A Critical Examination of Tiie Death of God in Nietzsche: Pity, Revenge and Laughter G

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

A Critical Examination of Tiie Death of God in Nietzsche: Pity, Revenge and Laughter G Diálogos, 64 (1994) pp. 59--91. A CRITICAL EXAMINATION OF TIIE DEATH OF GOD IN NIETZSCHE: PITY, REVENGE AND LAUGHTER G. STEVEN NEELEY W'hen gods die> they always die severa/ kinds ofdeath .1 Nietzsche is known as the great trumpeter of the death of God. In several bold and dramatic passages, he informs us not only that God is dead, but also how His death was brought about. The reports on the ex­ act mode of death, however, are inconsistent. In several places, Nietzsche suggests that God fell victim to violence. Elsewhere, we are told that God died out of psychic trauma. A thorough examination of the various passages in whic\1 Nietzsche explicitly mentions the death of God will reveal an interesting weave of thought which has not yet been ade- · quately explored by the commentators. An investigation into this concep­ tual network will yield a richer appreciation of the death-of-God theme and will shed new light on Nietzsche's account of the emotions involved. 1 Tbe Deatb of God The stray light of a madman illuminated the most tremendous event of human history. Nietzsche's prophetic tolle Mensch of The Gay Science ran into the market place, leaped into the midst of the crowd, and pierced them with his eyes: "Whíther is God?" he cried; "I will tell you. We have kílled him-you and I. All of us are his murderers... Do we hear nothing as yet of the noise of the gravediggers who are burying God? Do we smell nothing as 1 Friedrich Nietzsche, Thus Spoke Zarathustra, i~ The Portable Nietzsche, trans., Walter Kaufmann, New York: Viking Press (1954) part 4, § 6. 59 yet of the divine decomposition? Gods, too, decompose. God is dead. Finally, there is a curious passage in Zaratbustra which suggests that God remains dead. And we have killed him." God may have died out of a psychic trauma of an entirely different sort. "How shall we comfort ourselves, the murderers of all murderers? What Nietzsche informs us that the "old gods" met with a "good gay godlike was holiest and mightiest of all that the world has yet owned has bled end": to death under our knives: who will wipe this blood off us?"2 They did not endin a 'twilight,' though this lie is told. lnstead: one day A similar tale of murder is spun by the "ug1iest man" of Zaratbustra they laugbed themselves to death. That happened when the most god­ who confesses that he murdered God out of the spirlt of revenge: less word issued from one of the gods themselves the word: 'There is one god. Thou shalt have no other god before me!' But be bad to die: he saw with eyes that saw everything; he saw man's (Nietzsche, Zarathustra., part 3, § 8) depths and ultimate grounds, all his concealed disgrace and ugliness. His pity knew no shame: he crawled into my dirtiest nooks. This most Kaufmann lists the many passages in Nietzsche in which we are ex­ curious, overobtrusive, overpitying one had to die. He always saw me: pressly told of the death of God.3 Of those passages, only those cited di­ on such a witness I wanted to ha ve revenge or not live myself. The god rectly above tell us the mode of God's death. The passages reveal that who saw everything, even man- this god had to die! Man cannot bear God may be said to have died in several different ways: He was mur­ it that such a witness should live. dered in the spirit of revenge; He died out of his pity for mankind; and (Nietzsche, Zarathustra, part 4, § 7) the "old gods" laughed themselves to death. Pity and revenge are two fundamental attitudes which play an important role in Nietzsche's Elsewhere, however, we are led to believe that God dies a less vio­ thought. Furthermore, pity and revenge are closely related attitudes in lent death. There are two passages in Zaratbustra in which God dies out the sense that pity is often a disguised forro of vengeance. Laughter is of pity. In the section aptly entitled "On The Pitying," Zarathustra con­ also an important lietmotif in Nietzsche's writing, which symbolizes, ínter fides: ''Thus spoke the devil to me once: 'God too has his hell: that is bis afia, the state of the spirit which is beyond tragedy. The primary goal of love of man.' And most recently 1 heard him say this: 'God is dead; God this paper is to ask-and hopefully, answer-the question: Why, out of a d.ied of his pity for man" (Ibid., part 2, § 3). Similarly, in the later section near infinite number of possible ways to die, did Nietzsche choose to entitled "Retired," Zarathustra asks the "old pope" if he knows how God portray the death of God through scenarios involving these