li." (II. 5: Waley)

109 Meng We p0 asked about the treatment of parents. The Master said Behave in such a way that your father and mother have no anxiety about you, except concerning your health." (II. 6: Waley) y

The Master said, "In serving his father and mother a man may qentlv remonstrate with them. But if he sees that he has failed to chanqe their opinion he should resume an attitude of deference and not thwart them- may feel discouraged, but not resentful. (IV. 18: Waley)

The Master said, "If for the whole three years of mourning a son manaqes to carry on the household exactly in his father's day, then he is a good9 son indeed." (IV. 20: Waley) y

The Master said, "A man should not be ignorant of the age of his father and mother. It is a matter, on the one hand, for rejoicing and, on the other hand, for anxiety." (IV. 21: Lau)

Mencius said, "There are three things which are unfilial, and to have no posterity is the greatest of them." (M: IV. A. 26: Legge) Certainly, all the acts or duties mentioned above are commendable aspects of filial piety; to the early

Confucians, it meant more than just performing prescribed duties. Confucius said:

Nowadays for a man to be filial means no more than that he is able to provide his parents with food. Even dogs and horses are, in some way, provided with food. If a man shows no reverence, where is the difference? (A: II. 7: Lau)

Tzu-hsia asked about being filial. The Master said, "What is difficult to manage is the expression of one's face. As for the young taking on the burden when there is work to be done or letting the old enjoy the wine and the food when these are available, that hardly deserves to be called filial." (A: II. 8: Lau)41

They considered filial piety as a basic virtue of great importance in the following passages. Mencius said:

Humanity (ienl attains its finest flower in the service of parents. (M: IV. A. 27: Dobson)

There are many duties one should discharge, but the fulfillment of one's duty towards one’s parents is the most basic. (M: IV. A. 19: Lau)

If only everyone loved his parents and treated his elders with deference, the Empire would be at peace. (M: IV. A. 12: Lau)

no In the Analects, we read:

It is rare for a man who is filial to his parents and obedient to his elders tn nnle '"CVna,IOn t0 tr3ns9ress against his superiors; it is unheard of for one who has no such inclination to be inclined to start a rebellion The fn?^°n.h8rn °Vhe 9enlleman is 10 the roots and fundamentals of thinqs MieHn h lhe f ar® 'established, the Way will grow therefrom. Being9 ' 'a l .h s p,aren’s anvd obedient to his elders: are they not the root of v'- Lau-bnin)

The tie between a man and his parents being the closest of all human relationships, it is not difficult to understand why Confucius and Mencius considered filial piety to be one of the basic moral obligations of man to other human beings. The practice of any virtue at all was naturally expected to begin with and among the members of his own family, but filial piety is only a branch of yen. And jen is the root. When a man's genuine nature jen with its inherent feelings of commiseration (shu) and loyalty (chung) expresses itself in treatment of his own parents, it automatically becomes filial piety. When Mencius said,

"There has never been a man possessing jen who neglected his parents," (M: I.

A. 1. v: Legge), probably he was implying this.

At this point, it must be noted that, in Confucian moral education, the study of religion has no place in the curriculum. Although the existence of spirits, gods, and ghosts is recognized, the early Confucians do not credit them as having any power in shaping man's moral character.

However, the concept of tien, generally rendered in English as Heaven, imparts a considerable influence on a man's moral cultivation, but only as a distant but perfect model for him to contemplate upon and emulate. The word tien (£z) primarily means sky, heaven, or firmament. Its meaning extended, tien represents Nature or the Universe. It also expresses the idea of something natural, as opposed to anything artificial. Giancarlo Finazzo further spells out its additional meanings in the following words. "The remoteness of the sky, its

111 immensity and its beauty are such that man is induced to employ the term denoting it, to signify anything supreme, mysterious and pure."42 Finazzo's arrangement of the moral qualities of Heaven as described in the Four Bonks is transcribed below. Noting that the term tien also indicates "the energy pervading all natural things," he wrote:

This conceptual value which the word stands for finds its clearest enunciation in Monq tse V. A. 6. ii: "All this is lien, what could not be made by man; that which is done without man's doing it is tien "

This energy that pervades things and acts as their organizing principle operates silently: "the doings of the supreme li^n have neither sound nor smell (DM: XXXIII. 6); "does tien speak? The four seasons follow their course and all things are produced, vet does tien speak?" (A- XVII 19 iii); "li£Q does not speak." (M: V. A. 5. iv)

This silent activity is thus peculiar to all natural things; we read f.i. that "the four limbs do not speak and yet understand," (M: VII. A. 21. iv) inferring that they know naturally how to operate and to arrange themselves, (yiz. also M: VII. A. 38)

Its ways are therefore defined as "unfathomable" (DM: XXVI. 7); "extensive and substantial"; "lofty and shining"; "far-reaching and permeating"; "profound and endless." (DM: XXVI. 8. 10)

Its activity appears to be one of "supporting, covering and containing all things" (DM: XXX. 1. 2.), i.e. "all embracing" (DM: XXXI. 3), and following a "cyclical progression" comparable to the progression of the four seasons and the successive shining of the sun and the moon. (DM: XXX. 1.2)

This power, furthermore, "nourishes all things" and makes them pursue their way "without resistance."

The magnitude of their doings is what makes "heaven and earth" so great. (DM: XXX. 3) They produce things in a veracious way which excludes "duplicity," rectifications of repetitions (DM: XXVI. 7), letting things have "one root" (M: III. A. 5. iii) and manifesting a power which is the one "true virtue." (DM: XXXII. 3)

To the Chinese, there was a common principle of moral order throughout the Universe of which human society was only a part. They saw in the Universe or Heaven a moral paragon no chun tzu-to-be should ignore. Having observed

112 and listed the main qualities of Heaven, they concluded that "the way of Heaven is Sincerity." The purpose of their education being to help men attain "sincerity" or cheng, they taught them to get inspiration and learn from the way of Heaven.

This is what Confucius meant when he said, "Without recognizing the ordinance of Heaven it is impossible to be a superior man." (A: XX. 3: Legge) The

DagtrinQ gf lhfi Mqgn, agreed with him, saying, "In order to know men, the superior man may not dispense with the knowledge of Heaven." (XX. 7: Legge)

We must not forget, however, though the knowledge of Heaven is very important, Heaven cannot make man like itself with all the Heavenly qualities cited above. Thus, "Sincerity is the way of Heaven," but "the attainment of sincerity is the way of man." (DM: XX. 18: Legge) As humanists, the early

Confucians denied even Heaven to have any power to make man virtuous. It was entirely the responsibility of each man to cultivate his innate moral qualities, which Heaven had given him.43

Finally, there is a word frequently used in the Four Books with moral overtone: the word is tao (3J). Tao simply means "way" or "road," for example, tao as the way of Heaven and Earth (DM: XXVI. 7. 8) or the way of ease (M: VII. A. 12) or "the crooked way or the straight way" as used in A: XVIII. 2.

When it is used as in A. XV. 31, which reads: "The Master said, ’A gentleman, in his plans, thinks of the way; he does not think how he is going to make a living... But a gentleman’s anxieties concern the progress of the Way; he has no anxiety concerning poverty,"' (Waley) tao is the way of moral principle or "truth," as Legge interpreted it. In the Four Books, tao is used almost always denoting it as the way to moral excellence. The following few passages will be sufficient to show it.

113 The Master said, "The Way is not far from man. When men seek the

Sway. ?y(DM.,n9M XIII.r f1:W ?Legge)y fr°? man*thiS COurse cannot be considered the "Loyalty tebuna) and reciprocity (situ) are not far away from the Wav What you do not like when done to yourself, do not do to others" (DM- XIII. 3: Legge) '

Tszu-hsia said, "The gentleman studies, that he may perfect himself in the Way." (A: XIX. 7: Waley-Shin)

The Master said, "It is Man who is capable of broadening the Way It is not the Way that is capable of broadening Man." (A: XV. 28: Lau)

Tao, then, understood as the way to moral perfection, is what the chun- tzu-Xo-be must certainly know. The utmost importance of knowing the Way is expressed by Confucius in the following statement: "If one hears the Way in the morning, he may die in the evening without regret." (A: IV. 8) And, as with the road, the Way, too, is frequently in need of repair and extension. That is why education, which is the training of man in the capacity of "broadening the Way," becomes very important.

In the Dialogues

The entire curriculum proposed by Socrates-Plato for their ideal state is geared to the production of men and women of the highest virtue. They wanted

only those courses of study which will induce those students with natural

aptitudes for guardianship to cultivate their philosophic minds in the soul to

acquire knowledge of the ultimate virtue.

The children start receiving education at the age of three, first in music for

the mind and then in gymnastics for the body. The term ^ou

for music, as used in the text, has no English equivalent. Music as a curricula,

like wen {X) in the Confucian system, included not only playing the lyre and

the study of music in general, it also included other subjects such as poetry,

letters, culture, and philosophy.44 The education in music for the young children

114 included not only singing and dancing, but also listening to stories created by poets. They are unable yet to read themselves, so the stories are told to them and most of these stories they now tell, we must reject," says Socrates.

To Socrates, it is extremely important to tell the right kind of stories in a correct manner, because "the beginning in every task is the chief thing, especially for any creature that is young and tender." (Rep.: 377 B) Most Greek stories are derived from legends and myths and do not always tell the truth about the gods. These stories are made by poets, and in Socrates’ view almost all the poets, including Homer and Hesiod, are tellers of false stories about the gods for they are ignorant of the true nature of the gods. In the Apology.

Socrates states:

I went to the poets, those of tragedies, and those of dithyrambs, and the rest... taking up the poems of theirs that seemed to me to have been most carefully elaborated by them, I asked them what they meant, that I might at the same time learn something from them. Now I am ashamed to tell you the truth, gentlemen; but still it must be told. For there was hardly a man present, one might say, who would not speak better than they about the poems they themselves had composed. So again in the case of the poets also I presently recognized this, that what they composed they composed not by wisdom, but by nature and because they were inspired, like the prophets and givers of oracles; for these also say many fine things, but know none of the things they say; it was evident to me that the poets too had experienced something of this same sort. And at the same time I perceived that they, on account of their poetry, thought they were the wisest of men in other things as well, in which they were not. (22 B-C)

Socrates thinks that there are two kinds of stories, the one true and the other false, and that the false stories must be banned. If the stories are about god, "the true qualities of god we must always surely attribute to him whether we compose in epic, melic, or tragic verse... And is not god of course good in reality and always to be spoken of as such?" says Socrates. (Rep.: 379 B) His complaint about the existing literature and poetry is that it does not illustrate the gods as they really are. Insisting on his own view of god as nothing but good,

115 Socrates asserts that god cannot be the cause of evil things. He says, "This then will be one of the laws and patterns concerning the gods to which speakers and poets will be required to conform that God is not the cause of the things, but only of the good." (Efift.: 380 C) Therefore, he says, "we shall condemn as a foolish error Homer's description of Zeus as the dispenser alike of good and of evil to mortals." (Ml.: 379 E) And "we surely will not say that

God is deficient in either beauty or virtue," says Socrates. (Rep.: 381 C) In short, the children must be taught to understand that the gods are unchanging, non-deceptive, and truthful. Moreover, the stories which discourage bravery and moderation must not be told, and also the stories which suggest that injustice is profitable must be forbidden.45

The children, especially older ones, are allowed to take part in telling the stories by reciting certain lines or imitating certain characters in the stories, but they are allowed only the parts of the good men. Socrates gives the reason for this restriction as follows:

If they imitate they should from childhood up imitate what is appropriate to them - men, that is, who are brave, sober, pious, free and all things of the kind but things unbecoming the free man they should neither do nor be clever at imitating, nor yet any other shameful thing, lest from the imitation they imbibe the reality. Or have you not observed that imitations, if continued from youth far into life, settle down into habits and [second] nature in the body, the speech, and the thought? (R: 395 C-D)

He forbids his guardians-to-be to play many different roles in a performance for the simple reason that "each one can practice well only one pursuit and not many, but if he attempts the latter, dabbling in many things, he would fail of distinction in all... And does not the same rule hold for imitation, that the same man is not able to imitate many things well as he can one?" (Rep.: 394 E)

"Neither can the same men be actors for tragedies and comedies." (Ml.: 395

B) Moreover, the future guardians are neither allowed to imitate the characters

11 6 of women, slaves, and undisciplined men, nor the sounds and noises of animals and other things, such as "the roar of the sea and the thunder and everything of that kind." (Mi.: 395 D - 396 B)

To Socrates, the style and manner of telling stories are equally important as the content of stories. After identifying basically three styles of audio-visual representation of stories, he favors the simple third-person narrative style over the styles that require dramatic imitation only and that combine narration and imitation. He says, "For ourselves, we shall for our own good employ story¬ tellers and poets who are severe rather than amusing, who portray the style of the good man and in their works abide by the principles we laid down for them..." (Mi.: 397 C) Aiming at training the future guardians in truthfulness, goodness, courage, and modesty in their character, Socrates does not think it right to expose them while they are young to fictitious literature and allow them to play the roles of undesirable characters or multiple roles even in an accepted performance.

The training in "music" as we understand the term today was very important. In the Timaeus. we read:

Concerning sound also and hearing... they were bestowed by the Gods... Music, too, in so far as it uses audible sound, was bestowed for the sake of harmony. And harmony, which has motions akin to the revolutions of the Soul within us, was given by the Muses to him who makes intelligent use of the Muses, not as an aid to irrational pleasure, as is now supposed, but as an auxiliary to the inner revolution of the Soul, when it has lost its harmony, to assist in restoring it to order and concern with itself. And because of the unmodulated condition, deficient in grace, which exists in most of us, Rhythm also was bestowed upon us to be our helper by the same deities and for the same ends. (47 C - E)

In the above passages from his myth of Creation of the Universe, Plato

has Timaeus say that music with its harmony and rhythm was with man from the

117 beginning of time and it was to help man keep his soul in order and harmony.

In the Peppplig. Socrates describes how the works of art in general and music in particular can affect man's soul in the following poetic passages.

Is it, then, only the poets that we must supervise and compel to embody in their poems the semblance of the good character or else not ^fnr°^ham°.n9 US’ 0r must we keep watch over the other craftsmen, and forbid them to represent the evil disposition, the licentious, the illiberal, the graceless, either in the likeness of living creatures'or in buildings or in any other product of their art, on penalty, if unable to obey of being forbidden to practise their art among us, that our guardians may not be bred among symbols of evil, as it were in a pasturage of poisonous herbs, lest grazing freely and cropping from many such day bv day they little by little and all unawares accumulate and build up a huae mass of evil in their own souls. y But we must look for those craftsmen who by the happy gift of nature are capable of following the train of true beauty and grace, that our young men dwelling as it were in a salubrious region, may receive benefit from all things about them, whence the influence that emanates from works of beauty may waft itself to eye or ear like a breeze that brings from wholesome places health, and so from earliest childhood insensibly guide them to likeness, to friendship, to harmony with beautiful reason... And is it not for this reason... that education in music is most sovereign, because more than anything else rhythm and harmony find their way to the inmost soul and take strongest hold upon it, bringing with them and imparting grace, if one is rightly trained, and otherwise the contrary? And further, because omissions and the failure of beauty in things badly made or grown would be most quickly received by one who was properly educated in music, and so, feeling distaste rightly, he would praise beautiful things and take delight in them and receive them into his soul to foster its growth and become himself beautiful and good. The ugly he would rightly disapprove of and hate while still young and yet unable to apprehend the reason, but when reason came the man thus nurtured would be the first to give her welcome, for by this affinity he would know her. (401 B - 402 A)

Socrates imposes the same sort of strict rules on the content and style of music as he does on literature, because of the importance of music in education and his desire to keep it as an effective course of study in the training of moral character of the guardians.

In its broadest sense, music in ancient Greece consisted of melody, dance and poetry, and poetry was always chanted to the accompaniment of

118 instruments and also gestures. The Homeric bard sang his ode and strummed his lyre as he told stories.** The song," Socrates says, "is composed ot three things, the words, the melody, and the rhythm. And the melody and the rhythm must follow the words." ©SB.: 398 A - B) The words being the direct expression of man’s reason, therefore, reason must lead also in musical performance.

Socrates dismisses as unsuitable "the dirge-like modes of music " identified by his musician friend Glaucon as "the mixed Lydian and the tense

Lydian modes," and "certain Ionian and also Lydian modes that are called lax," for they are only suited for drunkenness, unmanliness, and idleness.47

Confessing his ignorance of other musical modes by name, yet he says, "Leave us those two modes - the enforced and the voluntary - that will best represent the utterance of men failing or succeeding, the temperate, the brace - leave us these." (Re£.: 398 E - 399 C) He bans those musical instruments of many strings or a wide harmonic range, such as harps, zithers, and also the flutes which have "the widest harmonic range of all," and allows only the lyre and the zithara in the city and "in the fields the shepherds would have a little piccolo to pipe on." (jjaid.: 399 C - D)

Socrates now discusses the importance of rhythm in music and what it does to man's soul. In the Republic, he, again confessing his inability to explain it in technical terms, insists, nevertheless, that rhythms which suit a life of courage and discipline must be allowed.48 He thinks that beauty and ugliness result from good rhythm and bad and says:

Good or bad rhythm and also tunefulness or discord in music go with the quality of the poetry; for they will be modelled after its form, if, as we have said, metre and music must be adapted to the sense of the words... And the content of the poetry and the manner in which it is expressed depend, in their turn, on moral character... Thus then, excellence of form and content in discourse and of musical expression and rhythm, and

1 1 9 grace of form and movement, all depend on goodness of nature bv V.nnll n=t6an-K0t.the ,00l'Sh simPlici,V sometimes called by courtesy artru“abHsUhedna,Ure in ^ 9°°dneSS °f Character has been well h A"d the absence of grace, rhythm, harmony is nearly allied to baseness of thought and expression and baseness of character- 7!®“^ Presence goes with that moral excellence and self-masterv of which they are the embodiment. (400 C - 401 A: Cornford) ^

"Pleasure is indeed a proper criterion in the arts," Plato has the Athenian

concede in the LaittS, "but not the pleasure experienced by anybody and

everybody. The productions of the Muse are at their finest when they delight

men of high calibre whose education and moral standards reach heights

attained by no one else." (658 E: Saunders) Deeply distressed by the

contemporary trends in music and literature which were arousing man's

passion for pleasure more than his desire for moral excellence, Socrates and

Plato have a director of music appointed to regulate the arts.49 The director

must appoint censors of at least fifty years of age and make them select from

any ancient composition what seems to come up to standard with the

knowledge that "among the works we have inherited from the past there are a

great many grand old pieces of music,"50 reject unsuitable ones, and revise or

rearrange substandard pieces, on the advice of poets and musicians.51 They

are also charged to regulate the songs suitable for men and those suitable for

women, "so an elevated manner and courageous instinct must be regarded as

characteristic of the male, while a tendency to modesty and restraint must be

presented - theory and law alike - as a peculiarly feminine train." (Laws: 802 E:

Saunders) They are also responsible to determine whether or not music is correctly taught to the young.52 Why all these restriction and censorship? It is because:

...we and these guardians we are to bring up will never be fully cultivated until we can recognize the essential form of temperance, courage, liberality, high-mindedness, and all other kindred qualities, and also their

120 opposites, wherever they occur. We must be able to discern the presence of these forms themselves and also of their images in anythino nr? ,tcontams them-realizing that to recognize either, the same skill and9 practice are required, and that the most insignificant instance is not beneath our notice. (R: 402 C: Cornford)

In concluding this section of study on musical training, it must be repeated that for Socrates and Plato only poetry or literature and music fitting all above indicated specifications will be permitted in the education of the guardians, because there is a connection between beauty and order in music and the corresponding features of character and of soul.

Socrates turns now to the other of the "two formal lessons or courses" required of all citizens between the ages of three and twenty, gymnastics or the physical training. At the outset of his discussion on gymnastics, he says he does not believe "that a sound body by its excellence makes the soul good, but on the contrary that a good soul by its virtue renders the body the best that is possible." (Rep.: 403 D) By this statement, Socrates implies that even in physical training the soul that can reason soundly can produce a sound result and give it its true meaning.

Gymnastic training involves not just physical exercises, but many other things including a regulated life style, correct diet, and competitions. There are many things one should not do. For example, from intoxication he must abstain

(Ibid.: 403 E), even though the drinking party is considered a valuable educational medium to test a man’s true nature and also to help him acquire and exercise the virtue of self-control by being exposed to conditions in which he can be easily tempted to be licentious. (Laws: 645 D - 650 B) Too much sleeping and sumptuous eating are mentioned to be the causes of dull mind and physical illness and, therefore, must be avoided. (Rep.: 404 A - 405 A)

Gymnastics is adopted as a curricula not merely to develop strength and athletic agility, but "chiefly for the soul's sake." (Mi.: 410 B) And the training in

121 music and gymnastics must be balanced or must compliment each other, because "the devotees of unmitigated gymnastics turn out more brutal than they should be and those of music softer than is good for them... They must be harmoniously adjusted to one another... And the soul of the man thus attuned is sober and brave." (Ml.: 410 D-E) "Then he who best blends gymnastics with music and applies them most suitably to the soul is a man whom we should most rightly pronounce to be the most perfect and harmonious musician... rather than one who brings the strings into unison with one another." (ibid.: 412 A)

However, the training in music and gymnastics for males and females between the ages of three and twenty is only the first stage of moral education for future leaders of the state. Socrates says, "gymnastics is devoted to that which grows and decays of the body. Then this cannot be the study that we seek." (Ibid.: 521 E) About the training in music, too, Socrates has the following statement to make.

It educated the guardians through habits, imparting by melody a certain harmony of spirit that is not science, and by the rhythm measure and grace, and qualities akin to those in the words of tales that are fables and those that are more nearly true. But it included no study that tended to any such good as you are now seeking. (Ibid.: 522)

Therefore, to the next stage of moral education, Socrates lists the following studies as indispensable: Arithmetic, geometry, astronomy, and harmonics.

