Nietzsche, Polytheism and Parody

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Nietzsche, Polytheism and Parody Bulletin de la Sociiti Amhicaine de Philosophie de Langue Franrais Volume 14} Number 2} Fall 2004 Nietzsehe, Polytheism and Parody Pierre I<lossowski Parody and polytheism in Nietzsche? At first sight, it is not at all clear what relation exists between these two terms, nor what kind oE concerns would lead one to speak oE them, nor what interest one n1ight have in raising such a question. If for most people Nietzsche's name is inseparable from the utterance God is dead, then it may seem surprising to speak of the religion of many gods with regard to Nietzsche. After all, there are countless people today for whom Nietzsche's name signifies nothing more than this utterance-and they did not need Nietzsche to know that all the gods are dead. It mayaiso seem, perhaps, that I am simply using Nietzsche to demonstrate the existence of many gods and to legitimate polytheism; and, by playing on these words, I will not escape the reproach, under the pretext of showing the meaning of parody in Nietzsche, of making a parody of myself and thus of parodying Nietzsche. If I must open myself to such confusion, I would nevertheless like to make one thing clear: insofar as one is lead to interpret the thought of a mind [eprit] that one tries to comprehend and make comprehensible, there is no one who leads his interpreter to parody him as much as Nietzsche. 82 NIETZSCHE, POLYTHEISM, AND PARODY This is true not only of those interpreters who are smitten with his thought, but also those who try hard to refute him as a dangerous spirit. Nietzsche himself urged one of his first interpreters-no one had yet spoken of hirn-to abandon all pathos, not to take sides in his favor, and to put up a sort of ironic resistance when characterizing him. Here, then, we cannot avoid being the victim of a sort of ruse, nor can we avoid falling into the trap inherent in Nietzsche's own experience and thought. Unless we simply undertake the work of the historian, as Andler did,l the moment we try to elucidate Nietzsche's thought, he is always made to say more than he says and less than he says. This is not-as is often the case with other thinkers--due to a simple lack of perspective or even because a determinate point of departure has been omitted. In assimilating Nietzsche, we make him say more than he says, while in rejecting or altering him, we make rum say less than he says-for the simple reason that, properly speaking, with Nietzsche there is hardly either a point of departure or a precise terminus. Nietzsche's contemporaries and friends were able to follow an evolution from The Birth of Tragedy to The Wanderer and His Shadow and on to The Gqy Science) and from Zarathustra to The Twilight of the Idols. But those of us who have at our disposal the youthful writings as weil as the posthumous work, includingEcce Homo, have not only been able to follow the ramifications of Nietzsche's posterity, and to witness the accusations made against Nietzsche as a result of recent historical upheavals, but have also been able to discern something which, I think, is not without importance: Nietzsche, who was despite everything a professor of philology at Basel, and thus an academic with absolutely certain pedagogical ambitions, did not develop a philosophy. Instead, outside of the framework of the university, Nietzsche developed variations on a personal then1e. Living a simple life marked by extreme suffering and convalescence, forced to sojourn with increasing frequency at health resorts, while in the midst of the greatest intellectual isolation, Nietzsche was thereby abandoned, in the most 83 PIERRE I<LOSSOWSI<I auspicious manner, to listen to himself alone [d sa seule audition]. This academic, trained in the disciplines of science in order to teach and train others, found himself compeiled to teach the unteachable. What is unteachable are those moments when existence, escaping from the delimitations that produce the notions of history and morality, as weil as the practical behavior derived from them, is shown to be given back to itself with no other goal than that of returning to itself. All things then appear at once new and quite old; everything is possible and everything is immediately impossible; and there are only two courses open to consciousness: either to keep silent, or to speak; either to do nothing, or to act so as to imprint on one's everyday quotidian ambiance the character of existence given back to itself; either to lose itself in existence or to reproduce it. Nietzsche had immediately attained this unteachable in his own solitude, through his own idiosyncrasies-that is, by descnbing himse!f as a convalescent who had suffered from the unresolvecl nihilism of his own era and who had resolved this nihilism, to the point where he was able to restore to the notion offatum its fuil force. He had grasped