particular died: "Is it true what they say, that pity strangled him, that he saw how emotions? There is considerable literature in the fi eld, and it is considered man hung on the cross and that he could not bear it, that Iove of man de riguer to at least mention the death-of-God theme in any serious work became his hell, and in the end his death?" (Ibid., part 4, § 6). Eventually, on Nietzsche. Yet none of the commentators have focused squarely on the "old pope" replies: the issue at hand. Moreover, the psychological dynamics of pity, revenge and laughter present a fertile and continuing source of interest in When he was young, this god out of the Orient, he was harsh and Nietzsche scholarship. Accordingly, a second and related goal will be to vengeful and he built himself a hell to amuse his favorites. Eventually, however, he became old and soft and mellow and pitying... Then he examine Nietzsche's thoughts on pity, revenge and laughter and to ex­ sat in his nook by the hearth, wilted, grieving over his weak legs, weary plore whatever connections they may have to the death-of-God theme. of the world, weary of willing, and one day he choked on his all-too­ great pity. (Nietzsche, Zarathustra., part 4, § 6) 2 Friedrich Nietzsche, Tbe Gay Science, trans., Walter Kaufmann, New York: Vintage 3 The list occurs in Kaufmann's translation of Tbe Gay Science, supra, note 2, p . Books 0974) part 3, § 125. 167. 60 61 verse interpretation concerning whether the will-to-power denotes 11 Pity and Revenge something empirical or is rather a hypothesis entertained on Hollingdale suggests that pity and revenge are but two of a large methodological grounds alone, but the question arises concerning the number of effects which proceed from a single cause, namely: the will­ actual scope of the will-to-power. One might ask whether the will-to­ to-power.4 Near the beginning of the AntiChrist, Nietzsche presents a power properly pertains to the entire cosmos, only to the organic series of questions and answers which represent the very core and direc­ ldngdom, or merely to the realm of human psychology. Moreover, the tion of the philosophy of power as it has been built up and refined dur­ proposed analysis of pity and revenge is complicated even further by the ing the course of his writings: notion that the two emotions appear to occur on a variety of different levels. Thus, it is possible to address individual psychological states of What is good? Everything that heightens the feeling of power in man, these attitudes, or universal ontological states of pity and revenge. 7 At the will to power, power itself. bottom, any analysis which attempts to grapple with such elusive What is bad? Everything that is born of"weakness. concepts as the will-to-power or its various complex psychological manifestations is destined to be fraught with difficulty. Yet, despite an What is happiness? The feeling that power is growing, that resistance is overcome. S inevitable margin of imprecision, such an undertaking will be of real benefit towards the recognition of certain subtle nuances in Nietzsche's The bold identification of will-to-power with goodness, coupled with writings. Thus, invoking the jurisprudential prescript of deciding only the assertion that happiness is the feeling of enhanced power, provides a those matters which are necessary for resol u tion of the immediate penetrating insight into Nietzsche's thought. Thus, we see "a large range controversy, this paper will proceed simply upon the recognition that for of effects which it is suggested proceed from a single cause: gratitude, Nietzsche, the will-to-power applies at least to the field of psychology, moral evaluations, the desire to arouse pity, humility, teasing, lave of and that pity and revenge arise out of competing drives for power. knowledge, production of works of art, philosophizing, lawgiving, the As a psychologist, Nietzsche is not satisfied with a mere description idea of justice, all taking their origin from sorne aspect of the possession of mental scenery; his main concem is with the inner dynamics of human of, or the dríve to preserve, or the desire to enhance power" nature and with the complex interplay of forces which mould thought, (Hollingdale, p. 79). In short: "Will to power' as the basic psychological character, and conduct. 8 Viewed as manifestations of the will-to-power, drive in man, of which all other human activities are sublimations is pity and revenge are closely related emotions. Nietzsche often speaks of ' Nietzsche's specific psychological 'theory"' (Ibid., p. 183). pity as being a more subtle form of revenge, and from the very begin­ But what precisely is the will-to-power? At one place Nietzsche states: ning, the analysis is complex.