Arithmetic

To activate and sharpen man's inborn faculty of reason, which alone will ultimately seek, contemplate, and acquire the knowledge of the good, the study of arithmetic is one of the basic courses Socrates insists that all future

122 guardians must take. "This common thing," says Socrates in the Republic "that all arts and forms of thought and all sciences employ... is among the first things that everybody must learn." (522 C) Because the mathematical studies "naturally conduce to the awakening of thought."53

In the world of endless dualities to our sense perception, such as of

bigness and smallness, thickness and thinness, softness and hardness,

lightness and heaviness, and so on, "naturally," says Socrates, "it is in such cases as these that the soul first summons to its aid the calculating reason and tries to consider whether each of the things reported to it is one or two." (523 B)

He explains further that "reckoning and the science of arithmetic are wholly concerned with number... And the qualities of number appear to lead to the apprehension of truth." Therefore, "these would be among the studies that we are seeking. For a soldier must learn them in order to marshal his troops, and a philosopher, because he must rise out of the region of generation and lay hold on essence or he can never become a true reckoner... And our guardian is soldier and philosopher in one." (525 A - B) Elaborating his point once more

Socrates says:

Those who are to take part in the highest functions of state must be induced to approach it, not in an amateur spirit, but perseveringly, until, by the aid of pure thought, they come to see the real nature of number. They are to practise calculation, not like merchants or shopkeepers for purposes of buying and selling, but with a view to war and to help in the conversion of the soul itself from the world of becoming to truth and reality... Moreover, talking of this study, it occurs to me now what a fine thing it is and in how many ways it will further our intentions, if it is pursued for the sake of knowledge and not for commercial ends. As we were saying, it has a great power of leading the mind upwards and forcing it to reason about pure numbers, refusing to discuss collections of material things which can be seen and touched. Good mathematicians, as of course you know, scornfully reject any attempt to cut up the unit itself into parts: if you try to break it up small, they will multiply it up again, taking good care that the unit shall never lose its oneness and appear as a multitude of parts...

123 eir^Y°wSee’ thuen’that this study is real|y indispensable for our Duroose though, 085 ,h9 mind ,0 arrive at pure '"u,h bV,he exercise o, puT ' n=,.„^e y^"®“?8d' too, how people with a talent for calculation are £ rSc 2 cf* gaming almost any other subject; and how a training in it makes a slow mind quicker, even if it does no other good? 9 Also, it would not be easy to find many branches for study which requ're more effort from the learner. For all these reasons we cannot do Cornford) °rm °f training for the most gifted natures- (R- 525 B - 526 C:

Geometry

After arithmetic, Socrates identifies geometry as another study that would train the soul to direct its vision toward where the essential form of good is.54

He believes that geometry "can facilitate the apprehension of the idea of good and compel the soul to contemplate essence,” thus, it is a suitable study.55

Socrates explains why geometry can be a right subject of study as follows.

The real object of the entire study is pure knowledge... That it is the knowledge of that which always is, and not of a something which at some time comes into being and passes away... for geometry is the knowledge of the eternally existent... [Moreover] it would tend to draw the soul to truth, and would be productive of a philosophic attitude of mind. (R: 527 A - C: Shorey)

Like the study of arithmetic, Socrates says that even the by-products of the study of geometry are valuable for its uses in war and "for the better reception of all studies there will be an immeasurable difference between the student who has been imbued with geometry and the one who has not."56

Therefore, he concludes, those who dream of building an ideal state should not neglect geometry.

124 Astronomy and Harmonics

After arithmetic and geometry, Socrates now lists astronomy and harmonics as two other important subjects his future guardians must study before entering the last stage of moral training in dialectics.

His reasons for picking astronomy and harmonics are briefly explained in the Republic as follows.

It is indeed no trifling task but very difficult to realize that there is in every soul an organ or instrument of knowledge that is purified and kindled afresh by such studies when it has been destroyed and blinded by our ordinary pursuits, a faculty whose preservation outweighs ten thousand eyes; for by it only is reality beheld. (R: 527 D-E: Shorey)

To Glaucon's question of how it ought to be taught to meet the expected result,

Socrates answers:

[T]hese sparks that paint the sky since they are decoration on a visible surface, we must regard, to be sure, as the fairest and most exact of material things: but we must recognize that they fall far short of the truth, the movements, namely, of real speed and real slowness in true number and in all true figures both in relation to one another and as vehicles of the things they carry and contain. These can be apprehended only by reason and thought, but not by sight... Then, we must use the blazonry of the heavens as patterns to aid in the study of those realities. (R: 529 C - E: Shorey)57

What about harmonics? "As the eyes are framed for astronomy," says

Socrates, "so the ears are framed for the movements of harmony."58 He explains his reason for endorsing harmonics as a valuable study contrary to its current use as follows. Having agreed with the Pythagorians who consider astronomy and harmonics to be sister sciences, Socrates says:

[0]nly we must constantly hold by our own principle, not to let our pupils take up any study in an imperfect form, stopping short of that higher region to which all studies should attain, as we said just now in speaking of astronomy. As you will know, the students of harmony make the same sort of mistake as the astronomers: they waste their time in measuring audible concords and sounds one against another. Yes, said Glaucon, they are absurd enough, with their talk of 'groups of quarter-tones' and all the rest of it. They lay their ears to the instrument

125 Svl'hlcansWMofJ? over,hear >he conversation from next door. One can ^tin detect a note in between, giving the smallest possible J®^3 ’ .whlch ought to be taken as the unit of measurement, while Bo?hhnrplflSI?i!,S that thGre is now no difference between the two notes Both prefer their ears to their intelligence. . „ f800^68 says:] You are thinking of those worthy musicians who torture the stnngs, racking them on the pegs. I will not push the metaphor so far as to picture the musician beating them with the plectrum and charging them with faults which the strings deny or brazen out. I will drop the comparison and tell you that I am thinking rather of those Pythagorians whom we were going to consult about harmony They are just like the astronomers - intent upon the numerical properties embodied in these audible consonances: they do not rise to the level of formulating problems and inquiring which numbers are inherently consonant and which are not, and for what reasons. (R- 531 A - C- Shorey)

In short he calls these studies useful, but "only when pursued as a means to the knowledge of beauty and goodness."59

In the Dialects

According to Socrates, all the studies so far mentioned are invaluable for the future leaders of state, but not all aspirants are successful in cultivating in themselves a certain philosophic mind that can pursue the ultimate object of all

studies, the Good. Although these are important as preparatory disciplines

before search for the knowledge of the Good in the next and final stage or moral

education, none of these studies can make the student grasp any absolutely

self-evident and unconditional principle, because of the inherent defect of these

studies. According to Socrates the various studies are not taken synoptically as

one connected whole, but studied separately based on the assumption of its

own fixed premises, thus producing a separate chain of deductive reasoning,

self-evident but not linked at the upper end to any self-evident principle.60

Therefore, he is compelled to come up with a new discipline which will secure

this synoptic view of all mathematical knowledge in connexion with the whole of

reality. For Socrates this consummate discipline is dialectics. He is certain that

126 ’this course of study will... contribute to the end we desire and not be labour wasted, only if it is carried to the point at which reflection can take a comprehensive view of the mutual relations and affinities which bind all these sciences together." (Esq.: 531 C - D: Cornford)6i

Dialectic is not only the study of the nature of the good, but also the method of getting the knowledge of the Good. The Good belongs to the realm of the eternal, unchanging, real, and intelligible worlds ihe knowledge of the

Good, therefore, can be attained only by those who are proven to be most richly endowed with the ability to pursue the knowledge all the way until they get it with love and devotion after the successful completion of the mathematical studies. Socrates says:

The summit of the intelligible world is reached in philosophic discussion by one who aspires, through the discourse of reason unaided by any of the senses, to make his way in every case to the essential reality and perseveres until he has grasped by pure intelligence the very nature of Goodness itself. This journey is what we call Dialectic. (R: 532 B: Cornford)

He asserts that the highest of all realities, the Good, "can be revealed only to one who is trained in the studies we have discussed, and to him only by the power of dialectic."63 The method of dialectic and what it does are explained in the Republic in the following way. Socrates says:

No one will maintain against us that there is any other method of inquiry which systematically attempts in every case to grasp the nature of each thing as it is in itself. The other arts are nearly all concerned with human opinions and desires, or with the production of natural and artificial things, or with the care of them when produced. There remain geometry and those other allied studies which, as we said, do in some measure apprehend reality; but we observe that they cannot yield anything clearer than a dream-like vision of the real so long as they leave the assumptions they employ unquestioned and can give no account of them. If your premise is something you do not really know and your conclusion and the intermediate steps are a tissue of things you do not really know, your reasoning may be consistent with itself, but how can it ever amount to knowledge? (533 B - C: Cornford)

127 Furthermore, on the method of dialectic, he says that it is "the only one which takes this course, doing away with assumptions and traveling up to the first principle of all, so as to make sure of confirmation there."64 Socrates describes a master of dialectic in the following quote.

...He must be able to distinguish the essential nature of Goodness isolating it from all other Forms; he must fight his way through all criticisms, determined to examine every step by the standard not of apPearances and opinions, but of reality and truth, and win through to the end without sustaining a fall. If he cannot do this, he will know neither Goodness itself nor any good things; if he does lay hold upon some semblance of good, it will be only a matter of belief, not of knowledqe (534 C: Cornford) a '

Therefore, he concludes that this discipline, which will make those who are selected to be in the final stage of moral education masters of the technique of asking and answering questions, is the most important of all studies.

The Four Cardinal Virtues and the Good Itself

Now, as the select few are mastering the technique of dialectic, they are at the same time pursuing the knowledge of the Good or the Form of the Good using the technique.65 Having declared the Form of the Good or the Good itself to be the highest object of knowledge, Socrates is certain that one can attain that knowledge through dialectic, because the Form of the Good dwells in the intelligible world which no other studies including mathematics can explore.66

For repeatedly insisting that all virtues, whether individual or civic, are only varied and derived expressions of the timeless, immutable and ultimate

Good, Socrates is pressed for the definition of the Good. He confesses his inability to render it, but agrees to engage in a dialectical pursuit after it until they come as close as they can to the clearest possible understanding of the

Good. "Socrates," asks Glaucon, "what is your own account of the Good?...We

should be quite content with an account of the Good like the one you gave us of

128 justice and temperance and the other virtues."*? Socrates responds with the following words.

...I am afraid it is beyond my powers; with the best will in the world I should only disgrace myself and be laughed at. No, for the moment let us leave the question of the real meaning of good; to arrive at what I at any rate believe it to be would call for an effort too ambitious for an inquiry like ours. However, I will tell you, though only if you wish it what I picture to myself as the offspring of the Good and the thing most nearlv resembling it. (R; 506 D - E: Cornford) y

Before proceeding to the inquiry of the "offspring of the Good," Socrates reminds Glaucon of the existence of the two realms of cognition: one, the visible realm of sensible appearances with changeable beliefs and the other, the intelligible realm of timeless and immutable Forms, dominated by the Good

Accordingly, the things that can be seen are not objects of rational thought, but the invisible Forms are.68 The following quote from the Republic will show the way a philosophical discussion is conducted and at the same time what

Socrates means by the "offspring of the Good" and its relationship to the Good itself.

And we see things with our eyesight, just as we hear sounds with our ears and, to speak generally, perceive any sensible thing with out sense- faculties. Of course. Have you noticed, then, that the artificer who designed the senses has been exceptionally lavish of his materials in making the eyes able to see and their objects visible? That never occurred to me. Well, look at it in this way. Hearing and sound do not stand in need of any third thing, without which the ear will not hear nor sound be heard; and I think the same is true of most, not to say all, of the other senses. Can you think of one that does require anything of the sort? No, I cannot. But there is this need in the case of sight and its objects. You may have the power of vision in your eyes and try to use it, and colour may be there in the objects; but sight will see nothing and the colours will remain invisible in the absence of a third thing peculiarly constituted to serve this very purpose. By which you mean —?

129 Naturally I mean what you call light; and if light is a thinq of value the sense of sight and the power of being visible are linked together by a very precious bond, such as unites no other sense with its object V No one could say that light is not a precious thing And of all the divinities in the skies is there one whose light, above all t e rest, is responsible for making our eyes see perfectly and making objects perfectly visible? 9 There can be no two opinions: of course you mean the Sun And how is sight related to this deity? Neither sight nor the eve ^CLCH°f^S rt*u thG Sun’ but 0f al1 the sense-organs it is the most sun- like, and further, the power it possesses is dispensed by the Sun like a stream flooding the eye. And again, the Sun is not vision, but it is the cause of vision and also is seen by the vision it causes Yes. It was the Sun, then, that I meant when I spoke of that off-spring which the Good has created in the visible world, to stand there in the same relation to vision and visible things as that which the Good itself bears in the intelligible world to intelligence and to intelligible objects How is that? You must explain further. You know what happens when the colours of things are no longer irradiated by the daylight, but only by the fainter luminaries of the night: when you look at them, the eyes are dim and seem almost blind, as if there were no unclouded vision in them. But when you look at things on which the Sun is shining, the same eyes see distinctly and it becomes evident that they do contain the power of vision. Certainly. Apply this comparison, then, to the soul. When its gaze is fixed upon an object irradiated by truth and reality, the soul gains understanding and knowledge and is manifestly in possession of intelligence. But when it looks towards that twilight world of things that come into existence and pass away, its sight is dim and it has only opinions and beliefs which shift to and fro, and now it seems like a thing that has no intelligence. That is true. This, then, which gives to the objects of knowledge their truth and to him who knows them his power of knowing, is the Form or essential nature of Goodness. It is the cause of knowledge and truth and to him who knows them his power of knowing, is the Form or essential nature of Goodness. It is the cause of knowledge and truth; and so, while you may think of it as an object of knowledge, you will do well to regard it as something beyond truth and knowledge and, precious as these both are, of still higher worth. And, just as in our analogy light and vision were to be thought of as like the Sun, but not identical with it, so here both knowledge and truth are to be regarded as like the Good, but to identify either with the Good is wrong. The Good must hold yet a higher place of honour. You are giving it a position of extraordinary splendour, if it is the source of knowledge and truth and itself surpasses them in worth. You surely cannot mean that it is pleasure.

130 . ^Hea^en for?d’ 1 exclaimed- B|Jt I want to follow up our analoov still fVr!['f1r- You Wl11 a9ree that the Sun not only makes the things we see visible but also brings them into existence and gives them growth and nounshment: yet he is not the same thing as existence. And so, with the objects of knowledge: these derive from the Good not only their power of being known, but their very being and reality; and Goodness is not the

poweVTR' *507WB?cSrnfoT SUrpaSSi"9 * in

In short, Socrates makes it clear that the offspring of the Good can be known by the soul’s reasoning power illuminated by the Good itself, but the

Good itself remains beyond the grasp of human reason and defies description.

But it can be seen by a leap of the mind. This process can be called intuition.

This flash of insight or self-revelation of the Good itself comes only to those who have made a persistent inquiry about the Good for the love of it. This is what

Socrates means by supreme knowledge.

Good as a virtue is variously described in many dialogues. For instance,

in the Philebus. Socrates describes the Good as being perfect and sufficient

and he goes on the declare that "no one can deny that all percipient beings desire and hunt after the good, and are eager to catch and have the good about them, and care not for the attainment of anything which is not accompanied by

good."69 The Good is mentioned as having three components: Beauty,

Symmetry, and Truth, all intermixed in the Good itself to make it truly good.70 In the Laws, goodness is said to be of two kinds, human and divine. The human

goods are health, beauty, bodily strength, swiftness in running and agility, and

wealth. The divine goods are wisdom, temperance, justice from the union of wisdom and temperance, and fourth in the scale, courage.71 Contrasting the

powers of good and evil, Socrates says "that which destroys the corrupt in every case is the evil; that which preserves and benefits it the good."72

131 The divine kinds of the Good mentioned above are extensively discussed

throughout the dialogues, although none of the so-called Four Cardinal Virtues is dealt with separately in a conclusive way.

In the BfiClMc. they are discussed as the indispensable qualities of the

individuals composing the state in their public capacity as citizens first, and

then, as equally important moral qualities to be had by the private citizens.

Wisdom

Wisdom {crofCct ) is mentioned in the Republic as the only

virtue of the four which is not acquired by habit, but is "of a more divine quality, a

thing that never loses its potency,"™ innate, and the gift of God, of whom it is the

peculiar attribute and prerogative.74 The man with wisdom is described as one

who knows himself, being capable of examining what he knows or does not

know, and see what others know and do not know. In the Charmides. Socrates

says: "This is the state and virtue of wisdom, or temperance, and self-

knowledge, which is just knowing what a man knows, and what he does not know."75

In the Phaedo. Socrates says that "true virtue exists only with wisdom,

whether pleasures and fears and other things of that sort are added or taken

away... Truth is in fact a purification from all these things.”76 A few passages

later in the same dialogue, wisdom is said to be the virtue which purges the soul

from her wanderings and helps her to settle with the timeless and constant

truth.77 And it is this virtue that effects the soul's progress from darkness to light

and makes her see the Good, and in fact, wisdom is said to be very much like the Good, "because it has a large share of the three elements of the Good,

namely Beauty, Symmetry, and Truth."78

132 The following passages in the MenQ seem to express Socrates' view of wisdom most clearly. He says:

in brief, all the undertakings and endurances of the soul, when guided by wisdom, end in happiness, but when folly guides in the opposite... Then may we assert this as a universal rule, that in man all other things depend upon the soul, while the things of the soul herself depend upon wisdom, if they are to be good; and so by this account the profitable will be wisdom, and virtue, we say, is profitable. (88 C & E: Lamb)

Finally, it is stated repeatedly in the Flepublic and the Laws in particular that the virtue of wisdom must be present in the guardians. For the ideal state the guardians, who must counsel wisely in order to maintain harmonious relations among people and states, the virtue of wisdom is the most important of the four, simply because without a knowledge which advises, "not about any particular thing in the state, but about the whole and for the best,"79 no guardian would be able to perform his duty. Thus, wisdom is for the philosopher-kings, whose number may be the smallest, but who comprise the most important class in the state.

Temperance

The virtue of o'uxfporvvy, variously translated in English as

"temperance," "sobriety," "prudence," "modesty," "self-control," etc., is what restrains men "by the advice of the proverbial expression 'nothing too much,' which guides their actions."80

In the Charmides. many definitions of this virtue are mentioned.

Temperance is defined as "quietness," "modesty," "minding one’s own business," and "self-knowledge - knowing what we know and what we do not know.”81 Socrates does not consider these definitions to be adequate. In his understanding, the virtue of temperance is what gives the health and order to

133 the soul,82 because it brings harmony to all other elements that make the soul sound and healthy.8^ Hg says;

...Viewed from hors it bears more likeness to a kind of concord and nfHpr0rnHthan th+e °ther ™nues did- Soberness is a kind of beautiful order and a continence of certain pleasures and appetites, as they sav using the phrase ’master of himself I know not how.P But, the intended meanmg of th's way of speaking appears to me to be that the soul of a man within him has a better part and a worse part, and the expression ?RT(n. 430 t - 431 A:s cShorey)ke C0r? tr01 0f the WOrse by the natural|y better part,

The virtue of temperance can be cultivated by habit and practice,84 by partaking in common meals,85 in gymnastic exercises and the study of simple harmonious music.86

In the Lavys, temperance is described as "the inseparable companion of all the other parts of virtue."87 As the virtue of courage, for example, separated

from temperance or justice devoid of temperance cannot be true courage or

justice. In a way, this aspect of temperance makes it rather an appendage or

condition to make other virtues truly excellent than itself a virtue.88 Temperance is further discussed in the Laws as the quality which gives control over self.

Together with courage, temperance is the strength that not only makes us

endure physical sufferings without losing our self-possession, but also

overcome the temptation of self-destructive and excessive pleasure.89

In the Republic, temperance in an individual is said to be the quality that

makes the three elements of the soul work in harmony and cooperation; and in the state, like wisdom, it assures that those who are superior by nature rule over the inferior in order to produce a perfect working harmony among the different classes. In this respect, it is unlike wisdom or courage, but more like justice in that it is not the exclusive possession of a class of citizens within the state, but a

virtue which needs to be cultivated by all.90

134 Courage

In the Laches, courage (&v8f&ia ) is defined by Laches, first, as "anyone who is willing to stay at his post and face the enemy, and does not run away,”91 and secondly, as "a certain endurance of the soul."93 Nicias introduces a third definition saying that courage is "the knowledge of what is to be dreaded or dared, either in war or in anything else."93 He says:

I do not describe animals, or anything else that from thoughtlessness has no fear of the dreadful, as courageous, but rather as fearless and foolish. Or do you suppose I describe all children as courageous that have no fear because they are thoughtless? I rather hold that the fearless and the courageous are not the same thing. In my opinion very few people are endowed with courage and forethought, while rashness, boldness, and fearlessness, with no forethought to guide it, are found in a great number of men, women, children, and animals. So you see, the acts that you and most people call courageous, I call rash, and it is the prudent acts which I speak of that are courageous. (197 A - C: Lamb)

Advancing Nicias' idea of courage which is combined with thoughtfulness, Socrates states in the Republic that courage is that element or quality or power in man which makes him preserve under all circumstances the wisdom which knows what ought or ought not to be feared. In his view, to know what is good or evil is to be wise. Therefore, courage exhibited without the aid

of wisdom cannot be accepted as courage. Laches' view of courage, that is, to

stay at one's post and face the enemy and endure all sufferings, too, is not

enough without wisdom to be called truly courageous.94

Courage, as one of the essential qualities of the guardianship, is never

questioned. In fact, Socrates points out that a true guardian must be "keen of

perception, quick in pursuit of what he has apprehended, and strong too if he

has to fight it out with his capacity," and "he must further be brave if he is to fight

well,"95 but without the philosophic power or wisdom in his soul working with the

spirited element also in the soul, he will not be truly courageous.