Recommended publications
  • APA Newsletters
    APA Newsletters Volume 02, Number 1 Fall 2002 NEWSLETTER ON PHILOSOPHY AND THE BLACK EXPERIENCE LETTER FROM THE NEW EDITORS, JOHN MCCLENDON & GEORGE YANCY ARTICLES JOHN H. MCCLENDON III “Black and White contra Left and Right? The Dialectics of Ideological Critique in African American Studies” GEORGE YANCY “Black Women’s Experiences, Philosophy of Religion and Womanist Theology: An Introduction through Jacquelyn Grant’s Hermaneutics of Location” BOOK REVIEWS Mark David Wood: Cornel West and the Politics of Prophetic Pragmatism REVIEWED BY JOHN H. MCCLENDON III George Yancy, Ed.: Cornel West: A Critical Reader REVIEWED BY ARNOLD L. FARR © 2002 by The American Philosophical Association ISSN: 1067-9464 APA NEWSLETTER ON Philosophy and the Black Experience John McClendon & George Yancy, Co-Editors Fall 2002 Volume 02, Number 1 George Yancy’s recent groundbreaking work, Cornel West: A ETTER ROM THE EW DITORS Critical Reader. Farr particularly highlights the revolutionary L F N E historical importance of Yancy’s book. For submissions to the APA newsletter on Philosophy and the Black Experience, book reviews should be sent to George We would like to say that it is an honor to assume, as new Yancy at Duquesne University Philosophy Department, 600 editors, the helm of the APA Newsletter on Philosophy and the Forbes Avenue, Pittsburgh, PA 15282; and he can be e-mailed Black Experience. Editors Leonard Harris and Jesse Taylor have at [email protected]. Articles for submission can done a consistent job of providing us with articles and reviews be sent to John H. McClendon, Associate Professor of African that reflect the importance of philosophy vis-a-vis the Black American and American Cultural Studies, Bates College, 223 experience.
    [Show full text]
  • Interpreting the Theology of Barth in Light of Nietzsche's Dictum “God Is Dead”
    Interpreting the theology of Barth in light of Nietzsche’s dictum “God is dead” André J Groenewald Pastor: Presbyterian Church of Scotland Edinburgh, Scotland Abstract Karl Barth responded with his theology to Nietzsche’s dictum “God is dead” by stating that God is the living God. God does not need the human race to exist. God reveals God self to humankind whenever God wills. Barth agreed with Nietzsche that the god of the nineteenth century was a “Nicht-Gott”. The article aims to discus Karl Barth’s respons to Nietzsche’s impulse towards the development of a concept of God that would lead to neither atheism nor theism. The article argues that Barth paved the way for talking about God by defining God as the “communicative God”. 1. INTRODUCTION In his book, Die fröhliche Wissenschaft, originally written in 1882, Nietzsche tells about a mad man who runs around in a marketplace looking for “God” (Nietzsche 1973:159). Since he cannot find God, he can only reach one conclusion. God is dead! Nietzsche did not per se deny or affirm the existence of God. He announced the death of the god of modernity (Ward [1997] 1998:xxix; Groenewald 2005:146). He had a problem with the notion of “Fortschritt” according to which history has proven that human beings develop to greater heights of their own accord and that the potential for progress is intrinsic to humankind (Nietzsche 1969a:169; 1972: 304, 309, 310; see Jensen 2006:47, 51). “God’s existence and providence could then be proven on account of this optimistic progress in the course of history” (Groenewald 2005:146).