135 In the Statesman, courage and temperance are defined as two distinctly different parts of virtue. "In a way," says the Stranger,96 "they are in a condition of great hostility and opposition to each other in many beings."^ Generalizing the nature of each of these two qualities as understood by most people, he says:

When we admire, as we frequently do in many actions, quickness and energy and acuteness of mind or body or even of voice, we express our praise of them by one word, courage. (306 E: Lamb)

[And] don’t we always say "How quiet!” and "How restrained!" when we are admiring the workings of the mind, and again we speak of actions as slow and gentle, of the voice as smooth and deep, and of every rhythmic motion and of music in general as having appropriate slowness; and we apply to them all the term which signifies, not courage, but decorum? (307 A: Lamb)

He then points out that if these qualities go their separate ways and beyond a certain limit, they will become either violent and brutal or cowardly. Therefore, these two must be made mutually supportive of each other with the help of wisdom, so that they can be true courage and temperance. Warning against the extremities of courage and temperance, he also says:

In the nature of things courage, if propagated through many generations with no admixture of a self-restrained nature, though at first it is strong and flourishing, in the end blossoms forth in utter madness. But the soul, on the other hand, that is too full of modesty and contains no alloy of courage or boldness, after many generations of the same kind becomes too sluggish and finally is utterly crippled. (310 D - E: Lamb)

Therefore, the future guardians and auxiliaries must learn the art of blending of these two virtues in the school, which is supervised by the philosophic rulers who know the true meanings of honor, justice, and goodness.

It is also pointed out in the same dialogue that courage separated from other virtues in a ruler can cause misery and destruction on his own and other states by his constant warring desire and unbridled aggressiveness, because

136 such courage is nothing but wanton brutality. Yet, if it is blended with other virtues, it can produce gentleness, love, and justice.98

In the Republic, Socrates defines courage as "the power of preserving in all conditions." Asked for his meaning, he says:

I am saying that courage means preserving something. Yes, but what? The conviction, inculcated by lawfully established education about the sort of things which may rightly be feared. When I added ’in all circumstances,' I meant preserving it always and never abandoning it whether under the influence of pain or pleasure, of desire or of fear... Such a power of constantly preserving, in accordance with our institutions, the right conviction about the things which ought, or ought not to be feared, is what I call courage. (429 C - D & 430 B: Cornford)

The conviction that must be preserved is, of course, the knowledge of what really is, or is not, to be feared. Therefore, courage is the power that can preserve true knowledge in all circumstances.

The following passages in the Laws describe yet another power, which courage can exercise.

Ath. But how ought we to define courage? Is it to be regarded only as combat against fears and pains, or also against desires and pleasures, and against flatteries; which exercise such a tremendous power, that they make the hearts even of respectable citizens to melt like wax? Mea. I should say the latter. Ath. Now, which is in the truest sense inferior, the man who is overcome by pleasure or by pain? Cle. I should say the man who is overcome by pleasure; for all men deem him to be inferior in a more disgraceful sense, than the other who is overcome by pain. Ath. But surely the lawgivers of Crete and Lacedaemon have not legislated for a courage which is lame of one leg, able only to meet attackers which come from the left, but impotent against the insidious flatteries which come from the right? Cle. Able to meet both, I should say. (633 C - 634 A: Jowett)

It is clear that courage, to be true to its name, must not only endure pains, but also resist pleasures of all sorts.

137 Justice

In the HspufrMc, where the virtue of justice {butctiorCv^) is most extensively discussed, it is defined variously by Socrates' interlocutors.

Justice is first defined by one as "not to cheat any man even unintentionally or play him false, nor remaining in debt to a god for some sacrifice or to a man for money."99 It is also defined as the act of rendering "to each his due," meaning

"to do good to friends and evil to enemies."1™ Still another definition is given by Thrasymachus as "the interest or advantage of the stronger." Asked by

Socrates to elaborate on his statement, he says:

Don’t you know that some cities are governed by tyrants, in others democracy rules, in others aristocracy?... And each form of government enacts the laws with a view to its own advantage, a democracy democratic laws and tyranny autocratic and others likewise, and by so legislating they proclaim that the just for their subjects is that which is for their - the rulers’ - advantage and the man who deviates from this law they chastise as a lawbreaker and a wrongdoer... [TJhe just is the same thing everywhere, the advantage of the stronger. (338 D - 339 A: Shorey)

Although Thrasymachus admits that the stronger sometimes command the weaker subjects to act against their interests by mistake, meaning that the men in power are not always infallible, he is adamant in claiming that justice means doing what is to the interest of the stronger.101 In short, for

Thrasymachus, justice is the exclusive possession of men in power and whatever they do to protect their own interests must be accepted as just. To support his contention, he goes so far as to declare that justice, fairness, and

honesty never pay, but injustice is always more profitable. He says to Socrates:

You must look at the matter, my simple-minded Socrates, in this way: that the just man always comes out at a disadvantage in his relation with the unjust. To begin with, in their business dealings in any joint undertaking of the two you will never find that the just man has the advantage over the unjust at the dissolution of the partnership but that he always has the worst of it. (343 D: Shorey)

138 Socrates disagrees. He confutes Thrasymachus' view on three points first, that the just is superior to the unjust in virtue and wisdom; second, that justice is a source of strength; and third, that it brings happiness. "Justice is " says Socrates, virtue and wisdom and injustice vice and ignorance."102

Having established this, he then asserts that justice is in truth stronger than injustice. He explains:

For factions, Thrasymachus, are the outcome of injustice, and hatreds and internecine conflicts, but justice brings oneness of mind and love... If it is the business of injustice to engender hatred wherever it is found, will it not, when it springs up either among freemen or slaves, cause them to hate and be at strife with one another, and make them incapable of effective action in common?

The justice in the state, then, not only generates oneness that makes it strong, but also brings happiness, benefit, and harmony among citizens.103 To make his last point Socrates asks Thrasymachus whether or not "there is a specific virtue or excellence of everything for which a specific work or function is appointed."104 For example, whether or not the eyes or ears have specific virtue and excellence to perform their functions. Thrasymachus' answer is affirmative. Socrates, then, asks whether or not the soul has a specific virtue or excellence and its peculiar work to perform. The answer is yes. The discussion goes on as follows:

Soc. Will the soul ever accomplish its own work well if deprived of its own virtue, or is this impossible? Thra. It is impossible. Soc. Of necessity, then, a bad soul will govern and manage things badly while the good soul will in all these things do well. Thra. Of necessity. Soc. And did we not agree that the excellence or virtue of the soul is justice and its defect injustice? Thra. Yes, we did. Soc. The just soul and the just man then will live well and the unjust ill? * Thra. So it appears by your reasoning. Soc. But furthermore, he who lives well is blessed and happy, and he who does not the contrary.

139 Thra. Of course. SfiQ. Then the just is happy and the unjust miserable Um So be it. (353 E-354 A: Shorey)

In Socrates' view, justice has two distinct applications; one to the state and the other to man or the soul of man. The state is comprised of a class of rulers, a class of auxiliaries, and a class of artisans, farmers, and the rest of citizenry. In parallel fashion, the soul has three parts: the reasoning, the spirited, and the appetitive part. Given this view, Socrates believes that in both cases, justice is the condition which exists when each class in the state or each part in the soul performs the task to which it is naturally suited.

Accordingly, justice in the state means the three social classes are kept distinct and the members of each class are left to perform their one task or service for which their nature is most adapted for the welfare of the entire state.

Simply put, "justice is,” in Socrates' words "to do one's own business and not be a busybody.’’105 The following quote, one of the many explanations he gives to support his view, shows his way of thinking. He says:

When I fancy one who is by nature an artisan or some kind of money¬ maker tempted and incited by wealth or command of votes or bodily strength or some similar advantage tries to enter into the class of the soldiers or one of the soldiers into the class of counselors and guardians, for which he is not fitted, and these interchange their tools and their honours or when the same man undertakes all these functions at once, then, I take it, you too believe that this kind of substitution and meddlesomeness is the ruin of the state. The interference with one another's business, then, of three existent classes and the substitution of the one for the other is the greatest injury to a state and would most rightly be designated as the thing which chiefly works it harm. Again, let us put it in this way. The proper functioning of the money¬ making class, the helpers and the guardians, each doing its own work in the state, being the reverse of that just described would be justice and would render the city just. (434 B - C: Shorey)

Justice in the individual man exists when the reasoning, the spirited, and the appetitive parts in his soul perform their functions, with the condition that the reasoning part play the dominant role. Socrates says:

140 A man is just in the same way that a state is just. And we have surelv not forgotten that justice in the state meant that each of the three orders in it was doing its own proper work. So we may henceforth bear in mind that each one of us likewise will be a just person, fulfilling his proper function, only if the several parts of our nature fulfill theirs. And it will be the business of reason to rule with wisdom and forethought on behalf of the entire soul; while the spirited element ouqht to act as its subordinate and ally. The two will be brought into accord as we said earlier, by that combination of mental and bodily training which will tune up one string of the instrument and relax the other, nourishing the reasoning part on the study of noble literature and allaying the other's wildness by harmony and rhythm. When both have been thus nurtured and trained to know their own true functions, they must be set in command over the appetites, which form the greater part of each man’s soul and are by nature insatiably covetous. They must keep watch lest this part, by battening on the pleasures that are called bodily, should grow so great and powerful that it will no longer keep to its own work, but will try to enslave the others and usurp a dominion to which it has no right, thus turning the whole of life upside down. (441 C, E - B: Cornford)

When the three parts of the soul are working together in a just person, he would not cheat, steal, be disloyal to his friends and the state, commit adultery, dishonour his parents, or neglect his religious duties.106 Socrates declares that

"justice is the power which produces states or individuals of whom this is true."107 Before concluding the discussion on justice, Socrates makes the

following conclusive recapitulation:

Soc. And so our dream has come true... Our principle that the born shoemaker or carpenter had better stick to his trade turns out to have been an adumbration of justice; and that is why it has helped us. But in reality justice, though evidently analogous to this principle, is not a matter of external behaviour, but of the inward self and of attending to all this is, in the fullest sense, a man's proper concern. The just man does not allow the several elements of his soul to usurp one another's functions, he is indeed one who sets his house in order, by self-mastery and discipline coming to be at peace with himself, and bringing into tune those three parts, like the terms in the proportion of a musical scale, the highest and lowest notes and the mean between them, with all the intermediate intervals. Only when he has linked these parts together in well-tempered harmony and has made himself one man instead of many, will he be ready to go about whatever he may have to do, whether it be making money and satisfying bodily wants, or business transactions, or the affairs of state. In all these fields when he speaks of just and honourable conduct, he will mean the behaviour that helps to produce and to preserve this habit of mind; and by wisdom he will mean the

141 knowledge which presides over such conduct. Any action which tends to break down this habit will be for him unjust; and the notions governina it he will call ignorance and folly. y Gla. That is perfectly true, Socrates. Good. I believe we should not be thought altogether mistaken if we claimed to have discovered the just man and the just state, and wherein their justice consists. Gla. Indeed we should not. Shall we make the claim, then? Gla. Yes, we will

Justice is mentioned and discussed numerous times in the Laws, no less than in the Republic, and is given a high place among the virtues. A few representative passages from the dialogue deserve to be quoted. Athenian

Stranger, the protagonist of the dialogue, says:

For as we acknowledge the world to be full of many goods and also of evils, and of more evils than goods, there is, as we affirm, and immortal conflict going on among us, which requires marvellous watchfulness; and in that conflict the Gods and demigods are our allies, and we are their property. Injustice and insolence and folly are the destruction of us, and justice and temperance and wisdom are our salvation; and the place of these latter is in the life of Gods, although some vestige of them may occasionally be discerned among mankind. (906 A: Jowett)

There are many noble things in human life, but to most of them attach evils which are fated to corrupt and spoil them. Is not justice noble, which has been the civilizer of humanity? How then can the advocater of justice be other than noble? (937 E: Jowett)

In summary

Organized education involving a large number of students with the

clearly defined aim of producing a new class of future rulers began with

Confucius in the East and Socrates in the West. For making education a matter

of fundamental importance in improving the quality of human life and

implementing it with a carefully selected curriculum and methods, they must be

recognized as the earliest pioneers of modern educational theories and

practices.

142 Some courses of study offered by both groups are identical with strikingly

similar rationales, while some other courses are offered only by one group. For

instance, the Confucian courses called Wen ) and the Athenian course

called^ooJ-.icj both include the study of poetry, music, and history. However,

only Wen requires the study of Li (7f^) and only requires the

study of fine arts in painting and sculpture. The purpose of Wen and

is the same, that is, to make their students broadly educated and cultured. The

Athenian group requires gymnastics as a separate course to be given with / juovdTiK^ for their young students, but the Confucian group does not.

When the students reach the age of twenty and are selected to receive

the second stage or higher education, the Athenians require courses in

advanced arithmetic, geometry, astronomy, and harmonics with the singular

purpose of preparing them for the final stage or highest education in dialectics,

if they pass the last selection process when they reach the age of thirty.

Dialectic, a separate course of study offered only by the Athenians, not only

develops the technique of philosophical discussion to grasp the substance of

the knowledge of moral excellence, but explores simultaneously, using the

developing technique, the substance of that knowledge itself. The Confucians

use the dialectical method freely to gasp the same in their normal study of

music, poetry, history, and Li, as it is the only best method, therefore needing no

identification of it by name.

Having declared their educational goal as the making of future rulers of

moral excellence, both groups engage their students heavily in a critical

examination of all virtues of the old and the new; and conclude that "all virtues

are one." According to their investigation, all virtues must be interdependent

and complementary to be genuine. The virtue of 'courage,' for example, in

order to be genuine, also must be wise, just, temperate, humane, sincere,

143 constant, and so on. Moreover, both groups believe that there is a Cosmic

Moral Principle, whether it is called the Way of jen-yi or the Form of the Good, from which all genuine virtues flow. Therefore, all virtues flowing from the one source are one.

The study of //, considered very important by the Confucians, is not only knowing ’good manners’ and proper ways of doing things, but is a power that makes every human behavior and action truly human and moral. To have the knowledge of virtue is essential to be virtuous, but the knowledge of // is equally essential, because an improperly applied virtue can be dehumanizing and immoral. Accordingly, a man may have all the knowledge of justice, love, and courage, but if he does not know //, he cannot be a man of true justice, love, and courage.

The Confucian emphasis on the ceremonial aspect of //, too, must not be overlooked. A ceremony, carefully organized and beautifully performed with special words, music and even dance appropriate to whatever occasion it is celebrating or commemorating, can affect the participants profoundly. Li, as ceremony, is open and public and can make the participants become aware of their common bond of humanity, capable of appreciating together with others common values that can reward them with a sense of community and

happiness.

Li, that also teachers 'good manners' and 'proper conduct' can make all

human institutions, whether of the family or state, ordered and civilized. In their view, the fundamental human institution is the family, and it can be a

harmonious and happy place, if the head of the family performs his role as

proper father/husband, his spouse her role of proper mother/wife, and their children their roles as proper sons/daughters and brothers/sisters. To the

144 Confucians, the family is a microcosm of the State. Therefore, the study of li is vital for the future rulers of the state.

To the Confucians, the family is very important for its effect on the moral education of man. The family is where children's earliest moral training can take place and also provides a place for them to practice what they learn.

According to the Confucians, the virtue of hsiao (^) or honoring one's parents and elders, considered by them as the root of all other virtuous practices, must begin in the family. It is there that children must find their proper places in the family hierarchy, which is inevitable and indispensable for any

institution, and learn to conduct themselves properly to have a happy

relationship with each member of the family for the unity, harmony, and

happiness of the whole.

Socrates/Plato, too, mention the family as the place where children’s

virtue of honoring their parents should begin, but the family does not play an

educational role for those who are selected to be the future rulers or Guardians.

That role belongs to the state. Moreover, the future rulers and Guardians of

their ideal state are not to have their own families and the children, produced by

the union between the rulers or Guardians and the women who are selected

and matched by the state for procreation, are the property of the state. The

children so produced are, therefore, without their own families to practice the

virtue of filial piety. Socrates/Plato, too, considered the root of honoring all

honorable things and other virtues.

Before concluding this summary, a brief comment on the censorship

imposed so severely by the Athenians on curriculum materials needs to be

made. The Confucians are as aware of the existence of bad materials for the

study of poetry, music, and history as the Athenians are, but they do not attempt

to expurgate them as zealously as the Athenians do. The Confucians display

145 greater confidence in the quality of their curriculum materials than the

Athenians. They even seem to feel the necessity of exposing students to bad materials to help them develop their own ability to see, compare, and choose the best. Socrates/Plato insist that only good materials must be used in all courses.

146 CHAPTER VI

KOHLBERG AND THE ANCIENTS

This chapter will examine today's best known, albeit highly controversial, moral education theory of Lawrence Kohlberg to compare it with the theories forwarded by the classical thinkers of Greece and China and see what progress has been made in the field of moral education. More specifically, Kohlberg's philosophical, psychological, and educational theories will be examined to see, first, in what respects he is a modern heir of Socrates/Plato and second, in what other respects he is an explorer of new territories which his Athenian mentors had not covered.

Philosophically, Kohlberg draws heavily both from Socrates/Plato and

John Dewey. This he admits in one of his more important papers as follows.

It is surely a paradox that a modern psychologist should claim as his most relevant source not Freud, Skinner, or Piaget but the ancient believer in the ideal form of the good. Yet as I have tried to trace the stages of development of morality and to use these stages as the basis of a moral education program, I have realized more and more that its implication was the reassertion of the Socratic faith in the power of the rational good.1

Accordingly, Kohlberg's view of the nature of virtue does not differ at all from the way Socrates/Plato viewed it and Kohlberg summarizes the Athenians' view in the following way.

First, virtue is ultimately one, not many, and it is always the same ideal form regardless of climate or culture. Second, the name of this ideal form is justice. Third, not only is the good one, but virtue is knowledge of the good. He who knows the good chooses the good.

147 Eaurth, the kind of knowledge of the good that is virtue is philosophical knowledge or intuition of the ideal form of the qood not correct opinion or acceptance of conventional beliefs. Eifih, the good can then be taught, but its teachers must in a certain sense be philosopher-kings. the reason the good can be taught is because we know it all along dimly or at a low level and its teaching is more a calling out than an instruction. y Seventh, the reason we think the good cannot be taught is because the same good is known differently at different levels and direct instruction cannot take place across levels. .Eighth, then the teaching of virtue is the asking of questions and the pointing of the way, not the giving of answers. Moral education is the leading of people upward, not the putting into the mind of knowledqe that was not there before.2

Kohlberg agrees with Socrates/Plato on all points summarized above except on one aspect of the definition of justice. He understands justice as equality indicating his indebtedness to Dewey, while Socrates/Plato understand it as hierarchy. Defining justice as "a matter of equal and universal human rights,"

Kohlberg says:

Justice is not a rule or a set of rules, it is a moral principle. By a moral principle, I mean a mode of choosing that is universal, a rule of choosing that we want all people to adopt always in all situations... A moral principle is a principle for resolving competing claims: you versus me, you versus a third person. There is only one principled basis for resolving claims: justice or equality. Treat every person's claims impartially regardless of the person. A moral principle is not only a rule of action but a reason for action. As a reason for action, justice is called respect for people.3

In short, Kohlberg's conception of justice is a Bill of Rights that recognizes the equality or the equal rights of individuals.

Having accepted justice as the most important moral principle, which he defines as "equal and universal human rights" that include the child's right to

exercise his own reason to attain moral maturity, the bag of virtues must not be

given to the child. Kohlberg thinks that the bag of virtues approach equates the

teaching of virtue with indoctrination of conventional or social consensus

morality and it will not allow the child to learn values on his own, using his own

148 power of reason to attain moral excellence. Moreover, he thinks that the bag of virtues approach is inevitably relativistic, for each person and each society would have his and its own bag.4

Although Kohlberg draws heavily from Dewey in developing his own philosophical and psychological theories on moral education, he criticizes

Dewey's partial agreement with Aristotle, which produced a bag of virtues. Aristotle stated in his Ethics, that:

Virtue is of two kinds, intellectual and moral. While intellectual virtue owes its birth and growth to teaching, moral virtue comes about as a result of habit. The moral virtues we get by first exercising them; we become just by doing just acts, temperate by doing temperate acts, brave by doing brave acts.5

"Dewey," says Kohlberg, "of course, does not distinguish the intellectual from the moral and objects to lists of virtues and vices in either area. Nevertheless,

Deweyite thinking has lent itself to the Boy Scout approach to moral education, which has dominated American practices in the field."6 In his view, the Boy

Scout approach to moral education is to depend on the bag of virtues and vices and his objections to it are: first, for its demand on obedience, thus denying the child's right to reason out the validity of each virtue in the bag; and second, the so-called virtues in the bag are mere labels from praiseworthy behaviors or habits, which does not help the child develop his own reasoning power to make his own moral decisions when situations demand.

As an inheritor of virtually all the major philosophical, psychological, and educational ideas of Socrates/Plato and Dewey, Kohlberg criticizes and rejects any moral education strategy or approach that accepts indoctrination and moral relativism and any other extreme and one-sided ideology. He rejects the cultural transmission strategy, because it "maintains that values are determined by each particular society. Teaching is the process of imparting such values to

149 children, who are viewed as passive learners,"7 meaning it is value relative and indoctrinative. The romantic ideology of education is unacceptable to him, because it "sees the educational process as one that should free the individual for natural inner-directed growth based on the psychological theory of

maturationism, which conceptualizes the individual as possessing in an

embryonic form all the important elements necessary for growth,"8 therefore, it is too self-centered. The values clarification approach, too, is unsatisfactory,

because it recognizes that values are relative and tolerates the divergences of

individual value hierarchies, although its basic premises are commendable.9

Kohlberg calls his own strategy the cognitive-developmental approach,

acknowledging the fact that it is built upon the stages theory of cognitive-

developmental psychology of Jean Piaget and the educational views of Dewey.

"Developmental," says Kohlberg, "because it is a psychology of stages,

cognitive because the stages involve forms of thinking. This psychology is

interactional: it holds that stages do not mature biologically but develop through

interaction between the child’s structuring capacities and the intellectual and

social stimulation of the environment.”10

According to Kohlberg, the criterion to judge a person's moral

development is the knowledge of justice and the level of his moral maturity as

measured by the level of his understanding of the principles of justice. His

typology of moral development contains three levels of moral reasoning and

each level has two stages.

I. Preconventional 1 The Punishment & Obedience Orientation 2 The Instrumental Relativist Orientation 3 The Interpersonal Concordance or II. Conventional 'Good Boy/Nice Girl' Orientation 4 The 'Law and Order' Orientation

5 The Social Contract Orientation

150 III. Post-conventional 6 The Universal Ethical Principle Orientation

Kohlberg claims that these stages have the following characteristics. They are structured wholes that are universal; follow an invariant, irreversible, and increasingly integrative sequence; and the last stage of the progression is the most adequate. This means all movement is forward in sequence and does not skip stages. No one in Stage 2, for example, has gone through Stage 3, but the

Stage 3 person has gone through Stage 2.11

The six stages are defined and validated, according to Kohlberg, after his longitudinal and cross-cultural studies over a long period of time. One study involved fifty Chicago-area boys of the middle- and working-class. Initially asking them to respond to a series of hypothetical moral dilemmas at ages ten through sixteen, then repeating the process at three-year intervals thereafter for twenty years. Another longitudinal study conducted in Turkey involved a small number of village and city boys of the same age, asking them to respond to another set of moral dilemmas. Then, a variety of other cross-cultural studies in

Canada, Britain, Israel, Yucatan, Honduras, and India.12

To help a person move forward or become morally mature, Kohlberg says that the person's reasoning faculty must be stimulated by a number of things. He uses most heavily hypothetical moral dilemmas to stimulate the person's moral thinking for the following reasons. He is convinced that:

1. Moral judgment, while only one factor in moral behavior, is the single most important or influential factor yet discovered in moral behavior. 2. While other factors influence moral behavior, moral judgment is the only distinctively 'moral' factor in moral behavior. 3. Moral judgment change is long-range or irreversible; a higher stage is never lost. Moral behavior as such is largely situational and reversible or 'losable' in new situations.13

151 Moral discussion, however, constitutes only one portion of the conditions

stimulating moral growth. For school children, moral discussion can be

incorporated into various academic courses, such as social studies to stimulate their thinking.14 According to Kohlberg the moral atmosphere of the home, the

school, and society itself, too, is very important in stimulating their moral thinking, for the role-taking opportunities it provides and also the justice

structure each of the perceived rules or principles for distributing rewards,

punishments, responsibilities and privileges among its members. He reports that his studies suggest that a higher level of institutional justice is a condition

for individual development of a higher sense of justice.15

Accepting another Socratic conviction which implies that "the knowledge

of the good is always within but needs to be drawn out like geometric

knowledge in Meno's slave,"16 Kohlberg says:

In the cognitive-developmental view, morality is a natural product of a universal human tendency toward empathy or role-taking, toward putting oneself in the shoes of other conscious beings. It is also a product of a universal human concern for justice, for reciprocity or equality in the relation of one person to another.17

The first step in teaching virtue, then, is the Socratic step of creating dissatisfaction in students about their knowledge of the good. This we do experimentally by exposing the students to moral conflict situations for which their principles have no ready solution. Second, we expose them to disagreement and argument about these situations with their peers. Our Platonic view holds that if we inspire cognitive conflict in students and point the way to the next step up the divided line, they will tend to see things previously invisible.18

In other words, the task of moral education is "to draw the child's perceptions of

justice from the shadows of the cave step by step toward the light of justice as

an ideal form. And like Meno's slave, children are initially quite confident of

their moral knowledge, of the rationality and efficacy of their moral principles.

The notion that children feel ignorant and are eager to absorb the wisdom of

152 adult authority in the moral domain is one that teacher or parent will know is nonsense.”19

Kohlberg asserts that his developmental approach is different from indoctrinative approaches "because it tries to move student’s thinking in a direction that is natural for the student rather than moving the student in the direction of accepting the teacher's moral assumptions. It avoids preaching and didacticism linked to the teacher’s authority.”29 Elaborating this point further, he says:

Because there are culturally universal stages or sequences of moral development, stimulation of a child's development to the next step in a natural direction is equivalent to a long-range goal of teaching ethical principles. Because the development of these principles is natural, they are not imposed on the children - they choose principles themselves... According to the cognitive developmental'^ view, there is an important analogy between scientific and ethical patterns of judgment or problem solving, and there are overlapping rationales for intellectual and ethical education. In exposing the child to opportunities for reflective scientific inquiry, teachers are guided by the principle of scientific method that the teachers themselves accept as the basis of rational reflection. Reference to such principles is nonindoctrinative if these principles are not presented as formulas to be learned ready-made or as rote patterns grounded in authority. Rather, they are part of a process of reflection by students and teachers.21

The goal of Kohlberg's approach to moral education, then, is to stimulate a person's natural moral tendency to develop step by step through the stages to its highest attainable maturity.

Kohlberg says that the majority of adults of American society are at conventional Stages 3 and 4, and only about ten percent of the adult population

are at Stages 5 and 6.22 Kohlberg names Socrates, Lincoln, Thoreau, and

Martin Luther King, individuals who "tend to speak without confusion of tongues,

as it were,’’23 among those very few Americans whom he considers to have

153 attained Stage 6 in moral development. His reasons for including, for example, Martin Luther King are as follows.

Because morally mature people are governed by the principle of justice rather than by a set of rules, there are not many moral virtues but one. Let me restate the argument in Plato's terms. Plato’s argument is that what makes a virtuous action virtuous is that it is guided by knowledge of the good. A courageous action based on ignorance of danger is not courageous; a just act based on ignorance of justice is not just; and so on. If virtuous action is action based on knowledge of the good, then virtue is one, because knowledge of the good is one. I have already claimed that knowledge of the good is one because the qood is justice. ...At the highest stage [of moral development], however, is regard for law a regard for universal moral law and regard for rights a regard for universal human rights. At this point, both regard for law and regard for human rights are grounded on a clear criterion of justice that was present in confused and obscure form at earlier stages.24

King's acts of civil disobedience were, then, clearly dictated by his autonomous

moral judgment based on the principles of justice.

According to Kohlberg, "justice is not a character trait in the usual sense...

One cannot make up behavior tests that would indicate that Martin Luther King

and Socrates were high on a trait of justice. The reason for this is that justice is

not a concrete rule of action such as that underlying virtues like honesty.25 He

elaborates this point as follows:

To be honest means "Don't cheat, don't steal, don't lie." But justice is not a rule or a set of rules, it is a moral principle. By a moral principle, I mean a mode of choosing that is universal, a rule of choosing that we want all people to adopt always in all situations. We know it is all right to be dishonest and steal to save a life because it is just, because one person's right to life comes before another person's right to property. We know it is sometimes right to kill, because it is sometimes just. The Germans who tried to kill Hitler were doing right because respect for the equal values of lives demands that we kill someone who is murdering others, in order to save lives. There are exceptions to rules, then, but no exception to principles.26

154 To further prove that Martin Luther King’s moral reasoning was at Stage

6, Kohlberg quotes King's own words from his ’Letter from a Birmingham Jail.' King wrote:

There is a type of constructive nonviolent tension which is necessary for growth. Just as Socrates felt it was necessary to create a tension in the mind so that individuals could rise from the bondage of half-truths so must we see the need for nonviolent gadflies to create the kind of tension in society that will help men rise from the dark depths of prejudice and racism. One may well ask, "How can you advocate breaking some laws and obeying others?" The answer lies in the fact that there are two types of laws, just and unjust. One has not only a legal but a moral responsibility to disobey unjust laws. An unjust law is a human law that is not rooted in eternal law and natural law. Any law that uplifts human personality is just, any law that degrades human personality is unjust. An unjust law is a code that a numerical or power majority group compels a minority group to obey but does not make binding on itself. This is difference made legal. I do not advocate evading or defying the law, as would the rabid segregationist. That would lead to anarchy. One who breaks an unjust law must do so openly, lovingly, and with a willingness to accept the penalty. An individual who breaks a law that conscience tells him is unjust, and willingly accepts the penalty of imprisonment in order to arouse the conscience of the community over its injustice, is in reality expressing the highest respect for law.27

Commenting on King's way of moral reasoning, Kohlberg says: "King makes it clear that moral disobedience of the law must spring from the same root as moral obedience to law, out of respect for justice."28

By necessity, the above description of Kohlberg's cognitive developmental theory of moral education is brief, but a fuller discussion will follow as it is compared with the theories of classical thinkers of China and

Greece.

First, on human nature, Kohlberg does not analyze human nature as did the classical thinkers, who understood it as being composed of distinctly different parts or elements, such as, the appetitive, the reasoning, or the spirited.

He does not raise objection to their understanding of it, but seems to agree with

155 them on one important point, namely, the reasoning part of man’s nature is what makes him different from other creatures. Kohlberg believes like the classical thinkers that man’s desire to be moral is his natural tendency or inclination and with the help of education, man can develop his most important gift, that is, his

reasoning power, to acquire the knowledge of the absolute and universal moral value or justice in Kohlberg's philosophy, and live with others morally according to the dictates of the knowledge. Kohlberg says:

In the cognitive-development view, morality is a natural product of a universal human tendency toward empathy or role-taking, toward putting oneself in the shoes of other conscious beings. It is also a product of a universal human concern for justice, for reciprocity or equality in the relation of one person to another.29

In the view of the classical thinkers, however, although all human beings

come with a mind that can reason, only those who are additionally endowed

with special intellectual and emotional qualities necessary to explore the

knowledge of moral excellence or the highest moral values should receive

moral education to be the future rulers and teachers. Therefore, the classical

moral education was elitist, while Kohlberg’s is not. Although his research

findings indicate that only about ten percent of the adult population reaches the

fifth or the sixth stage of moral maturity, Kohlberg believes that moral education

should be given to all in school, either as an independent course or as part of

other courses.

In and for a democratic nation like ours, Kohlberg's call for a universal

moral education is understandable. Here we all claim our equal rights and

know that our rights are protected by the Constitution. But isn't it also true that

there must be leaders and the led in every social group and institution? And

we, in fact, demand that the leaders should be more moral that the rest. The

156 classical thinkers had no illusions about this and made it their mission to see a

class of moral rulers come through their education.

Second, as for the aim of moral education, Kohlberg's is not and cannot

be essentially different from the classical thinkers’, because philosophically, he

aligns with Socrates and Plato. Like the classical thinkers of both groups,

Kohlberg asserts that there is an objective moral value, which is absolute and

universal, and humans can know it. As the absolute and universal moral value

belongs to the intelligible realm, one can acquire the knowledge of it only with

the use of his reason. Therefore, the aim of his moral education, too, is to

"stimulate" the student’s innate power of reason in such as way that he will

develop his reasoning power on his own volition, supported by his natural

human tendency for justice, from one stage to the next all the way to the sixth

stage, which is of the highest moral maturity, where moral excellence of justice

becomes his own value to guide his moral judgment and behavior.

Although the classical thinkers did not produce an elaborate stages

theory of moral development like Kohlberg's, they all understood that, like

everything else that grows in the world, human moral reasoning, too, grows

gradually from one stage to the next if it is correctly guided. With this

understanding, Plato was particularly careful in his educational planning to

make his student's moral development attain its highest level of maturity by

offering different courses of study, which were considered appropriate to the

student's intellectual, emotional, and physical maturity and age at each of the

evolving stages of his growth, with one ultimate purpose of making his

reasoning capacity thoroughly prepared to obtain the knowledge of moral

excellence when he entered his final stage of study in dialectics.

The classical Confucian thinkers did not produce a stages theory of

moral development either. But the following quotation from the Analects is

157 enough allow us to assume that they, too, knew that man’s moral maturity developed gradually, from one stage to the next. Confucius said, reminiscing on his own progress:

At fifteen, I had my mind bent on learning. At thirty, I stood firm. At forty I had no doubts. At fifty, I knew the decrees of Heaven. At sixty my ear was an obedient organ for the reception of truth. At seventy, I could follow what my heart desired, without transgressing what was riqht (II 4- Legge)

Neither Confucius nor the Greek thinkers, however, claimed, as Kohlberg does,

that developmental stages are structured wholes that are universal, follow an

invariant, irreversible, and increasingly integrative sequence, and that the last

stage is also the most adequate morally. Perhaps such claims, some of them

quite indefensible, never entered their minds.30

Like the aim of moral education of the classical thinkers, Kohlberg’s aim

is also twofold. One part of the aim is to help the student’s reasoning power to

develop to its maximum to know what is and is not justice and the other part is to

help him become a moral man who would fulfil his obligation to his society

according to the principles of justice. By citing Socrates, Lincoln, and Martin

Luther King, Jr. among a few others whom he designates as the achievers of

the highest moral maturity or as morally "principled" people, Kohlberg, too,

wants his students to become socially conscious men and women who would

do morally positive things in an immoral world.

However, by declaring the aim of his cognitive-developmental approach

to be different from the aims of other approaches to moral education, Kohlberg

sets himself apart from other theorists and educators of moral education. Like

the classical thinkers, especially the Athenians, Kohlberg is intolerant towards

moral indoctrination and moral relativism. He criticizes almost all conventional

approaches as indoctrinative because they aim to form moral characters with

158 "the bag of virtues," and rejects the popular modern program known as "values clarification" as relativistic. To claim his own approach that emphasizes stimulation of movement to the next stage of reasoning as not indoctrinate, he gives the following reasons among others. First, "Change is in the way of reasoning rather than in the particular beliefs involved," and second, "the teacher's own opinion is neither stressed nor invoked as authoritative. It enters in only as one of many opinions, hopefully one of those at the next higher stage."31 His is not relativistic, because "the moral development approach restricts value education to that which is moral or, more specifically, to justice."32 "Moral psychology describes what moral development is as studied empirically," says Kohlberg.33 Because he is a moral psychologist, the aim of his approach, too, is that of a scientist-researcher, whose chief concern is to learn more about the pattern of the maturing process of his students' moral reasoning than the content of moral value itself, towards which his students' reasoning ought to be growing and developing. In Dennis Krebs' words, the aim of Kohlberg's approach is "to decipher the logic of moral decisions made by people at different stages of cognitive and social maturity. He is not concerned with what people believe is right or wrong (the content of moral thought, or moral attitude); he is concerned with the rules they use to arrive at conclusions about what is right or wrong (the structure of thought)."34 James Rest explains it in the following way:

Kohlberg has contended that moral education should not be aimed at teaching some specific set of morals but should be concerned with developing the organizational structures by which one analyzes, interprets and makes decisions about social problems. ...The Cognitive developmental approach aims not at producing mere conformity with the state's, teacher's, or the school's values, but at developing capabilities in decision making and problem solving.35

159 By setting forth the development of capabilities in analyzing, interpreting, and decision-making to solve moral dilemmas as his prime aim of moral education, Kohlberg makes the means to attain the end more important than the end itself. His chief concern and interest appears to be with the pattern or the structure of reasoning more than the content of value, or the end of reasoning.

On this, both the Confucians and the Athenians differ from Kohlberg. Although they also believed that by reasoning one could learn what moral excellence is, they were not interested in studying how their students' moral reasoning developed, but in the object of reasoning, the universal moral value or excellence itself. This is because they considered the aim of moral education to be to help the student acquire the knowledge of moral excellence, which alone would make him live and act morally. They didn’t think everyone acquired the moral knowledge in the way Kohlberg's stage theory of development describes.

According to them, some were born with the knowledge and others acquired it in different ways.

Another difference is in the teacher-student relations. By emphasizing the stage development of moral reasoning, the Kohlbergian teacher distances himself from his student. He is a morally neutral interrogator and judge of his student's progress in moral reasoning. The classical thinkers as teachers were fellow-seekers after moral excellence and their relations with their students were intimate and personal, freely and openly questioning and answering, and sharing their ignorance and knowledge.

Third, regarding the methods: Kohlberg accepts the dialectical methods of the classical thinkers. The main objective of this method is to help the student acquire the knowledge of moral excellence all on his own. The core of their theory is the existence of a reasoning power in every human being that can develop when stimulated in the direction of an increasingly more

160 comprehensive and satisfactory understanding of the principles of the universal value. The dialectical method is the one that most successfully stimulates the

student's reasoning closer to the knowledge of that value.

On the use of the method, Kohlberg differs from the classical thinkers.

While Kohlberg recommends the method for children and adults alike, even

though he admits that even some high school students are found not ready to

carry on a truly productive dialogue on moral questions, the classical thinkers

recommended it only for those who were ready for philosophical dialogues.

According to Kohlberg, the application of the method requires the trained

teacher or discussion leader. The teacher's task is to stimulate the student's

thinking with questions and suggestions without disclosing his own moral

views, so that the student will make his own reasoned progression

independently to the next higher stage of moral maturity. In James Rest's

words, "Since the teacher is no longer primarily an answer-giver but a process-

facilitator, the chief activity of these value education programs then is the

student's search rather than the teacher’s answers."36 Kohlberg recommends

that the teacher must be at least one stage above the student in moral maturity

to be able to lead discussion, so that he can provide models of thinking which

are one stage above the student's current level of thinking.37 But, isn’t it

possible that the teacher's own stage of reasoning can be at the stage lower

than the student’s, if we recall Kohlberg’s own finding that only ten percent of

the population reaches the highest or "principled" Stage 5 or 6? And also, how

does the teacher accomplish his task of stimulating the student’s reasoning

without somehow convincing the student that his current level of reasoning is

not morally mature enough, and according to what or whose criterion? On the

matters of teacher's qualifications and functions as discussion leader, Kohlberg

is unconvincing.

161 The qualifications set by the classical thinkers of their teachers were very high. Ideally, only those who have the knowledge of the highest moral excellence should be the teachers, chun-tzu and the philosopher kings. In the absence of those, the thinkers themselves became teachers and by implication they would have approved as teachers of moral education those who (1) believed in the existence of universal moral value; (2) knew that the acquisition and practice of that value by the future leaders alone would make the world moral; and (3) were totally devoted to the search for that value for the happiness it would give them and the world. They were not process-facilitators or graders of their students’ moral maturity while leading discussions, but teachers who, humbly acknowledging their ignorance of the true and complete knowledge of the highest and universal moral value, wanted to seek it together with their students who would be leaders of the future.

Fourth, on curriculum: The only education the classical thinkers felt important was moral education for the future rulers, for the happiness of the

people within the state depended totally on its rulers' moral excellence. In constructing their curriculum, therefore, they selected courses of study they

considered to be essential to the wholesome growth of their students' whole

being. Having analyzed human nature encased in the body as composed of

reasoning, spirited, appetitive, and feeling elements, their curriculum was

designed to cultivate them all and the body also in a balanced way. Although

the development of a human mind that reasons was the most important,

because it alone distinguishes man from all other creatures, and it alone could

acquire the knowledge of moral excellence, An ideal man of moral excellence

was not simply a possessor of the knowledge, but a man whose other human

elements also were cultivated purposefully and were able to render concerted

support when his knowledge had to be put into practice.

162 The Confucians put poetry, history, music, rituals, and ethics in their formal curriculum. Aware of the complexities of human problems in the real world, they felt it was of absolute importance to expose their future rulers as liberally as possible to the courses which recorded and reflected the past and present human experience for critical study and reexamination. The Athenians, too, included many courses in their curriculum, such as music, gymnastics, mathematical sciences, and dialectics, but were not as liberal as the Confucians in that they censored certain forms of art and historical literature as unacceptable. The students were required to study these courses in depth, some for a few years while others for a longer period of time, depending on the ages of their students, all for a common objective of producing men and women with the knowledge of moral excellence and the power to apply it in real life.

Compared with the curriculum offered by the classical thinkers,

Kohlberg's program offers virtually none. If his "discussion of moral dilemmas" can be called a course, it has been used by him and his experimenters as an independent discipline or as part of other academic courses, such as English or history in various schools. It appears primarily in the form of research projects to gather scientific data to formulate a new academic discipline called cognitive developmental psychology. Such subjects as music, gymnastics, or mathematical science, which demand disciplined work habits to attain their projected objects, are not included in his curriculum.

The nature of his moral dilemmas themselves, are limited in scope. All his hypothetical dilemmas are designed to stimulate the student's moral

reasoning to reach the highest stage of moral maturity, where the knowledge of justice will guide his judgment and action. But, is the knowledge of justice alone enough to solve the immensely complex human problems his students will encounter in the real world? Granted that Kohlberg agrees with the

163 classical thinkers that "all virtues are ultimately one," therefore, justice does include other moral values and qualities, such as love, courage, moderation, human-heartedness, and so on. Nevertheless, his hypothetical dilemmas are not inductive to the discussion of these other values and qualities. Kohlberg’s exposition of justice, however, is brilliant. Neither the Athenians nor the

Confucians could have done any better, especially when he defends its position of primacy above all other values, in complete agreement with Plato.

Plato's argument is that what makes a virtuous action virtuous is that it is guided by knowledge of the good. A courageous action based on ignorance of dangers is not courageous; a just act based on ignorance of justice is not just; and so on. If virtuous action is action based on knowledge of the good, then virtue is one. Because knowledge of the good is one. I have already claimed that knowledge of the good is one because the good is justice.38

But, Kohlberg neither proposes in his curriculum a course that is designed to involve students in the discussion of what "just" love, "just" courage, "just" moderation, and so on, are, nor does he attempt to elucidate them himself.

Having rejected the "bag of virtues," which have been used by conventional agents of moral education as indoctrinative, and therefore, harmful to children's moral reasoning and natural development, Kohlberg's program is short of virtues to study, especially for children. In spite of Kohlberg's fear of indoctrination, such simple virtues as honesty, kindness, respect for other's rights, and so on, can and must be explained to them even before their reasoning capacities are developed enough to explore independently and understand the concept of justice.