    [Show full text]
  • Nietzsche, Polytheism and Parody
    Bulletin de la Sociiti Amhicaine de Philosophie de Langue Franrais Volume 14} Number 2} Fall 2004 Nietzsehe, Polytheism and Parody Pierre I<lossowski Parody and polytheism in Nietzsche? At first sight, it is not at all clear what relation exists between these two terms, nor what kind oE concerns would lead one to speak oE them, nor what interest one n1ight have in raising such a question. If for most people Nietzsche's name is inseparable from the utterance God is dead, then it may seem surprising to speak of the religion of many gods with regard to Nietzsche. After all, there are countless people today for whom Nietzsche's name signifies nothing more than this utterance-and they did not need Nietzsche to know that all the gods are dead. It mayaiso seem, perhaps, that I am simply using Nietzsche to demonstrate the existence of many gods and to legitimate polytheism; and, by playing on these words, I will not escape the reproach, under the pretext of showing the meaning of parody in Nietzsche, of making a parody of myself and thus of parodying Nietzsche. If I must open myself to such confusion, I would nevertheless like to make one thing clear: insofar as one is lead to interpret the thought of a mind [eprit] that one tries to comprehend and make comprehensible, there is no one who leads his interpreter to parody him as much as Nietzsche. 82 NIETZSCHE, POLYTHEISM, AND PARODY This is true not only of those interpreters who are smitten with his thought, but also those who try hard to refute him as a dangerous spirit.
    [Show full text]
  • Thomas J.J. Altizer: on the Death of God Theology
    Obsculta Volume 7 Issue 1 Article 3 June 2014 Thomas J.J. Altizer: On the Death of God Theology Jose L. Gutierrez OSB College of Saint Benedict/Saint John's University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.csbsju.edu/obsculta Part of the Christianity Commons ISSN: 2472-2596 (print) ISSN: 2472-260X (online) Recommended Citation Gutierrez, Jose L. OSB. 2014. Thomas J.J. Altizer: On the Death of God Theology. Obsculta 7, (1) : 11-28. https://digitalcommons.csbsju.edu/obsculta/vol7/iss1/3. This Article is brought to you for free and open access by DigitalCommons@CSB/SJU. It has been accepted for inclusion in Obsculta by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@CSB/SJU. For more information, please contact [email protected]. OBSCVLTA T HOMAS J.J. A L T IZER : O N T HE D EA T H OF G O D T HEOLO G Y José L. Gutierrez, O.S.B. (1970) Note bene—This paper was submitted to the faculty of graduate studies at Saint John’s University, Collegeville, Minnesota, in partial fulfill- ment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in Theology, in 1970. Obsculta is proud to present archived scholarship in the spirit of tracing the historical continuum of Saint John’s commit- ment both to ressourcement and to the equally arduous task of being attentive to the signs of the times. Introduction—Radical theology Radical theology or “death of God” theology is a development within Protestantism, which is carry- ing the careful openness of the older theologies toward atheism a step further.