Unlike Kohlberg, the classical thinkers were deeply interested in discussing openly and freely, all values big or small, old or new, which drew their attention in order to acquire the true knowledge of universal moral

excellence.

164 Kohlberg’s three most frequently cited moral heroes are Socrates,

Mahatma Gandhi, and Martin Luther King. One wonders whether or not these principled" men of morality did not begin their development of moral reasoning with the "bag of virtues," which has been successfully used universally for centuries in the family, the church or temple, the schools, and other civic organizations. Moreover, one can also question whether or not these men matured morally by developing their reason alone. Were they not men of universal human love and forgiveness more than justice? Were they not men who understood a certain higher moral law or principle than the principle of justice? Were they not religious besides being rational? Did their religions or religious experiences have any influence on their moral development?

Kohlberg discusses all these questions without altering his basic approach to moral education that capitalizes the orderly development through stages of moral reasoning stimulated by discussions of moral dilemmas, although he acknowledges the close relationship between religious thinking and moral reasoning, and what the power of religious faith can do to a person’s moral judgment and action.

Citing Socrates and Martin Luther King, "two great moral educators who willingly sacrificed their lives to their mission as educators for justice," Kohlberg states:

Socrates, like Martin Luther King, was a profoundly religious man who held a natural law theory of the relations between morality and religion. Indeed, it is doubtful that either King or Socrates would have calmly faced his own death, or sacrificed his life for principles of justice if his principles did not have some religious support. Their willingness to die for moral principles was partly based on their faith in moral principles as an expression of human reason and partly on their faith in justice, which had religious support. This support was not the support offered by divine command theory, which equates "higher law" with God's commandments. Rather, the support comes from seeing principles of justice as not only a social contract to resolve conflicts in a civil society

165 but as the reflection of an order inherent in both human nature and in the natural or cosmic order.39

I wonder why Kohlberg does not say, like the classical thinkers would have, that these men of moral excellence and action did what they did in obedience to God's, cosmic, or Heaven's command.

Kohlberg notes that "there are universal religious issues as problems that all people attempt to answer. However, these issues are limiting issues that entail some reflection on life in relation to the infinite, unlimited, or eternal. With regard to morality, the fundamental issue that religious thinking may address is

'Why be moral? Why be just in a universe that is not manifestly just?'"40 He admits that his moral stages alone cannot provide a sufficient answer to the question, "Why be moral?" As early as in 1973, Kohlberg says, he suggested a need for a new stage he would call "Stage 7" or a religiously oriented stage of love or agape to answer the question "Why be moral?"

In Kohlberg's view, "religion is a conscious response to, and an expression of, the quest for an ultimate meaning for moral judging and acting.

As such, the main function of religion is not to supply moral prescriptions but to support moral judgment and action" by providing a transcendent or infinite ground for purposeful and rational activities. In order to perform this function, one's religious thinking must comprehend Stage 6's moral conception of justice first to go beyond it. The dominant value of "Stage 7" in his mind is agape or responsible love or compassion which is first, "nonexclusive and can be extended to all including one's enemies; second, it is gracious and is extended without regard for merit."41 Kohlberg says that a man's decision to live agape and to love even his enemies comes with or as a result of religious experiences of union with deity, whose central concern is love and justice. Therefore, the

166 experience of union or oneness with deity gives man the reason to live a moral life and act morally.42

Kohlberg talks about Spinoza, who, according to him, reached "Stage 7" with his experience of the union of the mind with the whole of nature," which enabled him to see "nature as an organized system of natural laws and to see every part of nature, including oneself, as parts of that whole." Kohlberg further explains:

This act of insight is, however, not purely cognitive. One cannot see the whole or the infinite ground of being unless one loves it and aspires to love it. Such love, Spinoza tells us, arises first out of despair about more limited, finite, and perishable loves. Knowing and loving God or Nature as the ground of a system of laws knowable by reason is a support to our acceptance of human rational moral laws of justice, which are part of the whole. Furthermore, our love of the whole or the ultimate supports us through experiences of suffering, injustice, and death. ...Central to his view is the idea of the cosmos as evolving to higher levels of consciousness and organization. The principle or end of this evolution is love.43

According to Kohlberg, Martin Luther King is one who belongs to "Stage 7" of agape, because he went beyond the highest moral stage of justice by breaking

unjust human laws out of his love of fellow human beings. It was his religion that made him see the eternal and true justice of God, who is love, after his

moral reasoning acquired the knowledge of justice in Stage 6, and enabled him to resolve even to die for that knowledge as his loving service to God and his

fellow human beings.

Kohlberg also refers to two other figures who achieved the highest moral

development through their religion or religious experiences. The first one is

Marcus Aurelius, the Roman emperor, "by nature a philosopher who hated war

and killing," who found himself surrounded by those who had no understanding

of his principles, was betrayed by those who were closest to him, and yet, found

167 his way not only to forgive but also to love his detractors and betrayers. Kohlberg explains:

The content of faith of Marcus Aurelius starts with the belief that the universe is lawful, knowable, and evolving. In referring to the ultimate lawful, rational, and evolving principle of the universe, Marcus Aurelius does not attempt to separate God from nature. Sometimes he calls the principle God, sometimes nature. From this belief, he derives a natural law view of morality that gives him the strength to act in terms of universal principles of justice in an unjust world. It also gives him the peace that comes from sensing oneself as a finite part of an infinite whole.44

Kohlberg quotes from the Meditations, which reveal what Marcus

Aurelius has to say regarding the place of the individual person in the cosmos.

Mortal life cannot offer you anything better than justice and truth; that is, peace of mind in the conformity of your actions to the laws of reason. Your destiny you cannot control. Even the vagaries of chance have their place in nature's scheme. You yourself are part of that universe. Remember always what the world-nature is and what your own nature is and that your nature is such a small fraction of so vast a whole. Then you will recognize that no man can hinder you from conforming each word and deed to that nature of which you are a part.45

Kohlberg concludes:

...the cosmic vision has a larger influx of union, love, joy, and grace as well as moral force. Marcus Aurelius, however, in stating the cosmic perspective in its starkest, simplest form, we think succeeds in illuminating how, in any culture, a person without special gifts or inner light, but with the courage and thoughtfulness to think through the human condition, can achieve moral and spiritual maturity 46

The other person is Andrea Simpson, an American mental hospital and social worker, whose religious experience elevated her life to "Stage 7" of agape beyond Stage 6 of justice. According to Kohlberg, Andrea Simpson, who was deeply despaired about the meaning of life, due to her mother's death, her brother's psychosis, and her own failure to form a stable, intimate relationship with a man, had religious experiences through Indian Vedantic meditation which made her aware of the existence of "it doesn't matter what you call it - 'God' or 'Jesus’ or 'Cosmic flow' or 'reality' or 'love' or 'the power greater

168 greater than ourselves.”’47 Kohlberg quotes Simpson’s own words elaborating the experience.

We start by seeking a power that is greater than ourselves. I don’t think anyone can fail to recognize that there is a power beyond themselves when they look out at the scene of their own neighborhood, to say nothing of the cosmos. I don't think it matters a bit what you call this power, but it is within every mind, and experience and makes one aware of this oneness, not only of all people but all of life.48

This awareness or oneness with the power that is greater than ourselves moves her out of despair, makes her accept life's mystery, which defies human comprehension, and starts her awakened life of devotion and caring not only for her brother, "’who was a pure, inless,but also other patients. Simpson describes her coming out of despair as follows.

I came out of it life this: human life is but a brief moment in eternity. I studied astronomy, and you get a broadened vista if you study astronomy, it opens out to incredible degrees. I've also studied anthropology, and you get some idea of the development of the human being on the planet Earth. If a human being’s life is his moment in eternity, [my brother] William's life may be the cocoon stage, to use a figure of speech, in his evolving into a spiritual butterfly. We think of life and death as a pair of opposites - you make your entrance and you make your exit from this material place - and that's death. But life is something contained in the hand of life.49

Kohlberg concludes as follows:

The case of Andrea Simpson illustrates "mystical" experience of identification with the eternal, or with the whole of what she says can be called God or reality. She exemplifies the striving for a cosmic or infinite perspective to answer the problems and questions raised but left unsolved by principled (Stage 5 or 6) morality itself, the problem of undeserved injustice and suffering. In these ways, Andrea Simpson is an example of "Stage 7" ...as is Marcus Aurelius... First, for Andrea Simpson religious thinking and experience not only support a moral orientation but inform it, unite with it, or give it new direction. Second, the moral principle to which this thinking and experience leads is agape, something differing from, or more than, our Stage 6 principles of justice.50

Should principles of agape, then, replace principles of justice of Stage 6,

because the rational principles of justice can neither answer the question Why

169 be moral?" nor motivate their knowers to go beyond them to love fellow human beings equally and unconditionally? Or should there be "Stage 7," "a metaphoric post-conventional stage of religious orientation" attained after the achievement of principled morality? At this point, Kohlberg does not seem to have the answer. The following questions prove his ambiguity on this issue. He says:

Although an ethic of agape goes beyond justice to supererogation, it still requires principles of fairness to resolve justice dilemmas. Furthermore, our Stage 6 principles of reversible fairness are the only principles on which the ethic of agape could rest. Agape, then, is not a principle competing with the principle of fairness.51

Rather than replacing principles of justice, agape goes beyond them in the sense of defining or informing acts of supererogation (acts beyond duty or beyond justice), acts that cannot be generally demanded or required of all people, acts that freely give up claims the actor may in justice demand.52

Agape, unlike justice, arises out of a religious or metaphysical notion of the ideal unity of people with each other and with God or Nature. This religious perspective is then the basis for a mode of action in which the interests of the self and the other are no longer seen as antagonistic but as being in profound harmony.53

Then, he says:

In our view, there are problems, experiences, and thinking that are centrally religious and metaphysical, although the problems depend in part on moral structures for their formulation. This view we are able to most clearly elaborate in terms of the experience and judgments of people at what we think to be "Stage 7," the highest stage of religious judgment. The center of the highest stage is experiences that are most distinctively religious experiences of union with deity, whether pantheistic or theistic.54

In our view, then, a psychological theory of religious stages, particularly a highest stage, rests on a philosophic theory, a set of metaphysical and religious assumptions consistent with, but not reducible to, rational science and morality... In the case of morality, we claim that there is a single definable structure defining a sixth or highest stage and that this structure can be interpreted and justified... In the case of "Stage 7," a highest level of ethical and religious thinking, the structure is much less unitary and undefinable.

170 Correspondingly, speculative theories... arising from and justifying this structure are more diverse and less rigorous than moral theories These theories, however, derive from a qualitatively new insiqht and perspective we call "Stage 7." The speculative philosophies that formulate this insight are not meaningless metaphysics, then, as positivism holds, but constructions essential for understanding human development.55

Kohlberg discusses extensively what religious experience can do to a man's moral development and suggests strongly the possibility of a "Stage 7" of religious or agape orientation into his system of moral stages, but he has not yet formally endorsed it. Kohlberg's recognition of religious thinking and

experience as a powerful agent or force in the making of men and women of the

highest moral maturity comes later when his six stages theory of cognitive moral

development is found insufficient to explain the moral actions or behaviors of

such persons as Martin Luther King or Andrea Simpson.

As a developmental psychologist, Kohlberg tries hard to separate moral

reasoning from religious thinking and experience by defining the former as

scientific reasoning to moral maturity and the latter as speculative metaphysical

intuiting and experience of oneness with such abstractions as God, Cosmic

Order, Reality, or the Whole, and so on. Only reluctantly, it appears, does

Kohlberg contemplate adding a "Stage 7” that enables a man of justice to act in

justice for his love of it.

The classical thinkers of both China and Athens did not carry the illusion

of thinking that universal and absolute moral values are entirely within the

range of human reason alone to apprehend. Rather, these values were the

"ways of Heaven" according to the Confucians and in the intelligible realm of

"Ideas" according to the Athenians. As moral educators, therefore, the classical

thinkers were the trainers not only of their students' reasoning capacity, but also

of their beyond- or extra-rational perceptivity to comprehend the "ways of

Heaven" or the "Ideas.” To them, moral education was the search for the

171 absolute, universal, and eternal moral values that should prevail in the cosmos, therefore, it was a rational as well as religious mission, which, they believed, they were assigned to carry out by Heaven or God. They would not separate cognitive moral reasoning from religious thinking in stimulating moral development, because in their view, cognitive and religious reasoning were not separable and should be developed together.

Confucius, for instance, firmly believed that his moral power and his mission as a moral educator were endowed by Heaven. Even though Heaven's ways were often perplexing and inscrutable, to him Heaven was the cosmic source of moral order and the only way to make the human world moral was to learn from the ways of Heaven. His Heaven ordained mission was, therefore, to love the ways of Heaven himself as always and help his students, too, acquire the knowledge of them so that they would make them prevail in human society as they once had prevailed under the sage kings of the past.56

Our Athenian thinkers, too, believed that the world was made in accordance with the absolute, eternal, and fundamental values, Ideas, which even the Olympian gods could not change, because the Ideas existed before the creation of gods. They also believed that the soul of man is immortal and it had seen or known the everlasting, unchanging, and absolute values of the good, the beautiful, the just, the true, and the holy, before it came to the world in

human form, therefore, their mission as moral educators was to help it reason

and recollect the knowledge it always had. And they took this mission humbly

and reverently because it was the divine command.57

Socrates was accused as a "criminal and busybody" by Meletus for

performing exactly this mission. One of Meletus' many charges against

Socrates was for his "investigating the things beneath the earth and in the

heavens and making the weaker argument stronger and teaching others these

172 same things."58 Socrates defended himself most movingly as follows. In the Apology we read:

Men of Athens, I respect and love you, but I shall obey the god rather than you, and while I live and am able to continue, I shall never give up philosophy or stop exhorting you and pointing out the truth to any one of you whom I may meet, young and old, foreigner and citizen... For know that the god commands me to do this, and I believe that no greater good ever came to pass to the city than my service to the god... And so, men of Athens, I am making my defense not for my own sake, as one might imagine, but more for yours, that you may not by condemning me err in your treatment of the gift the God gave you... Therefore I say to you, men of Athens, either do as Anytus tells you, or not, and either acquit me, or not, knowing that I shall not change my conduct even if I am to die many times over... But you also, judges, must regard death hopefully and must bear in mind this one truth that no evil can come to a good man either in life or after death, and God does not neglect him...... Now the time has come to go away. I go to die, and you to live; but which of us goes to the better lot, is known to none but God.59

In concluding this portion of study it is clear that all those who attained

the highest moral maturity are not only men and women of reason, but also of

faith in what is higher than themselves and in the absolute, universal, and

immutable values human reason alone cannot fully comprehend. It is

significant to note that all those persons Kohlberg cited as the achievers of the

highest moral excellence with the knowledge of the absolutes are without

exception men and women of profound religious faith of one sort or another.

Indeed, Socrates, Marcus Aurelius, Gandhi, Martin Luther King, Mother Teresa

of Calcutta, Janusz Korczak, and Confucius, too, were all clear thinkers who

upheld justice in making their moral judgments, and then went further to act

justly for their love of and service to Heaven, God, Nature, or whatever one may

call it, in whose agape all human beings are equal.

173 CHAPTER VII

SUMMARY AND CONCLUSION

The absence of moral authority in the rulers and the general deterioration of moral quality in people's lives, which made our thinkers of the Chou China and the City-State of Athens deeply concerned about the future of their respective states some twenty-three centuries ago, are what make us again today apprehensive for the future not only of this country, but of the whole world.

Since the end of World War II a few industrial powers have raised their living standards to an unprecedented height, thus widening the gap between themselves and the underdeveloped nations of the "have-nots." In today's world, however, modern technology in communication and transportation has brought all human races closer to each other and made the world a much smaller place than ever before. Thus, one nation's problems are no longer confined to that nation, but affect the rest of the world. Now more than ever, the few "have" nations must take up their moral responsibility to help the many

"have-not" nations, instead of exploiting them as in the past, in order to avoid tragic and global conflict.

We are now compelled to be aware that all human races must cooperate with and care for each other to live happily on this planet, for we are fated to coexist whether we want to or not. Yet, even after the two World Wars, we have

not been freed from large and small scale wars to the present. The future of the

world looked even bleaker when the two super-powers, the United States and

the Soviet Union, having divided up the world into two hostile camps,

174 threatened each other by stockpiling nuclear weapons. To our great relief, however, they finally seem to have realized that in a nuclear war there will be

no winners and appear to be intent on resolving their differences with the use of

reason. And indeed, it is the moral obligation of the super powers to liberate

human beings from the fear of nuclear war. The United States should assume

her share of leadership in a global effort to eliminate nuclear weapons once and for all.

There are many problems, in addition to nuclear war, which now threaten

the survival of this planet and everything on it. Environmental pollution, over¬

population and hunger are other problems of global proportions which can and

must be solved through the cooperative effort and moral commitment of the

leadership of all countries. Nations such as the United States, which is founded

on the universal values of justice, freedom, equality, and happiness for all

human beings, must now hold themselves accountable.

Ironically, however, the United States of all nations is deeply troubled by

loss of a moral standard. When a nation’s rich, well educated, and privileged,

who occupy positions of leadership are morally confused and violate even

basic moral values, how can we expect its poor, undereducated, and under¬

privileged to act otherwise? It is essential, therefore, to restore the nation's

moral health from the top down, for without a morally healthy leadership, we will

not have a morally healthy nation.

If we examine the current moral climate in the United States, we find that

our young people in particular exercise reckless violence on themselves and

others. They behave as though they have never learned to think or have given

up thinking. Their behavior indicates that they have lost faith in the nation's

leadership and in most human institutions, which seem to accept double¬

standards. Many of our young people, including children, who "are often

175 stronger and tougher than we think, and are capable of more moral reflection and political savvy than we give them credit for, and also know about moral hypocrisy,'"1 seem to have turned inward, jealously protecting their own privacy and right to get a maximum amount of self-centered happiness out of their lives by any means. Even those who clearly have violated other people's

'inalienable Rights' to 'Life, Liberty and the pursuit of Happiness,' demand respect for their own rights. One can seriously question also whether or not this nation's justice system is indeed serving justice for all the citizens equally regardless of their racial, economic, and social backgrounds.

Of all human enterprises, education has been the most powerful in the development of human civilization. Of all branches of learning that have

contributed to that development, moral education has been the most important,

for it makes human individuals become aware of their relatedness to each other

and helps them acquire the knowledge of universal moral values, such as, of

justice, goodness, love, reciprocity, and trust, which alone can make

harmonious coexistence possible.

Keeping in mind what I have learned from the classical thinkers of China

and Greece and Kohlberg, I would draw the following conclusions. First, I am in

agreement with all the thinkers I have read for this study, that above and over all

other educations or trainings which aim to produce specialists for a civilized

society, moral education must be taken as the most important, for without moral

standards, a society cannot be considered truly civilized. Although a universal

moral education is our ultimate goal, a special emphasis must be placed on the

moral education of the future leaders in government, business, industry, and the

legal profession. I wonder as Derek Bok of Harvard does why "somehow the

whole question of moral development, the development of character, is not

thought to be a central aim of most universities."2

176 Second, I believe that moral education should start with adult members of society for the following reasons. Adults play various and important roles in their children's lives for at least the first eighteen years, as their parents, teachers, and above all as their role-models. Parents are children's first and most intimate teachers of morality. The classical thinkers felt that moral education should begin even from the day the children are conceived and accordingly, admonished expectant mothers to speak, think, and behave morally lest they may impart morally undesirable influence on the unborn.

Hopefully most parents are morally maturer than their children. Even so, they must not force their values on their children, because forcing on children even good and sound values can damage that most important relationship between parents and their children. The parents must do their best to provide a family environment that is natural, loving, and just, for the children learn much about what is right or wrong at home.

As children enter the period of formal education, the next group of adults come into their lives, the teachers. The teachers can help the children improve their moral reasoning. Some important qualities all teachers must have are: (1)

Besides having a competent knowledge of the subject each of them teachers, they must seek the knowledge of universal moral values and consider them the most important elements for the wholesome growth of their children. (2) The teachers must care, love, and respect the students, because the future of society and its moral quality are dependent on them. (3) To establish a good and trusting relationship with the students, the teachers must be completely honest with himself and with the students. They must be willing to admit their ignorance if they does not know and acknowledge their mistakes when noted.

(4) The teachers must have their own moral standard, even if it may have to be

altered later. For there are clearly justice and injustice, good and evil, right and

177 wrong in the world, therefore, no teacher can be value-neutral. Teachers without their own moral standards will not be able to help their students’ moral development. (5) The teachers must become skillful users of various methods of moral education, knowing that there is no one method successfully applicable to all students at all times. (6) A person's moral maturity is not simply a matter of saying the right things, but is a matter of acting upon them as well.

Therefore, they should make this clear to their students, and at the same time practice themselves what they believe to be just and good. For people, including young children, are not blind to a man or woman of moral excellence and can most readily learn from him or her.

Third, although all three grounds used the dialectical method, the classical thinkers recommended other methods more suitable to those students whose capacity for philosophical reasoning on moral problems was not yet ready. Kohlberg's approach endorses only the dialectical method for all students of moral values, regardless of age.

The dialectical method according to Kohlberg is democratic, non- relativistic, and non-indoctrinative. It is democratic, because the method involves everybody in the group discussing moral problems and values. It is non-relativistic, because it specifically aims at acquiring the universal moral values upon which everybody can agree. And it is non-indoctrinative, because it makes students seek these values independently using their own reasoning

minds so that the values so acquired will be their own.

The classical thinkers, recognized, as does Kohlberg, that dialectics is

the best method, for it stimulates the students' own reasoning minds to their full

development, so that they can see on their own the values of moral excellence.

In contrast to Kohlberg, however, the classical thinkers did not attempt to use it

with little children, but only with adult students who were intellectually mature

178 and capable of carrying on philosophical discussions. Children, too, think, but they are certainly not yet "philosophers." And, as Kohlberg’s own research findings indicate, the method is not effective even with high school students, for they are not mature enough to carry on an intellectual discussion on moral issues.