    [Show full text]
  • Lay Christian Views of Life After Death: a Qualitative Study and Theological Appraisal of the `Ordinary Eschatology' of Some Congregational Christians
    Durham E-Theses Lay Christian Views of Life After Death: A Qualitative Study and Theological Appraisal of the `Ordinary Eschatology' of Some Congregational Christians ARMSTRONG, MICHAEL,ROBERT How to cite: ARMSTRONG, MICHAEL,ROBERT (2011) Lay Christian Views of Life After Death: A Qualitative Study and Theological Appraisal of the `Ordinary Eschatology' of Some Congregational Christians, Durham theses, Durham University. Available at Durham E-Theses Online: http://etheses.dur.ac.uk/3274/ Use policy The full-text may be used and/or reproduced, and given to third parties in any format or medium, without prior permission or charge, for personal research or study, educational, or not-for-prot purposes provided that: • a full bibliographic reference is made to the original source • a link is made to the metadata record in Durham E-Theses • the full-text is not changed in any way The full-text must not be sold in any format or medium without the formal permission of the copyright holders. Please consult the full Durham E-Theses policy for further details. Academic Support Oce, Durham University, University Oce, Old Elvet, Durham DH1 3HP e-mail: [email protected] Tel: +44 0191 334 6107 http://etheses.dur.ac.uk 2 Michael Robert Armstrong Lay Christian Views of Life After Death: A Qualitative Study and Theological Appraisal of the ‘Ordinary Eschatology’ of Some Congregational Christians ABSTRACT The thesis investigates the life after death (hereafter LAD) beliefs of members of my Congregational church via in-depth semi-structured interviews. Complementary criteria of critical reflection and visible effect on behaviour are used to identify these views as „ordinary theology‟.
    [Show full text]
  • God Is Dead: the Anatomy of a Slogan [Review] / Hamilton, Kenneth
    118 SEMINARY STUDIES place: as certainly as Christ was a man, there must reside in human nature the possibility of taking up the divine into itself, just as did happen in Christ. So that the idea that the divine revelation in Christ must in this respect be something absolutely supernatural will simply not stand the test. Natural laws (but divine too, as every- thing in Nature is natural-divine) account completely for the incar- nation." Then Hamilton goes on to show how the liberal theologians who have succeeded Schleiermacher have built upon his principles and teachings. It may be that he proves too much, but the broad outline of his conclusions seems to be valid. Billings, Montana WALTERSIEMSEN Hamilton, Kenneth, God is Dead; the Anatomy of a Slogan. Grand Rapids, Mich. : William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company, I 966. 86 pp. Paperbound. $ I .25. "It is hardly surprising that the death-of-God theology has made such a stir, for, considered as a slogan, 'God is dead' is magnificient. It is short, clear, and shocking even to the non-believer." With these words Kenneth Hamilton begins his second study of the "God is dead" theology. He goes on to say that "whatever else it may represent, death-of-God theology certainly represents a challenge to, and a break with, mainstream Christianity in all its forms. Christian atheism affirms that all images of God are equally uselcss, because the concept 'God' is an empty idea for modern man. There is nothing in the experience of our generation, with its scientific understanding of the universe, which can possibly correspond to the word 'God.' " This is certainly radical thinking, but Hamilton, as he did in his earlier work, demonstrates that its antecedents go back into the distant past.
    [Show full text]
  • Abandonment of Faith Among Jewish Survivors of the Holocaust Jennifer Lassley University of Nebraska-Omaha
    International Social Science Review Volume 90 | Issue 2 Article 3 2015 A Defective Covenant: Abandonment of Faith among Jewish Survivors of the Holocaust Jennifer Lassley University of Nebraska-Omaha Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.northgeorgia.edu/issr Part of the Anthropology Commons, Communication Commons, Economics Commons, Geography Commons, International and Area Studies Commons, Political Science Commons, and the Public Affairs, Public Policy and Public Administration Commons Recommended Citation Lassley, Jennifer (2015) "A Defective Covenant: Abandonment of Faith among Jewish Survivors of the Holocaust," International Social Science Review: Vol. 90: Iss. 2, Article 3. Available at: http://digitalcommons.northgeorgia.edu/issr/vol90/iss2/3 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Nighthawks Open Institutional Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in International Social Science Review by an authorized administrator of Nighthawks Open Institutional Repository. A Defective Covenant: Abandonment of Faith among Jewish Survivors of the Holocaust Cover Page Footnote Jennifer Lassley is a graduate student in the history department at the University of Nebraska-Omaha. This article is available in International Social Science Review: http://digitalcommons.northgeorgia.edu/issr/vol90/iss2/3 Lassley: A Defective Covenant A Defective Covenant: Abandonment of Faith among Jewish Survivors of the Holocaust Wenn es einen Gott gibt muß er mich um Verzeihung bitten. – Unknown The phrase above was carved into the prison cell walls of the Mauthausen concentration camp in Austria. Although the authorship is unknown, this prisoner’s words hold considerable weight. In English, the phrase translates to “If there is a God, He will have to beg my forgiveness.”1 Religious victims of the Holocaust were confronted with the ultimate test of faith.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter One Is Heaven a Place We Can Get To?