By dismissing other methods, especially conventional methods, as indoctrinative, Kohlberg severely limits his approach. His fear of indoctrination is excessive and unwarranted. In today’s world, even people who live under the most totalitarian regimes are not easily indoctrinated. They may not say what they really think, but they do think and will never cease to think. The voice of reason that demands respect for universal moral values in the U.S.S.R.,

Poland, Tibet, South Africa, and elsewhere, cannot be silenced by force.

Teachers do not indoctrinate their students by introducing someone else's moral values, for example, of Confucius, Socrates, Jesus, Martin Luther

King, or their own, as long as they do not deny students' rights to accept or reject any of the values presented. Moral values, such as love, justice, temperance, truthfulness, and so on, are absolutely essential to civilized society and must be defended. Presenting these proven moral values with the reasons that underlie them to students for their critical evaluation is an important method of moral education. Moreover, no one, including children, accepts externally imposed moral values blindly. Sooner or later, when they face problems that require moral judgments and decisions, they will examine and reexamine the validity of these values.

In Kohlberg’s view, any method that imparts predetermined moral values to children, who are viewed as passive learners, is indoctrinative. Accordingly,

what he labels as the "bag of virtues," the "Boy Scout," and "Sunday School"

approaches are not acceptable, because they propound virtues which have

179 been determined by a particular religion, culture or society and therefore do not

help the development of children’s own moral reasoning. He also points out

that "a vague consensus on the goodness of these virtues, such as honesty,

truthfulness, and so forth, "conceals a great deal of actual disagreement over

their definitions."3 Finally, citing the studies by Hartshorne and May (1928-

1930) and others, he concludes that the "bag of virtues" approach does not

make children moral. Regarding the definitions of each of the virtues in the bag, I agree with

Kohlberg that the definitions vary. Even Confucius and Socrates could not

provide a definition of jen or justice that satisfied everyone, confessing man’s

humble and limited capacity to describe the ultimate "Moral Reality,

"Principles," "Way," or "Forms." However, no one can miss the simplest and

purest meaning of a virtue such as honesty or truthfulness. Certainly not all

children who attend Sunday School or are boy or girl scouts will grow up to be

moral individuals, but I believe that for most, their affiliation with these groups,

will make them more aware of the existence of moral conflicts in the world, and

will teach them that "good" or moral behavior does not always entail getting

what one wants or receiving the praise and approval of others. Over the centuries, all civilized cultures have accepted as universal and

enduring the virtues included in the bag such as, honesty, temperance,

truthfulness, moral courage, self-control, and so forth. As marts nature and the

nature of his moral problems and dilemmas have not changed over the

centuries, people in today's world can learn a great deal from the past

experiences of men and women, whose collective wisdoms contributed to the

making of more humane and moral communities. In addition, we must explore

Iflethods o, moral education used by different culture, such as —

cultures, for their methods could definitely enrich our pedagogical resources.

180 Fourth, any suggestion of unifying our educational efforts or imposing censorship on educational materials by a central authority frightens most

Americans. But a set of moral guidelines or standards, must be adopted to ensure the nation's moral health and well-being. As the arms race of the 70s and early 80s proved to us, military strength ultimately does not make a nation strong. Moreover, in our unrestrained materialism and desire for excessive material comfort, we have neglected or lost sight of gains we should have made on the moral front. Somehow, the United States needs to regain its values- reestablish the moral grounds upon which it was founded. Laws which protect the people of this country, including its youth, already exist, such as laws on drinking, the use of drugs, and the control of pornography. A national effort must be made to see that the laws are observed. For in the final analysis, it is a nation's moral ideals and commitment to those ideals which makes it strong. A nation without a moral backbone cannot last long. It is my belief that the enormous task of restoring this nation's values is the job of moral education. It requires the cooperative effort of all concerned and the federal government must do its part.

Freedom of choice and freedom of action are the fundamental requisites for the democratic way of life. While these values must be preserved, they can make America a difficult place for children to grow up free and be moral and remain moral throughout their lives. But America, a microcosm of the world, is one place where a serious moral education must start, not only for the future of this country, but for the future of the rest of the world.

181 NOTES

Chapter I

1. The traditional Chinese histories date the Chou period to have been between 1122 and 211 B.C. Modern scholars differ widely on this matter, dating the beginning of the period between 1137 and 991 B C See Bam’ber Gascoigne, The Treasures and Dynasties of China (London: Jonathan Cape 1973), p. 31.

2. A contrary opinion on the Chou's ethnic origin is discussed in L. Carrington Goodrich's A Short History of the Chinese People, rev. ed. (New York: Harper and Brothers, 1951), p. 19.

3. Wolfram Eberhard, "On Three Principles in Chinese Social Structure” in Moral and Social Values of the Chinese, ser. no. 6 (Taipei, Taiwan: Distributed by Chinese Materials and Research Aids Service Center, 1970). Also see Wang Hsueh-wen, Legalism and Anti-Confucianism in Maoist Politics (Taipei, Taiwan: Institute of International Relations, 1975); Zhou Jinwei, "On Spiritual Civilization,” Beiiinq Review, vol. 24, no. 10 (March 9, 1981), pp. 18-20; "Socialist Decorum," Beiiinq Review, vol. 24, no. 15 (April 13, 1981), p. 5.

4. John Meskill et al. eds., An Introduction to Chinese Civilization (New York: Columbia University Press, 1973), p. 12; Wolfram Eberhard, A History of China. 4th ed. (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1977), pp. 24-26.

5. Michael Loewe, Imperial China - The Historical Background to the Modern Age (London: George Allen and Unwin, 1966), pp. 50-51.

6. Charles O. Hucker, China's Imperial Past - An Introduction to Chinese History and Culture (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1975), pp. 35-39. For a fascinating and detailed study of the Eastern Chou period, see Cho-yun Hsu, Ancient China in Transition - An Analysis of Social Mobility. 722-222 B.C. (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1965), especially chapters 3 and 4. Meskill points out that "For almost five centuries only one year in four was free of warfare among the major states." See his Introduction to Chinese Civilization, p. 15.

7. For numbers of feudal states at various times during the Warring States period, see Frederick W. Mote, Intellectual Foundation of China (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1971), p. 11.

182 Porinri Of rurrl00 ^f061! Hie Birth Qf China - A Survey Of the FnrmatjYf Eenpd Qf Chinese Civilization (New York: Frederick Ungar, 1937) n. 245- Hucker, Qhina § Imperial Pg?t, pp. 36-37; James Leqqe. The Chinese Cla'scirc 5vo|s. (Hong Kong: Hong Kong University Press, 1970;reprinted?from thelast edition of the Oxford University Press), 5: 114-117.

9. Mencius. VII. B. 2.

10. Hucker, China’s Imperial Past, p. 37.

Jo H.ej'.ee G' ■C:'!ee1, Confucius anfl thft r-hinog° W1Y Harper and Row, I960), pp. 22-23.

•^u Hsu, Ancient China in Transition, pp. 68-71. For an extensive study which compares the size of armies of the Chou states and the frequency of war during the Spring and Autumn and the Warring States period, see Ibid., pp. 53-

13. Eberhard, A History of China, pp. 54-57; Goodrich, A Short Histnrv nf the Chinese People, p. 23; Meskill, An Introduction to Chinese Civilization, pp. 16-20.

14. Rene Grousset, The Rise and Splendour of the Chinese Empire, trans. Anthony Watson-Gandy and Terence Gordon (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1965), pp. 39-41.

15. Ml-, P- 41; Hsu has 1,217,000 as war casualties of the Warring States period. See his Ancient China in Transition, p. 67.

16. Mote, intellectual Foundation of China, pp. 31 -32; Creel, The Birth of China, pp. 357-362.

17. Mote, Intellectual Foundation of China, pp. 35.

18. Joseph Needham Science and Civilisation in China, vol. 1 (London: Cambridge University Press, 1954), pp. 95-96.

19. Creel, Confucius and the Chinese Wav, p. 75.

20. Fung Yu-lan, A History of Chinese Philosophy, 2 vols. (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1953), 1:48.

21. Mote, Intellectual Foundation of China, pp. 39-40; Creel, Confucius and the Chinese Wav, pp. 164-170.

22. The Great Learning, trans. James Legge in The Chinese Classics, vol. 1, pp. 357-359 (text of Confucius 3-6).

183 23. Creel, The Birth of China pp. 365-366.

24. The Analects. VII i

25. Needham, Science and Civilisation in China vol. 2, p. 6.

, 26- UnYutang, Thg Wisdom of Confucius (New York: Modern Library lyjoj, pp. d/i-dJ4. 7’

27. The period is down to the year of Plato's death.

28. Hellanicus of Lesbos dated the first king of Athens to 1796 B C in his Ms or local history, which appeared c. 402 B.C., but modern scholars aoree on W RUrh 'a“,0' V250, ?S® nGL Han2>mond' A History Of flreere to P,C., 2nd ed. (London: Oxford University Press, 1967), pp. 583-584 Traditional histories say that it was the legendary king Theseus of Athens who had united all Attica under his rule. See Morton Smith, The Ancient HrppWq (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1960), p. 20.

29. A.R. Burn, The Pelican History of Greece (Harmnnriswnrth. Middlesex, England: Penguin Books Ltd., 1975), p. 308. The king was chairman of the jury-court at the trial of Socrates.

30. Raphael Sealey, A History of the Greek City States: ca. 700-338 B C (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1976), p. 95.

31. Sealey thinks that Cylon was motivated by personal ambition and doubts that he was a champion of popular discontent. See Sealey, op. cit., p. 98f., 114-115.

32. PP- 99-105, 130-133 for a detailed study of the surviving text.

33. Ibid., pp. 108-110 on Solonian reform; pp. 112, 114-119 on Eupatridae; pp. 119-121 on four classes.

34. Jean Hatzfeld, History of Ancient Greece (New York: W.W. Norton & Company, Inc., 1966), p. 129.

35. Sealey, A History of the Greek City States, pp. 123-126 regarding the nature of struggle which Peisistratus was in, Herodotus and Aristotle held differing interpretations.

36. Ibid., p. 127.

37. Hatzfeld, History of Ancient Greece, p. 68f.

38. Sealey, op. cit., pp. 151-155.

184 39. Ml-, pp. 155-157; N.G.L. Hammond. A Historv nf nroo^p tn qoo d ^ 2nd ed., (London: Oxford University Press, I9b^ p 190 t0 P r-

. 4P’ . ,Sea|ey. op- cit., pp. 164-165. Sealey points out that the modern scholarship questions the origin of ostracism which has been attributed to Cleisthenes, noting that Cleisthenes is not known to have been active after 500 thp J^YQf AncientJatesca. p. 130. The author explains how the generals (strategoi) became politically powerful during the Greco-Persian wars.

_ 42- Thucydides, Ifafi Peloponnesian Wqr, trans. with an introduction by Rex Warner (Harmondsworth, Middlesex, England: Penguin Books Ltd 1 971), pp. 123-129 for a graphic description of the plague and its effects on the’ Athenians.

43. Ml-, PP-180-191.

/kl 44- A.E. Taylor, Sacrates: The Man and His Thought. Anchor Rook* (New York: Doubleday & Co., 1953), pp. 37-88 for a comprehensive study of the composition and nature of the Socratic circle and some of the contemporary luminaries who were friends of Socrates. Also, see W.K.C. Guthrie, Socrates (London: Cambridge University Press, 1971), pp. 53-54 on the nature of gathering around Socrates.

45. Plato, Apology. 21 A et seq.

46. Plato's Protagoras and I Alcibiades tell us about the pre-Socratic education in ancient Greece. Also, see an excellent study on the Homeric education in Werner Jaeger, Paideia - The Ideals of Greek Culture, trans. Gilbert Highet (London: Oxford University Press, 1960), vol. 1, Introduction and first three chapters.

185 Chapter II

1. Analects, 1.7; IX. 17; XV. 12.

2. Jen ( ) and jen-yi (4-^) in a broader sense can be rendered as moral.’

3. Mencius, trans. with an introduction by D.C. Lau (Middlesex, England: Penguin Books Ltd., 1970), pp. 82-83.

4. The term hsin ( ^ ) is translated variously in English. See Confucius; Confucian Analects, the Great Learning and the Doctrinp gi Mean, trans. with critical and exegetical notes, prologomena, copious indexes and dictionary of all characters by James Legge (New York: Dover Publications, Inc., 1971), p. 468; The Analects of Confucius. W.E. Soothill (New York: Paragon Book Reprint Corp., 1968), p. 966; Mathew’s Chinese-Fngiish Dictionary, rev. American ed. (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press 1956), p. 404.

5. Giancarlo Finazzo, The Principle of Tien : Essay on its Theoretical Relevancy in early Confucian Philosophy. Mei Ya International ed. (New York: Paragon Book Gallery, Ltd., 1967), pp. 145-146. Finazzo notes: "The word is one of the most significant in Chinese cosmology, where it denotes the dual power of Yin and Yang . It is currently used otherwise, but occurs rarely injlhe Four Books, as: - physical energy, vigour (M: II. A. 2. viii) % - the raw natural energy that pervades the body (M: II. A. 2. ix, x)... This natural force is to be combined with righteousness (yi ) and the Way (iJt). If duly nourished by rectitude (chih $->) it expands itself immensely... Strong is its meaning in Mencius VI. A. 8. ii., where the word is employed twice, expressing both the "vigour" given by the night-rest and the "vigour" to pursue the right path, which man feels in himself. This "vigour" includes ardour and mood, and is grounded on the natural energy whose character has been considered in Mencius II. A. 2. ix, x."

6. The chapter where the "Niu Mountain" analogy is mentioned by Mencius as translated by Dobson reads as follows:

Mencius said, "Bull (Niu) Mountain was once wooded. But, because it was close to a large city, its trees all fell to the axe. What of its beauty then? However, as the days passed, things grew, and with the rains and the dews it was not without greenery. Then came the cattle and goats to graze. That is why, today, its has that scoured-like appearance. On seeing it now, people imagine that nothing ever grew there. But this is surely not the true nature of a mountain? And so, too, with human beings. Can it be that any man's mind naturally lacks Humanity (jen) and Justice (yi)? If he loses his sense of the good, then he loses it as the

186 mountain lost its trees, It has been hacked away at - day after day - what of its beauty then? "However as the days pass he grows, and, as with all men in the still air of the early hours his sense of right and wrong is at work. If it is barelv perceptible, it is because his actions during the day have disturbed or V destroyed it. Being disturbed and turned upside down the 'niqht airs' can barely sustain it. If this happens he is not far removed from the animals, beeing a man so close to an animal, people cannot imaqine that once his nature was different - but this is surely not the true nature of the man? Indeed, if nurtured aright, anything will grow, but if not nurtured ariqht anything will wither away. Confucius said, ’Hold fast to it, and you ’ preserve it; let it go and you destroy it; it may come and go at any time no one knows its whereabouts.' Confucius was speaking of nothing less than the mind." y

7. Basic Writings pf Mo Tzu. Hsun Tzu. and Han Fei Tzu. trans. Burton Watson (New York: Columbia University Press, 1967), p. 157.

8. Mi., pp. 158-159.

9. Ml-, pp. 166-167.

10. Ml-, pp. 170-171.

11. Analects. XII. 29. XIII. 11.

12. Finazzo, The Principle or Tien pp. 102-103.

13. Plato. Republic. 415 A - B.

14. Ml- 558 D - 559 C, 573 A - D.

15. Ml-, 550 B, 553 C, 581 B.

16. Ibid.. 440 A - C.

17. Mi-, 435 E, 553, 562 A, 589 E, 590 C.

18. Ml- 442 A - B, 550 A - B, 572 A, 580 E - 581 C.

19. Plato, Timaeus. trans. Francis M. Cornford, The Library of Liberal Arts series (New York: The Bobbs-Merrill Company, 1959)

20. Liddell and Scott's Greek-English Lexicon, rev. ed. Henry Stuart Jones and Roderick McKenzie (London: Oxford University Press, 1968), pp. 1827-1828.

187 21 . Plato, La&s, 713 C-D. See also E.R. Dodds, Ihe Greeks anrj ^ irrational (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1951), p 215.

22. Plato, Laws. 896 D - E.

188 Chapter III

1* 'Jen-yi' is extensively discussed in Chapter V.

2. In Mencius III. A. 3. X we read the following passages:

;Hsiang'4 , 'hsu'^ , ’hseuh’ and hsiao %were set up for the purpose of education 'Hsianq' means rearing , 'hsiao' means 'teaching' and 'hsu' means 'archery' In the Hsia Dynasty it was called 'hsiao', in the Yin 'hsu' and in the Chou 'hsiang', while 'hsueh' was a name common to all Three Dynasties They all serve to make the people understand human relationships. When it is clear that those in authority understand human relationships the people will be affectionate. Should a true King arise, he is certain to take this as his model. Thus he who practices this will be tutor to a true King. The Book of Odes says,

Though Chou is an old state, Its Mandate its new.

This refers to King Wen. If you can put heart into your practice you would also be able to renew your state, (trans. D.C. Lau, Mencius, pp. 98-99)

3. W.E. Soothill, The Analects, p. 242.

4. Li Fu Chen, The Confucian Wav - A New and Systematic Study of the Four Books, trans. Shih Shun Liu (Republic of China: National Chengchui University, 1970), pp. 13-19 for a long controversy over the "investigation of things" and Li Fu Chen's own commentary. Also, see James Legge, The Chinese Classics, vol. 1. Confucian Analects. The Great Learning, and The Doctrine of the Mean (Hong Kong: Hong Kong University Press, 1960), p. 358.

5. Analects. VII. 29: Legge.

6. Mencius. VII. A. 3. i: Lau.

7. In the Laws we read:

CLIN. What is that, Stranger? Are we to prescribe most exercise for new-born babies and tiny infants?

ATH. Nay, even earlier than that, - we shall prescribe it for those nourished inside the bodies of their mothers.

189 talking of?21^' Wha‘ d° V°U mea"' my d6ar Sir? ls 11 unborn babes you are

... 11 iS' StMI 11 is by no means surprising that you know nothinn nf this pre-natal gymnastic... (789 A - B: Bury) 9 ot

Plato says further on the matter:

For because of the force of habit, it is in infancy that the whole character is most effectually determined. I should assert further - were it not that it would be taken as a jest - that women with child above all others should be cared for during their years of pregnancy, lest any of them should indulge in repeated and intense pleasures or pains instead of cultivating, during the whole of that period, a cheerful, bright and calm demeanour. (Laws: 792 E: Bury)

8. Laws. 810 A - B.

9. On final selection of the future guardians for the highest education see Republic, 498, 503 E - 504 B, 537 A - E; Laws. 817 E, 961 A - C 964 E 965 A.

10. Republic. 373 D - 374 E.

11. Ibid-, 414 B - 415 D, 545 C - 547 C.

12. Ibid.. 401 D- 403C.

13. Ibid.. 520 D - E, 521 A: trans. Shorey.

190 Chapter IV

1 • ln the Analects we also read: The Master said, "In letters I am perhaps equal to other men, but the character of the superior man carrvinn out in his conduct what he professes, is what I have not yet attained to." (VII 32- Legge) The Master said, "As to being a Divine Sage of even a Good Man far be it from me to make any such claim. As for unwearying effort to learn and unflagging patience in teaching others, those are merits that I do not hesitate to claim." (A: VII. 33: Waley) Cf. Mencius: II. A. 2. xix.

2. W E. Soothill's translation of VII. 19 of the Analects in his Analects p. 309.

3. The Master said, "I am not one who was born in the possession of knowledge; I am one who is fond of antiquity and earnest in seeking it there " (A: VII. xix: Legge) The Master said, "A transmitter and not a maker believina in and loving the ancients..." (A: VII. i: Legge)

4. James Legge quotes Sze-ma Ch'ien who "makes Confucius say: - The disciples who received my instructions, and could themselves comprehend them, were seventy-seven individuals. They were all scholars of extraordinary ability.'" Legge himself lists eighty-eight "whose names have come down to us, as being his followers." James Legge, Confucian Analects. The Great Learning and The Doctrine of the Mean, p. 112. H.G. Creel. Confucius and the Chinese Way, Harper Torchbooks ed. (New York: Harper & Row Publishers, 1960), p. 63. Creel wrote: "Even when men are cited in the Analects as having asked questions of Confucius, it is not easy to be certain whether or not they were disciples. That work mentions some twenty-two persons who, it seems reasonable to believe, were disciples, but of these only a few stand forth as distinct individuals." About Mencius' disciples, Legge notes that "the disciples of Mencius were much fewer in number, and of less distinction than those of Confucius. The longest list does not make them amount to twenty-five." See James Legge, The Works of Mencius, p. 76.

5. Analects. I. 1, V. 21, VII. 28, XIII. 21; and Mencius VII. B. 37. ii.

6. Analects. VII. 7.

7. The Master said, "When I walk along with two others, they may serve me as my teachers. I will select their good qualities and follow them, their bad qualities and avoid them." (A: VII. 21: Legge)

8. Also see Analects. IX. 18. Admonishing his disciples not to give up their search for knowledge in the middle of their pursuit, Confucius said: "Suppose I am raising a mound, and, while it is still unfinished by a basketful, I stop short, it is I that stops short. Or, suppose I begin on the level ground, -

191 although I throw down but one basketful and continue to do make progress." (A: IX. 18: Soothill) so, then it is I that

9. See Mencius, VII. A. 41, also VII. B. 5. ie tJ?' A‘ 7‘ v says: "Heaven’s plan in the production of mankind ^ th's. - that they who are first informed should instruct those who are later in being informed, and they who first apprehend principles should instruct those who are slower to do so. I am one of Heaven's people who have first apprehended; -1 will take these principles and instruct this people in them If I 28 t?em’ Wh° Wl11 d° S°?" ^Le"e^ AIS0 See’ D M~: xxv- 3; A: VI.