    Copyrighted Material Chapter One Is Heaven a Place We Can Get To? Having shaken off the yoke of being chair of the department (aft er seven years) it is a great honor to be invited by my colleagues to give these lectures. It is also a particular delight. For this lecture series celebrates the memory of our wonderful former colleague, Carl Gustav “Peter” Hempel. Like all those who knew him, I remember Peter as a very good and kind man. To mention just one small kindness—a single example among so many—one Princeton summer, long ago, Peter off ered his magnifi ­ cent office in McCosh to my then fellow graduate student Alison Mc­ Intyre and me, with the encouragement that we look into his library. It provided a great education in the long history of positivism, especially in the often unnoticed practical idealism of that movement, which ap­ peared so forcefully in the many early pamphlets associated with its for­ mation, pamphlets that Peter still kept on hand. One of those pamphlets contained a partial translation of August Comte’s Système de politique positive, in which I found an idea that I shall return to in the last lecture. I wonder what Peter would have made of it. So now to begin on the lectures, I should say that I am very conscious of the awkwardness of my topic. To speak in this kind of academic con­ text about whether we survive death is widely regarded as a form of bad Many people have made enormously helpful comments on these lectures.
    [Show full text]
  • A Mennonite-Feminist Exploration of Dorothee Sölle and J. Denny Weaver on Nonviolence, Atonement, and Redemption
    Making Peace with the Cross: A Mennonite-Feminist Exploration of Dorothee Sölle and J. Denny Weaver on Nonviolence, Atonement, and Redemption by Margreta Susanne Guenther Loewen A Thesis submitted to the Faculty of Emmanuel College and the Department of Theology of the Toronto School of Theology In partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Theology awarded by the University of St. Michael’s College © Copyright by Margreta Susanne Guenther Loewen 2016 Making Peace with the Cross: A Mennonite-Feminist Exploration of Dorothee Sölle and J. Denny Weaver on Nonviolence, Atonement, and Redemption Margreta Susanne Guenther Loewen Doctor of Philosophy in Theology University of St. Michael’s College 2016 Abstract This thesis brings German liberationist-feminist theologian Dorothee Sölle and American Anabaptist-Mennonite peace theologian J. Denny Weaver into conversation as a way of addressing two significant debates within contemporary theology – namely, the debate among feminists and womanists asking whether the cross can be redemptive for women and other historically marginalized groups and the debate among Anabaptist-Mennonite and other peace-oriented theologians asking whether God is nonviolent. I take the position that by holding Sölle’s more Abelardian emphasis on the cross as divine solidarity with the oppressed together with Weaver’s “narrative Christus Victor” understanding of Jesus’ resurrection as nonviolent divine victory over evil, both debates can be addressed. I therefore synthesize their views into an integrated Mennonite-feminist theology of the cross and redemption which neither reifies violence nor all forms of suffering as redemptive. The first two chapters provide context for the conversation between Sölle and Weaver.