.. V ,FA°r *?n excellent study on this question, see "On Mencius’ Use of the Analogy in Argument" in Mencius, trans. D. C. Lau, Appendix 5, pp.

12. If the ruler is moral, so the people, too, will be. SeeGL IX 8&9-A- VIII. 2. ii, II. i, XV. 9; M: II. A. 8. iii and v. ' ~

13. About friends, see A- IV. 17. About places to live, see M '- II. A. 7. ii. On choosing neighbors Mencius quotes Confucius: "Confucius said, ’It is virtuous manners which constitute the excellence of a neighbourhood. If a man, in selecting a residence, does not fix on one where such prevail, how can he be wise?" (M: A. 7. ii: Legge)

14. Ancient sage-rulers whom both Confucius and Mencius considered wise, good, and just are succinctly described in H.G. Creel, Confucius and the Chinese Way, pp. 144-147, 185, 186, 188, 193. Also see, A: VI. 28, VIII. 19, XIV. 45, XX. 1; M: II. A. 2. 8, B. 2; IV. A. 1.2. 26. 28, B. 1. 19. 28. 32; V. A. 1 -7, B. 1. 3. 6; VIII. A. 16. 25. 30. 35. 46, B. 6. 32. 37. 38.

15. "Socrates does not speak of his 'pupils,' and refuses to be called anyone's 'teacher'" (Ap. 33 A). He has only an 'association' ( cTui/oocrca , cf ol crovov'res) with other men, of whatever age, and 'converses' with them (Sta'Xc

16. Laws. 788 ff.

17. Werner Jaeger, Paideia. vol. 2, p. 302.

18. Ibid., p. 63.

192 Chapter V

oc7. wa|J"e?ge; g?nfHC'an ,AnqlectR, P- 202’ Soothill, Analects of Confucius p. 357, Waley, Analects fllganiuciua, p. 128; Lau, Confucius- The Analects p 89.

196 on th^'w'off'yeh^^0)'^' PP' 357'359; Le9"' CfltltUCian *™'<*<*- P-

3- Waley, Analects of Confucius pp. 39-40.

. 4: Jlaid- PP- 39-41 ■ The passages in the Analects where the term ’wen’ (jC) is used to mean literary studies or literature are: I. 6 VI 25 VII 24 3? IX. 10. ii, XI. 2. ii, XII. 15. 24. '

5. James Legge, The Chinese Classics, vol. 4 The She King or the Bonk QlPoetry (Hong Kong: Hong Kong University Press, 1960), pp. 1-7 Also Creel, Confucius and the Chinese Way pp. 101 -103.

6. Analects. IX. 14.

7. Commenting on Analects XVII. 10 Legge notes: "Chau-nan and Shao-nan are the titles of the first two Books in the Songs of the States, or first part of the Shih-ching. For the meaning of the titles, see the Shi-Ching, I. i. and I. ii. They are supposed to inculcate important lessons about personal virtue and family government." Legge, Confucian Analects, p. 323.

8. By the time of Mencius the Shang Dynasty was no longer a legendary dynasty.

9. Analects, n. 23, m. u.

10. Mencius. V. A. 6. iii says: "To bring to the throne he whom no man can bring, that rests with Heaven's ordinances. One who, being a commoner, becomes the Son of Heaven, must be a man whose virtue is of the order of Shun's and Yu’s and, too, he must have a Son of Heaven to propose him. It was for this reason (i.e., because no Son of Heaven was in a position to propose him), that Confucius did not become the Son of Heaven." Dobson, Mencius, p. 63.

11. Mencius. III. B. 9. viii and xi.

12. Wolfgang Bauer, China and the Search for Happiness, trans. Michael Shaw (New York: Seabury Press, 1976), p. 22.

13. Mencius. IV. B. 22. ii.

193 , _.14, Le99e-1ha Chinese glassies, voi. 2: The Works of unH^tS.H68 S,ze-m,a Ch'ien’s account, which s^Ts tha^enciurSie^ the disdplles of Tsze-sze.' Mencius said: "Although I could not bp p ?'snclP e,of Confucius myself, I have endeavoured to cultivate my character and knowledge by means of others who were." (M: IV. B. 22: Legge) ^

15. Dobson. Mencius, p 14Q

16. Chen, The Confuoian vy^y pp. 53.54.

17 Harley Farnsworth MacNair, ed. China, United Nations series Berkeley and Los Angeles, 1951), pp. 31,49^5-59. 63; CreeL The Sfnh n,

r J®' Apal'?':1SS- Cp"f|lpi|1^ PP' 54_59' 64-69; Dona« J- Munro The Qoncapt Qf Man in Early China Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press iorS? pp. 26-28, 32-35; and also Noah Edward Fehl, Li; Rite° anHSZ' 1969)' Ljtaratbrg an

20. Analects. 11.11, III. 15. 17. 20, VI. 20.

21. Yet, the observation of all the proper rules are considered important by Confucius. See The Doctrine of the Mean. XXVII. 3 and Analects. VIII. 4.

22. Fung Yu-lan, A History of Chinese Philosophy, p. 73.

23. Lau, Confucius - The Analects, p. 100.

24. Mencius. II. A. 6. v.

25. James Legge, trans. Li Chi: Book of Rites, vol. 1 (New York: University Book, 1967), Introduction xli.

26. Burton Watson, trans. Basic Writings of Mo Tzu. Hsun Tzu. and Han Fei Tzu (New York: Columbia University Press, 1967), pp. 112-117.

27. Creel, The Birth of China, p. 331.

28. D.C. Lau suggests to read Analects XIII. 37, which he renders: "The Master said, There is no one who understands me... If I am understood at all, it is, perhaps, by Heaven.'" (A: XIV. 35) See also Analects XIV. 42, where Confucius' frustrated mood was detected in his playing of the stone chimes.

29. Waley, Analects of Confucius, p. 191. Waley translates the poem: "If the water is deep, use the stepping-stones; if it is shallow, then hold up your

194 ski.*s>" saying that its meaning is, "Take the world as you find it" As Cnnf..ri..e sa,d m the text, that is indeed an easy way out, but it was not for Con,uclus

••Qho« n°u6S commenting on Analects III. 25 and XV. 10 v that Shao (-fro) was the name of the music made by Shun l%) oerfect in me ody and sentiment. Wu (^) was the music of King Wu tlso perfect in melody but breathing the martial air, indicative of its author." "The shao was the music of Shun; the ’dancer,’ or 'pantomimes,' who kept time to the music See the Shu-ching, II. u. 21." Legge, Confucian Analerts pp. 164, 298.

Mathews' Chinese-English Dictionary, pp 4in dio

32. The philosopher Tsang said, "...’Perfect virtue (jen-/-) is the burden which he considers it is his to sustain; - is it not heavy'? Only with death does his course stop;- is it not long?"’ (A: VIII. 7. ii: Legge) "The Master said hand^’’16 J6n\/ll. 29.3 Legge)thm9 remote? 1 wish t0 be virtu°us, and lo! virtue is at’

33. Creel, Confucius and the Chinese Wav p. 89.

34. Also see Analects. XIII. 19.

35. Some scholars argue that the correct character for the text was misplaced with 'M/ which is its homophone. Therefore, the passage, they say should read to ’renew the people ($

36. Doctrine of the Mean. XX. 20. 37. ibid., xxi.

38. Fung Yu-lan, A History of Chinese Philosophy, pp. 120-121 Bodde’s translation of M: II. A. 6. The word ’tuan’ ) is translated as "germ" by Lau, "the principle" by Legge, and "the first sign" by Dobson.

39. Pu tung hsin ( 'f- ty/\cr ) is variously translated by others. Lau renders it as "a heart that cannot be stirred," in his translation of Mencius. II. A. 2. i. ii. iii. ix. x. Legge translates as "an unperturbed mind," and Dobson as "the mind that remains unmoved."

40. Ch’i ( ) is rendered by Legge as "passion nature," and by Dobson as "physical vigour." Lau’s short but excellent study of Ch’i states: "To understand Mencius’ teaching on the matter, it is necessary first to say something about the cosmology prevalent in the fourth century B.C. It was believed that the universe was made up of chi but this chi varied in consistency. The grosser ch’i. being heavy, settled to become the earth, while the refined ch’i. being light, rose to become the sky. Man, being half-way

195 between the two, is a harmonious mixture of the two kinds of chi His bodv consists of grosser chi while his heart is the seat of the refinedch'i The hinr,ri inehe9twneeeheha,S 35 ,he b°d* "°r as as the bS,t somewhere m between, but as it is not static and circulates in the body it is more akin to the refined chi... It is in virtue of the refined cm that a man is a ive and Ns faculties can function properly. As the heart is the seat of this refined chi it is necessa^ to have a regiment for the heart in order to be healthy and to IhTe to a ripe old ^ 3Q6... K , . ,n ^.^el''kno^5.PUsagejn II. A. 2, Mencius describes what he calls the tegjan Ch.h Ch.—ft.fr |L (the flood-like sM), and it is obvious that this presupposes the prevalent theory we have outlined.

But Mencius did not simply take over the current theory of chi he aave it a twist In the place of the physical Q he puts his own iiaojaojihilichl'which is, in the highest degree, vast and unyielding.' The point of contact between the frao |gn qhih ch’i and physical qWx is courage. Courage is believed to depend on cm. This no doubt has something to do with the fact that courage is accompanied by a state of heightened tension in the body in which breathing is quickened and the activity of the heart stimulated. But for Mencius, genuine courage, instead of being sustained by a state of heightened tension in the body, can only be sustained by the sense of being morally in the right. The hao jan phih ch'j 'is a £hl which unites rightness and the Way. Deprive it of these and it will collapse..." Lau, Mencius, pp. 24-28 passim.

41. More on tLSiaQ. ( ), see Fung Yu-lan, A History of Chinese Philosophy, pp. 357-361.

42. Finazzo, The Principle or Tien, p. 55.

43. Ibid., pp. 55-57.

44. Paul Shorey, Plato: The Republic. The Loeb Classical Library, vol. 1 (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1970), p. 175, note e.

45. Plato, The Republic. 386 A - 392 C passim.

46. Julius Portnoy, Music in the Life of Man (New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1963), p. 124.

47. Republic. 398 D - E.

48. 399 E.

49. M., 424 C; Laws. 700 A passim.

50. Laws. 802.

51. Ibid.. 766 A-B. 812 A-E.

196 52. Ibid., 700 C, 764 C - D; Republic. 424 B - D.

53. Shorey, Republic. 523 A, p. 153.

54. Ml., 526 E, p. 169. mathLo^'’ n0te f on 527 A’ p- 169- !t states that "geometry [and nHhp Pi tCS' 'S 'nevitabl7 less abstract than dialectics. But the special purpose abstract on°n"C educatlon values mathematics chiefly as a discipline in

56. idid., 527 C, p. 173.

. . 5^' p- 1 ®3' note f> commenting on 529 C - D, states that "No material object perfectly embodies the ideal and abstract mathematical relation. These mathematical ideas are designated as the true, , and the real, ••• 'be visible stars are in and are carried by their invisible mathematical orbits. By this way of speaking Plato, it is true, disregards the apparent difficulty that the movement of the visible stars then ouqht to be mathematically perfect..." y

58. idid , 530 D, p. 189.

59. Ml-, 531 C, pp. 193-195.

60. Cornford, The Republic of Plato, p. 251.

61. Shorey, Republic, 531 E, pp. 194-195. Shorey says that "though mathematics quickens the mind of the student, it is, apart from metaphysics, a matter of common experience that mathematicians are not necessarily good reasoners on other subjects..."; Charles Fox, Educational Psychology pp. 187- 188: "...a training in the mathematics may produce exactness of thought...provided that the training is of such a kind as to inculcate an ideal which the pupil values that he had "hardly ever known a mathematician who was capable of reasoning.’"

62. Cornford explains what Dialectic means in the Republic as follows: "It simply means the technique of philosophic conversation (dialogue) carried on by question and answer and seeking to render, or to receive from a respondent, an 'account' (logos) of some Form, usually a moral Form such as a Justice in this dialogue. At this stage visible illustrations are no longer available, and the movement at first is not downward, deducing conclusions from premisses, but upward, examining the premisses themselves and seeking the ultimate principle on which they all depend. It is suggested that, if the mind could ever rise to grasp the Supreme Form, it might then descend by a deduction confirming the whole structure of moral and mathematical knowledge. This state of mind is called intelligence or rational intuition (noesis) and knowledge (episteme, 533 E) in the full sense." Cornford, The Republic of Plato, p. 223.

197 63. ML 533 A, p. 253.

64. Haft, 533 C, p. 254.

65. "No absolute distinction can be drawn between and in Plato." Shorey, Republic, vol. 2, p. 104.

51 /I °n "thG intelligible world where the good is," see Republio 509 D -

67. Cornford, The Republic of Piqfn 506 B - D, pp. 216-217.

68. Bgpublic, 507 C. The sentence,"

H is rendered by different translators as follows. "And the one class of thinqs we say can be seen but not thought, while the ideas can be thought but not seen." (Shorey) Further the many things, we say, can be seen, but are not objects of rational thought; whereas the Forms are objects of thought, but invisible." (Cornford) "And, moreover, we say that the former are seen but not intellected while the ideas are intellected but not seen." (Bloom)

69. Plato, Philebus 20: Jowett.

70. Ibid.. 65 A: Jowett.

71. Laws, 631,661 A, 697. Also in the Republic. 357, 367 D; Protagoras 334; and Gorgias. 451 E. " ^

72. Shorey, Republic, vol. 2, 608 E, p. 471.

73. Ml-, 518 E, p. 137.

74. Bapublic 519 A; Phaedrus 278 D; Iheaetetus.

75. Plato, Charmides. 167 A; Jowett.

76. Plato, Phaedo. 69 B - C: Fowler.

77. Ml-, 79 D.

78. Republic. 518.

79. Ibid.. 427 E: Shorey.

80. As cited by Protarchus in the Philebus 45 E: Jowett.

81. Charmides. 159-167.

82. Gorgias. 504 D - E, 507, 508.

198 83. Bepublic. 430 E, 441 A, 442 D, 443, 591 D

84. Phaedo. 82 B.

85. Laws. 636 A.

86. ■Bepublic, 404 E, 410 passim; Laws. 802 passim.

87. ikid., 709 E, 710 B.

88. Mi-, 696 D- E.

89. ML, 647 D, 734 A - D.

90. Becobl'C, 268, 389, 431 A: also Laws, 73(1 F

91. Laches. 190 E.

92. Ml., 192 B.

93. Ibid.. 195 A.

94. .Republic. 430.

95. Ml. 375 A - B: Shorey.

96. As in the Laws, the Stranger in the Statesman is in effect Plato himself.

97. Republic. 430.

98. Ibid.. 308 A, 309 D - E.

99. Ibid.. 331 B: Shorey.

100. Ibid.. 332 D: Shorey.

101. Ibid.. 341 A: Shorey.

102. Ibid.. 350 D: Shorey.

103. Gorgias. 437: Republic. 445. 589 Dassim.

104. Ibid.. 353 B: Shorey.

105. Republic. 433 A; Shorev.

106. Ml-, 443 A: Cornford.

199 Ibid., 443 B: Cornford.

200 Chapter VI

3. ibid., pp. 39-40.

4. ibid-, pp. 9-10, 31-33, 184-185.

5. ibid-, p. 31.

6. Ibid.

7. ibid-, p. 4.

8. Ibid.

9. Ibid., pp. 10-12, 27-28.

10. ibid-, p. 55; Lawrence Kohlberg, "The Cognitive-Development Approach to Moral Education," in David Purpel & Kevin Ryan, eds., Moral Education; It Comes With the Territory (Berkeley: McCutchan, 1976), p. 177.

11. Lawrence Kohlberg, "The Moral Atmosphere of the School" in Purpel & Ryan, Moral Education, pp. 215-216.

12. Kohlberg, Essays on Moral Development, vol 1, pp. 115-116, 123, 141-142.

13. Kohlberg, "The Cognitive-Developmental Approach to Moral Education," in Purpel & Ryan, Moral Education, p. 181.

14. James Rest, "Developmental Psychology as a Guide to Value Education: A Review of 'Kohlbergian' Programs," in Purpel & Ryan, Moral Education., pp. 271-272; Donald W. Oliver and Mary Jo Bane, "Moral Education Is Reasoning Enough?," in Purpel & Ryan, Moral Education, pp. 357-359.

15. Kohlberg, Essays on Moral Development, vol. 1, pp. 143-144, 305.

16. Ibid., p. 46.

17. Kohlberg, "The Cognitive-Developmental Approach to Moral Education," in Purpel & Ryan, Moral Education, p. 189.

18. Kohlberg, Essays on Moral Development, vol. 1, p. 47.

201 19. Ibid.

20. Ibid., p. 28.

21- Mi., pp. 75-76.

22. Mi, p. 46.

23. Ml-, P- 46, 342.

24. Mi, p. 40.

25. Ml-, P- 39.

26. Ml-

27. Ml, P- 43.

28. Ml-

29. Kohlberg, "The Cognitive-Developmental Approach to Moral Education," in Purpel & Ryan, Moral Education p. 189.

_ 30- f/en Flanagan, Jr., The Science of the Mind (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1984), p. 150; Jack R. Fraenkel, "The Kohlberg Bandwagon: Some Reservations," in Purpel & Ryan, Moral Education, pp. 291-307.

31. Kohlberg, "The Cognitive-Developmental Approach to Moral Education," in Purpel and Ryan, Moral Education, p. 186.

32. Mi-

33. Mi, p.182.

34. Dennis Krebs, ed., Readings in Social Psychology (New York: Harper & Row, 1982), p. 326.

35. James Rest, "Development Psychology as a Guide," in Purpel & Ryan, Moral Education, p. 254.

36. Ibid., d. 212. 258.

202 Education for Adolescents, in Purpel & Ryan, Moral Education pp. 240-246.

38. Kohlberg, Essays on Moral Development p. 40.

39. ML, P. 318.

40. ML, P. 336, 343.

41. Ml-, P. 347.

42. Ml-, PP. 345-347, 354-356.

43. Ml-, P. 371.

44. Ml-, P. 346.

45. Ml-, PP. 346-347.

46. Ml- p. 347.

47. Ml-, p. 348; for a fuller study of Andrea Simpson's life, see PP 347- 351, 355-356, 404-405.

48. Ml-, P- 348.

49. Ibid., p. 349.

50. Ml-, pp. 350-351.

51. Ibid., p. 352.

52. Ibid., p. 351.

53. Ibid., p. 309.

54. Ibid., p. 370.

55. Ibid., pp. 371-372.

56. Arthur Waley. translated and annotated. The Analects of Confucius (London: George Allen & Unwin, 1949), p. 127, 139. See VII. 22 and IX. 5.

57. Plato, Phae

203 which "S* be reC0Verin9 knowled9s Fowler, translation. @ be r'9ht ,n callm9 th,s collection?" H.N

58- Plato, Apology, 19 b.

59. M., 29 D, 30 A, 30 D, 41 D, 42 A.

204 Chapter VII mMR^bFebC°7^986i,lpre6niKnOW ^ M°ra' HyP°Cris^" ^ NewS &

2- Ibe Christian Science Monitor. July P7 iq«7 p 21.

3. Kohlberg, Essays on Moral Development vnl i p q

205 bibliography

Basic Texts and Translations

0) The Confudan Group-

Akazuka

Dobson, W.A C.H Mgncius- A new translation arranged and annotated for the general reader. Toronto, Canada: University of Toronto Press, 1963.

FUii'S?966 fg69 ^ ^' lluQ£M^£_

Lau, DjC„ translated with an introduction. Mencius. London: Penquin Classics, 1970.

Legge, James, translated with critical and exegetical notes, prolegomena copious indexes, and dictionary of all characters. The Chinese Classics 1: Confucan Analects, The Great Learning and The Doctrine of the ’ vol. 2: Ihe Works of Mencius. Reprinted from the last editions of Oxford University Press, 3rd ed. Hong Kong: University of Honq Konq Press, 1960.

Lin, Yutang, edited and translated with notes. The Wisdom of Confucius New York: The Modern Library, 1943.

Pound, Ezra, translation and commentary. Confucius: The Great Digest - The Unwobblinq Pivot - The Analects. New York: New Directions, 1969.

Soothill, William Edward, translated. The Analects of Confucius. 2nd ed. New York: Paragon Book Reprint Corp., 1968. (First published in Shansi in 1910.)

Uchino, Kumaichiro £7$^ Moshi (Mencius). Tokyo: Meiji Shoin, 1962. ’

Waley, Arthur, translated and annotated. The Analects of Confucius. London: George Allen & Unwin Ltd., 1938.

Watson, Burton, translated. Basic Writings of Mo Tzu. Hsun Tzu. and Han Fei Tzu. New York: Columbia University Press, 1967.

206 Voshida, Kenko Shoin, 1960. ® BflDOfl i4ii_(The Analeds). Tokyo: Meiji

(2) The Platonic Group

The L°wkhCFanSnl!chl,Libr^' co",ains ,he te«s of Elattt's dialogues in 12 vols with English translation facing. Vol. 1: EuthvDhro - Anninnv - rvitn S” piaedQ - Phaedros, trans. by H.N. Fowler, 1914 (14th Imp )• vol 2* fihh|mn V ln|anQrP frans. by W.R.m! Lamb 1924 laPsmh’uSL3- HV?JS '!SynnpQsium - Gprgias, trans. by W.R.M. Lamb 1925 (7th Imp.); vol 4: Cratvlus - Parmenides - Greater Hi™;,,. . i ™.-.. ’;ans- by H.N. Fowler, 1926 (5th Imp.); vol. 5: The Renuhii^ fsoks I • V',rans- by Paul Shorey, 1930, rev. 1937 (7th Imp) vol 6^' The Thoae iCt' hSc 1 ,r3nS' by Paul Shor®y' !935 (6th Imp ); vol. 7:^ LhgaatatOS and Sophist, trans. by H.N. Fowler, 1921 (6th Imp.)- vol. 8: PlmhS?Qo»f/ShP|hlle^S’ t.rans‘ by HN- Fowler- to trans. by W.R.M. Lamb, 1925 (5th Imp.); vol. 9: Timaeus - Critias - Cleitoohon - Menexenus - Epistles, trans. by W.R.M. Lamb, 1925 (5th Imp )• vol 10* Itie Laws Books |-VI, trans. by R.G. Bury, 1926 (5th Imp.); vol. 11: The Laws^ BqqK§ VII - XII, trans. by R. G. Bury, 1926 (5th Imp.); vol. 12: pharrriicjeg - Alpibiades I and II - Hipparchus - The Lovers - Theanp^. MmOS - Epinomig, trans. by W.R.M. Lamb, 1927; rev.1955 (3rd Imp.).