    [Show full text]
  • Is God Dead? It Is a Question That Tantalizes Both Believers, Who Perhaps Secretly Fear That He Is, and Atheists, Who Possibly Suspect That the Answer Is No
    Friday, Apr. 08, 1966 THEOLOGY Toward a Hidden God Is God dead? It is a question that tantalizes both believers, who perhaps secretly fear that he is, and atheists, who possibly suspect that the answer is no. Is God dead? The three words represent a summons to reflect on the meaning of existence. No longer is the question the taunting jest of skeptics for whom unbelief is the test of wisdom and for whom Nietzsche is the prophet who gave the right answer a century ago. Even within Christianity, now confidently renewing itself in spirit as well as form, a small band of radical theologians has seriously argued that the churches must accept the fact of God's death, and get along without him. How does the issue differ from the age-old assertion that God does not and never did exist? Nietzsche's thesis was that striving, self-centered man had killed God, and that settled that. The current death-of-God group* believes that God is indeed absolutely dead, but proposes to carry on and write a theology without theos, without God. Less radical Christian thinkers hold that at the very least God in the image of man, God sitting in heaven, is dead, and—in the central task of religion today—they seek to imagine and define a God who can touch men's emotions and engage men's minds. If nothing else, the Christian atheists are waking the churches to the brutal reality that the basic premise of faith—the existence of a personal God, who created the world and sustains it with his love—is now subject to profound attack.
    [Show full text]
  • Feminism and the Deconstruction of God's Death Victoria Barker
    Feminism and the Deconstruction of God's Death Victoria Barker 1. Introduction: Feminism and the Death of God The relationship between feminism and postmodernism is not always an easy one. A range of criticisms has been levelled by feminists against this most slippery of discourses, targeting its apparent tendency to relativism, to apoliticism and, most importantly, its apparently refusal of 'woman' as a well-constituted political identity. These criticisms have, in turn, been ably addressed by feminists identifying themselves with the work of Jacques Derrida, Michel Foucault, Gilles Deleuze and others. 1 There is one criticism, however, which still seems rather telling. It is raised by Rosi Braidotti, among others. In her Patterns of Dissonance, Braidotti ponders why it is that the so-called death of the subject should become a philosophical necessity at precisely that point in our history when women should at last be demanding - and to some extent achieving - the status of full subjecthood within our political, economic, philosophical and other theoretical agenda.2 As women gain independence, autonomy, and the capacity for self­ definition, why are these qualities no longer deemed to support a claim to subjective identity? It is a mundane reality that the status of a community or profession is commonly downgraded as women gain increasing access to it; is the same tawdry operation occurring here at the theoretical level? Since this issue was first raised, it has often occurred to me that a parallel argument could be made out concerning the death of God. Is it happenchance that the death of God should have occurred at that moment when women are at last demanding - and to some extent achieving - the status of full subjecthood in relation to God? During this century, women have come to assume those qualities that were hitherto accorded to man in his relation to God: freedom, self-knowledge, and ethical and spiritual responsibility.
    [Show full text]
  • Phil 2303 Intro to Worldviews Philosophy Department Dallas Baptist University Dr
    Phil 2303 Intro to Worldviews Philosophy Department Dallas Baptist University Dr. David Naugle More on Naturalism: Naturalism, Atheism, Materialism, Humanism, Secularism I. Introduction Definitions and distinctions: Naturalism: In recent usage, naturalism is a specie of philosophical monism according to which whatever exists or happens is natural and can be explained, as modeled in the natural sciences, by means of the scientific method. Naturalism is a methodological monism rather than an ontological monism and as such repudiates the view that there exists any entity or event which lie beyond the scope of scientific explanation. Technically, naturalism is not to be confused with materialism or atheism and thus it leaves room for a variety of ontologies including dualism, idealism, materialism, atheism, theism. Here are a few of the leading propositions of naturalism. a. The entire knowable universe is composed of natural objects—objects that come into and pass out of existence as a result of natural causes. b. A natural cause is a natural object or episode in the history of a natural object which brings about a change in some other natural object. A natural process is any change in a natural object or system of natural objects which is due to a natural cause or system of natural causes. c. The natural method is (1) explaining natural processes through the identification of the natural causes responsible for them and (2) testing any given explanation with regard to consequences that must hold if it is true. d. Nature is intelligible based on the fact that natural processes are regular and predictable and hence knowable.
    [Show full text]