Bloom, Allan, trans. with notes and an interpretation. The Republic of Platn New York: Basic Books, 1968.

Bluck, R.S., ed. with introduction and commentary. Plato’s Meno London; Cambridge University Press, 1961.

Cornford, Francis M., trans. with introduction and notes. The Republic of Plato London: Oxford University Press, 1941.

Friedlander, Paul. Plato, vols. 2 and 3. Translated by H. Meyerhoff. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1969.

Guthrie, W.K.C., trans. Plato: Protagoras and Meno. Penguin Books, 1956.

Hackforth, R., trans. with an introduction and commentary. Plato's Examination of Pleasure (The Philebus). London: Cambridge University Press, 1945.

_. trans., with an introduction and commentary. Plato’s Phaedo. Cambridge University Press, 1952.

Jowett, B., trans. into English with analyses and introductions. The Dialogues of Plato. 4th ed., 4 vols. London: Oxford University Press, 1953.

Lee, Desmond, trans., with an introduction. Plato: The Republic. 2nd. ed. rev. Penguin Books, 1974.

207 MCD°ZUrsXpre1s.1^3°,e^ Thea^' L°"d°": Oxford

Saundcrrasl!'cs05975trans' Wi,h an in,roduction' Elato; The lawrj. Penguin

B. Books and Articles

Adkins, Arthur W.H. Emm the Many to the One: A Study of Personality and p ° ^un?an Na'u^e m ,he Context of Society, Values and Beliefs. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1970.

_• Merit and Responsibility: A Study in Greek Values. Oxford- The Clarendon Press, 1960.

-— Moral V^ldg? and Political Behaviour in Ancient Greene- From Homer to the End of the Fifth Century. New York: W.W. Norton, 1972.

Baldry, H.C. “Plato's Technical Terms'," in The Classical Quartern, XXXII, 1937, 141-150.

-• Ib.e Unity of Mankind in Greek Thought. Cambridge: Cambridqe University Press, 1965.

Barker, Ernest. Greek Political Theory. New York: Barnes & Noble, 1960 (First published by Methuen in London in 1918.)

-• Political Thought of Plato and Aristotle. New York: Russell and Russell, 1959.

Barker, Robert. "Restore ethics as partner to intellect," Christian Science Monitor. 30 January 1987, B9.

Barnes, Barbara R. "Continuing the Quest for Moral Education," Independent School. May 1983, 13-18.

Barrow, Robin. Plato and Education. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1976.

Beck, F.A.G. Greek Education 450-350 B.C. New York: Barnes & Noble, 1964.

Bloom, Allan. The Closing of the American Mind. New York: Simon and Schuster, 1987.

Bowra, C.M. Periclean Athens. Penguin Books, 1974.

Burn, A.R. The Pelican History of Greece. Baltimore, MD: Penguin Books, 1966.

208 ~ConSfconquest.sV a|London:rinnrt^tqt ThamesTl0t CirPOr anda : Hudson,From Their 1968. Rise t0 ,he Roman Bury, J.D. A History nf Qtqsss. f" thf The Modern Library, 1913. I New York:

BUrnetUniv^HPrhJS4.Part '' ^ t0 Pht^ L°"d°":

BUXba: S^Prrss.P97TnPnrP Chen, Li Fu. __t ^ ^ Eflflks^ Translated from the Chineseby ShliTshin Uu.^TaipeC Taiwan- The Commercial Press, 1972. K ’ 1

Ch en, Meng-chia. "The Greatness of Chou (ca. 1027 - ca. 221 B.C.)" in China ^ ^-McNair. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press 1951 04-/1. ’

Cheng Chung-ying. Ifli Chan’s Inquiry into Goodness Honolulu- East West Center Press, University of Hawaii, 1971.

Chow Tse-tsung. Wen-lip; Studies in the Chinese Humanities. Madison, Wl: University of Wisconsin Press, 1968.

Christensen, Reo M. "Moral Education: Consensus in a Pluralistic Society " Christian Science Monitor. 14 October 1986, p. 26.

Ch'u Chai and Winberg Chai. Confucianism: The philosophy of the Chinese people; its origins and developments; its effect upon the intellectual, political and spiritual life of the Chinese. New York: Barron's Educational Series, Inc., 1973.

Cole, Robert. The Moral Life of Children. Boston: Houghton Mifflin Co., 1986.

Cornford, F.M. Before and After Socrates. London: Cambridge University Press, 1932.

Plato's Theory of Knowledge. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1935.

Creel, Herrlee G. The Birth of China: A survey of the formative period of Chinese civilization. New York: Frederick Ungar, 1963.

_. Chinese Thought from Confucius to Mao Tse-tung. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1963.

209 --KS anrl lhP rh'nprp Wny. New York, Harper and Row al^^SSSSSSat£ 'i3ffHSSf.

-• £iatO, thg Midwife's Apprentice. New York: Barnes & Noble, 1965.

Dawson^Mies M. Ih,e Ethic? pf Confugigg. New York: G.P. Putnam's Sons,

Dawson,^Raymond, ed. Ibg Legacy Qf China. London: Oxford University

Demos, Raphael. "Plato on Moral Principles," in Mind, vol. 76, 1967, 125-126. dG SoLJsa. Ronald, review of Elhics and the Limits of Philosophy by Bernard Williams, in Hie New York Times Book Review. 14 July 1985, 11-12.

Dodds, E.R. Ihe Greeks and the Irrational. Berkeley and Los Angeles- University of California Press, 1951.

Dubs, H.H. "Comparison of Greek and Chinese Philosophy," in Chinese Social and Political Science Review. 17 (1933), 307-327.

_• "Human Nature in the Teachings of Confucius," Journal of the American Oriental Society. 50 (1930), 233ff.

Eberhard, Wolfram. A History of China. Berkeley & Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1960.

_• Moral and Social Values of the Chinese: Collected Essays. Taipei, Taiwan: Ch'eng-wen Publishing Co., 1971.

Ehrenberg, Victor. From Solon to Socrates. London: Methuen & Co., 1968.

Eichhorn, Werner. Chinese Civilization: An Introduction, trans. by Janet Seligman. London: Faber and Faber, 1969.

Encyclopedia of Philosophy. New York: Macmillan & Free Press, 1967.

Fehl, Noah Edward. Li: Rites and Propriety in Literature and Life. Hong Kong: University of Hong Kong Press, 1971.

Field, G.C. The Philosophy of Plato. London: Oxford University Press, 1949. Finazz°' Giancarlo. The Principle of Tien Gallery, Ltd., 1967. * New York: Paragon Book

Fingareand ~ ThR NewYork: Harper

F|Sher, Robert T- Classical utopian Theories nf PH, rmhn New Hav CT. College & University Press, 1964. ‘

Flanagan^ OwerKT, Jr. Ihg Science gf the Mind. Cambridge. MA: The MIT

Fraenkel, Jack R. "Now is Not the Time to Set Aside Values Education." Education (February 1981): 101-107. Social

Freeman, Kenneth J. Schools Qf Hell???- (Classics in Education No. 38). New York: Teachers College Press, Columbia University, 1969.

Friedlander, Paul. Elate, vol. 1: An Introduction, trans. by H. Meyerhoff. 2nd ed. rev. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1969.

Fuller, B.A.G. History pf Greek Philosophy, vol. 2: The Sonhists Sncratpc Elate. New York: Greenwood Press, 1963. (First published in 1931 by Henry Holt & Co.)

Fung, Yu-lan. A_History of Chinese Philosophy trans. by Derk Bodde, 2 vols. Princton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1952-1953.

Gardner, Charles S. Chinese Traditional Historiography (Harvard Historical Monographs XI). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1961.

Gascoigne, Bamber. The Treasures and Dynasties of China. London: Jonathan Cape, 1973.

Geach, P. "Good and Evil," in Theories of Ethics, ed. by Philippa Foot. London: Oxford University Press, 1967.

Gibbs, John C. "Kohlberg's Stages of Moral Judgment: A Constructive Critique." Harvard Educational Review, vol. 47 no. 1 (February 1977): 43-61.

Gernet, Jacques. A History of Chinese Civilization, trans. J.R. Foster. London: Cambridge University Press, 1982.

Goodrich, L. Carrington. A Short History of Chinese People, rev. ed. New York: Harper, 1951. Goodrich, L. Carrington and H.C. Fenn A-Svllabus Of the History of Civilization anr| QltlirQ 6th ed. New York: China Society of America, 1958.

Gosling, J.C.B. Plata. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1973.

GOU'd’uJrers^PesYse'?9P5rnt ^ ^ L°nd0":

Gouldnsr, Alvin VV. Enter Plato; Classical Greens end the Origins nt Snria, IhSQry. New York: Basic Books, 1965.

Grousset Rene The Rise and Splendour of the Chinos Fmnire trans. by Anthony Watson-Gandy and Terence Gordon. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1965

Grube, G.M.A. Plato's Thought. London: Methuen & Co., 1935.

Gruber, Howard E. and Voneche, J. Jacques, eds. The Essential Pianot: An interpretive Reference and Guide. New York: Basic Books, 1977.

Guthrie, W.K.C. Socrates. London: Cambridge University Press, 1971.

Hall, R.W. "Plato's Just Man," in New Scholasticism. 43 (1968), 202-225.

Hamilton, Edith. The Greek Wav to Western Civilization. New York: W.W. Norton, 1930.

Hammond, N.G.L. A History of Greece to 322 B.C. 2nd ed. London: Oxford University Press, 1967.

Hatzfeld, Jean. History of Ancient Greece. New York: W.W. Norton, 1966.

Havelock, Eric A. Preface to Plato. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1963.

Herodotus. The History, trans. by Aubrey de Selincourt in revised with introduction and notes by A.R. Burn. Penguin Books, 1972.

Highet, Gilbert. The Classical Tradition: Greek and Roman Influence on Western Literature. New York: Oxford University Press, 1949.

Hsu, Cho-yun. Ancient China in Transition: An Analysis of Social Mobility, 722i 222 B.C. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1965.

Huby, Pamela M. Greek Ethics. New York: St. Martin's Press, 1967.

_. Plato and Modern Morality. London: Macmillan Press, 1972.

212 "“‘S> sagaaas; ss~ as**Nv * “** isr* —r^&fg&SS^S^Ssr^ Jarrett, James L. ed. MEducational Theories of the .Sophists. (Classics in

UnSy Press >1969 ^ Te8ChWS C0"ege PrSSS' Columbia

"**aSRj^?W • “Llki »«. Tokyo:

• SbyQShl (Philosophers of A Hundred Schools) Tokyo: Iwanami Shoten, 1961. '

Kaji, Nobuyuki t\V$b tfif.. Ronoo wo vnmu r%% %%t H; (Reading the Analects). Tokyo: Kodanshya, 1959. ~

Kidder, Rushworth M. "Developing 'Character' again at American Universities " Christian Science Monitor. 27 July 1987, p. 21.

Kirschenbaum, Howard. "In Support of Values Clarification." Social Education (May 1977): 398, 401-402.

Kohlberg, Lawrence. Essays on Moral Development, vol. 1: The Philosophy of Moral Development: Moral Stages and the Idea of Justice, vol. 2: The Psychology of Moral Development: The Nature and Validity of Moral Stages. San Francisco, CA: Harper and Row, 1981, 1984.

Koyre, Alexander. Discovering Plato. Trans, by Leonora Cohen Rosenfield. New York: Columbia University Press, 1945.

Laistner, M.L.W. A History of Greek World: From 479 to 323 B.C. 3rd ed. London: Methuen & Co., 1957.

Legge, James, trans. with critical and exegetical notes, prolegomena, copious indexes, and dictionary of all characters. The Chinese Classics, vol. 3: The Shoo King or The Book of History: vol. 4: The She King or the Poetry; vol. 5: The Ch'un Ts'ew. with the Tso Chuen. Hong Kong: Hong Kong University Press, 1960.

213 LeminlMarch19S81^t 205O20C7y ^ S°°ial EdUCa,i0"'” ^ Ed^on

Ll> DUn|^u^frana~-,^f9nCQ 0f Chinese Civilization New York: D. Van

Lin.Yutang. Ihe Chinese Theory of Art London, 1967.

Liu, Wu-chi. A Short History Qf Confucian Philosophy Penguin Books, 1955.

L°CkWC(MdayA1l977L): ^ Va'UeS Clarification-" Social Education

Loewe, Michael Imperial China; The historical background to the modnrn agp London: Goerge Allen & Unwin, 1966 " w

Lodge, Rupert C. Plato's Theory of Art. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul,

■ 933*

-• BlatO’s Theory of Education. New York: Russell and Russell, 1970. (First published by Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner & Co., 1947.)

Lu, Xingwei. "Moral Education in the Schools: Training the Younger Generation with Socialist Consciousness." Beiiino Review. 7 December 1981, p. 21.

_• "Socialist Decorum." Beiiing Review. 13 April 1981, p. 5.

Mabbott, J.D. "Is the Plato’s Republic Utilitarian?" in Mind. 46 (1937), 468-474.

MacNair, Harley F., ed. China. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1946.

Maeroff, Gene. "Values Regain Their Popularity," New York Times (10 April 1984), C 9-10.

Marchant, E.C. Xenophon: Memorabilia and Oeconomicus, with an English translation. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1959.

Marquand, Robert. "Moral Education: Has 'values neutrality' left students adrift?" Christian Science Monitor. 30 January 1987, B 1, 12.

_. "Revitalizing civic education: universities should play key role in fostering concern for common good," Christian Science Monitor. 28 July 1986, p. 21.

McNaughton, William. The Book of Songs. New York: Twayne Publisher, 1971.

214 -Michfga?^^^11 (Ann Arb0r PaPerbacks> University of

Medlin^Wll|arn K. Ibg His^pry

Meskill, John etai., ed. AnJntroduction to Chinese P.iviii?^^ New York: Columbia University Press, 1973.

Morohashi, Teru \\\%% Chuaokukin no Ji-e ^ iS *9 ^0 ^ (The Wisdom of the Chinese). Tokyo: Kodanshya, 1956.

Mote, Frederick W. lnlellectual Foundation nf China New York: Alfred A Knopf, 1971.

Munro Donald J. Ihg Concept of Man in Early Chinn Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1969.

Nettleship, Richard L. Ihg Theory of Education in the Republic of Platn (Classics in Education No. 36) New York: Teachers College Press Columbia University Press, 1968.

Needham, Joseph. Science and Civilisation in China, vol. 1: Introductory Qrigntation?; vol. 2: History of Scientific Thought: vol. 3: Mathematics and the Sciences of the Heavens and the Earth. London: Cambridge University Press, 1954-1959.

Northrop, F.S.C. The Meeting of East and West: An Inquiry Concerning Human Understanding. New York: Macmillan, 1946.

Nussbaum, Martha, review of The Closing of the American Mind: How Higher Education has Failed Democracy and Impoverished the Souls of Today's Students, by Allan Bloom, in The New York Review. 5 November 1987, 20-26.

O'Brien, M.J. The Socratic Paradoxes and the Greek Mind. Chapel Hill, NC: University of North Carolina Press, 1967.

Owens, David. "Music carries lessons beyond the world of word," Christian Science Monitor. 30 January 1987, B 7.

Penner, Terry. "The Unity of Virtue," in the Philosophical Review. LXXXII (1973), 35-68.

Popper, Karl R. The Open Society and Its Enemies, vol. 1: The Spell Qf Plate- Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1971.

215 purpe! David and Kevin Ryan, eds. Moral Education; it Corns* with th«, SSng Corp. ie976KaPPa Publica,ion) Berkeley. CA: McCutchan

Randa^ Jo^Hemian,^Jr.^ D^matiSI 0. th„ I Up nf R^op. New York:

Rawls, John. AJTheory Qf Justice- Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press,

R|chmond^W. Kenneth, ed. Readings in Fduoation. London: Methuen & Co.,

Ritter, Constantin. The Essence of Plato’s Philosophy Trans, by Adam Alles London: G. Allen & Unwin, 1933.

Robinson, Richard. Essays in Greek Philosophy. London: Oxford University Press, 1969. 1

Rubin, Vitaly A. Individual and State in Ancient China: Essays on Four r.hinpsp PlHQSQPhers. Trans, by Steven I. Levine. New York: Columbia University Press, 1976.

Ryle, Gilbert. The Concept of Mind. London: Hutchinson, 1949.

Sachs, David. "A Fallacy in Plato's Republic," in Philosophical Review 72 (1963), 141-158.

Saunders, T.J. "The Socratic Paradoxes in Plato's Laws," in Hermes. 96 (1968), 421-434.

Schacter, Ronald. "Justice and gender: two views of moral growth," Christian Science Monitor. 30 January 1987. B 4.

Scharfstein, Ben-Ami. The Mind of China. New York: Dell Publishing Co., 1975.

Schiller, J. "Just Man and Just Acts in Plato's Republic," in Journal of History of Philosophy, vi (1968), 1-14.

Schipper, E.W. "Mimesis in the Arts in Plato's Law," in Journal of Aesthetic and Art Criticism. 32 (1963), 199-202.

Schwartz, Benjamin I. The World of Thought in Ancient China. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1985.

Sealey, Raphael. A History of the Greek City States: ca. 7QQ-338 B.Q.. Berkeley and Los Angeles, CA: University of California Press, 1976.

216 Sh!h, v*^ent Y.C. "Metaphysical Tendencies in Mencius," in Philosophy p^ct Press! 3^9-341 N°’ 4 (January 1963)' Honolulu> HI: University of Hawaii

Sh0reyPreass;ChiC89°' 'L: U"iv°*

-- What PlfltQ Sai

Solmsen, Fredrich. ElatQ’S Theology. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, I 942.

Stanley, William B. "Indoctrination and Social Education: A Critical Analysis " Social Education (March 1981): 200,202-204.

Stoddard, Pat. "Conflicting Messages: Which Values? Taught How'?" Independent School (October 1976) 23-25.

Ssu-ma, Ch’ien. Records of the Grand Historian of China. Trans, by Burton Watson. 2 vols. New York: Columbia University Press, 1962.

Taylor, A.E. The Mind of Plato. Ann Arbor, Ml: University of Michigan Press, 1960. (First published in 1922 by Constable and Co., London.)

_• Plato: The Man and His Work. London: Methuen & Co., 1926.

_• Socrates: The Man and His Thought. New York: Doubleday & Co., 1953. (First published in 1933.)

Thang, Yung-thung. "Wang Pi’s New Interpretation of the I ching and Lun Yu," Harvard Journal of Asiatic Studies. X (1947), 124 ff.

Thucydides. The History of the Peloponnesian War. Trans, by Richard Crawley. New York: E.P. Dutton & Co., 1950.

Tracy, Theodore J. Physiological Theory and the Doctrine of the Mean in Plato and Aristotle: Studies in Philosophy XVII. The Hague, Netherlands: Mouton & Co. Printers, 1969.

Versenyi, L. Socratic Humanism. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1963.

Verwilghen, Albert Felix. Mencius: The Man and His Ideas. New York: St. John's University Press, 1967.

217 Vastos Gregory, ed. Elato; A Collection of Critical Fssawc V0| 2: Ethics Philosonhv ot Art and Religion New York: Doubleday &

-- —Atonic Studies. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1973 yoegeHn.JErio. Elala. Baton Rouge, LA: Louisiana State University Press,

W/aley.JUthu^Ihrge Wav? Ot Thought in Ardent Dhinn New York: Macmillan

Wang, Hsueh-wen Legalism and Anti-Confucianism in Manist Politics Taipei, Taiwan: Institute of International Relations, 1975.

Watson, Burton. Early Chinese Literature. New York: Columbia University Press, 1962. 1

Wei, Francis C.M. Itie Spirit of Chinese Cultnra New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1947.

Weingartner, R. "Vulgar Justice and Platonic Justice," in Philosophical and Phenomenological Research. 25 (1964/65), 248-252.

Wellman, Robert R. "The Question Posed at Charmides 165 A -166 C " in Phronesis. IX (1964), 107-113.

Whibley, Leonard, ed. A Companion to Greek Studies. 4th ed. New York: Hafner Publishing Co., 1968.

White, Nicholas. A Companion to Plato's Republic. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Co., 1979.

Wild, John. Plato's Modern Enemies and the Theory of Natural Law. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1953.

_• Plato's Theory of Man: An Introduction to the Realistic Philosophy of Culture. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1948.

Wilhelm, Richard. Confucius and Confucianism. Trans, by George H. Danton and Annina Periam Danton. New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1931.

Wright, Arthur F., ed. Confucianism and Chinese Civilization. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1959.

_. Studies in Chinese Thought. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1953.

218 Yan9, ot!"rt'£hee?9; lag'gs 'n Chinese History. (Harvard-Yenching Institute tudies, vol. IV). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1950.

Yeh’ TDh°.d0re’ J Y; .£fofiJCianism, Christianity and P.hin^ New York: Philosophical Library, 1969.

Zen, Sophia H. Chen Symposium on Chinese Culture New York: Paraqon Book Reprint Corp., 1969. (First published in Peiping, 1931.)

Zhou, "0n Spiritual Civilization," Beijing Review, vol. 24, no. 10 (March y, 19oi).

219