the very ground of existence, lived as fortuitous-that is, he had grasped that aspect of existence which, through hirn, was fortuitously named Nietzsche. In this way, he had also grasped the necessity of accepting this fortuitous situation as his own destiny (in the sense he ascribes to this word), which amounts to a decision to affirm the existence of a universe that has no other end than that of being what it iso Nietzsche recognized this apprehension of existence-which is nothing other than the apprehension of eternity-in the simulacra of art and religion, but he also saw that this n10de of apprehension is perpetually denied by scientific activity, which explores existence through its tangible forms in order to construct a practicable and livable world. Nonetheless, Nietzsche feIt a solidarity with both these attitudes toward existence: that of simulacra, as weil as that of science, which declares fiat ventas pereat vita. 2 84 NIETZSCHE, POLYTHEISM, AND PARODY Andso heputsimulacra into seienee and saenee into simulacra: in sueh a wqy that the seientist ean sqy: ''Qualis artifexpereo!'3 Nietzsehe was prey to an inelucidable revelation of existence that did not know how to express itself except through song and image. A struggle was being waged within him between the poet and the scholar, between the visionary and the moralist, each of which was trying to disqualify the role of the other. This struggle was provoked by a feeling of moral responsibility toward his contemporaries. The different tendencies, the different attitudes that were fighting over Nietzsche's consciousness would endure until a crucial event was produced: Nietzsehe would be externalized in a character, a veritable dramatis persona: Zarathustra-a character who is not only the product of a fictive redoubling, but is in some way achallenge by Nietzsehe the visionary to Nietzsehe the professor and man of letters. The character of Zarathustra has a complex function: on the one hand, he is the Christ, as Nietzsehe secretly and jealously understands him; but on the other hand, insofar as he is the Accuser of the traditional Christ, he is the one who prepares the way for the advent of Dionysus philosophos. The years during which Thus Spoke Zarathustra was fashioned, and especially those that followed its birth, were for Nietzsehe astate of unparalleled distress: One pays dearly for immortality: one has to die several times while still alive. There is something that I call the rancor of what is great: everything great-a work, a deed-is no sooner accomplished than it turns against the man who clid it. By doing it, he has become weak; he no longer endures his deed, he can no longer face it. Something one was never permitted to will lies behind one, something in which the knot in the destiny of humanity is tied-and now one labors under itI-It almost crushes one... 4 85 PIERRE KLOSSOWSI<I Zarathustra, to be sure, was latent in the previous works, but what is important for Nietzsche's life is not only the creation and presence of the ineffable songs ofthe poem. What came to be determinant for Nietzsche's life was the more or less complete identification of Nietzsche with this physiognorny, which for him constituted a kind of promise, a resurrection, an ascension. In a certain sense, Zarathustra is the star of which Nietzsche hirnself is only the satellite. Even better, I would say that Nietzsche, after having paved the way for the triumph of Zarathustra, remains behind in a position sacrificed in the course of a victorious retreat. As he hirnself said, he would pay dearly for this creation. Zarathustra prefigures Nietzsche's own immortality-that immortality by which one dies more than once while still alive. When Nietzsche managed to separate Zarathustra from hirnself, and was therebyable to encounter him as a superior but still inaccessible reality, then the world of appearances-which, according to the divine fable, was created in six days-disappeared along with the true world; for in six days the true world became a fable once again. Nietzsche casts a retrospective glance at this re-fabulation of the true world that disappears in six days, or six periods, which are the inverse of the six days of the world's creation. It is this re-fabulation that he traces out in an aphorism of The Twilight of the Idols entitled "How the True World' Final!J Became a Fable." Here is the passage: 1. The true world-attainable for the sage, the pious, the virtuous man; he lives in it, he is it.
Recommended publications
  • APA Newsletters
    APA Newsletters Volume 02, Number 1 Fall 2002 NEWSLETTER ON PHILOSOPHY AND THE BLACK EXPERIENCE LETTER FROM THE NEW EDITORS, JOHN MCCLENDON & GEORGE YANCY ARTICLES JOHN H. MCCLENDON III “Black and White contra Left and Right? The Dialectics of Ideological Critique in African American Studies” GEORGE YANCY “Black Women’s Experiences, Philosophy of Religion and Womanist Theology: An Introduction through Jacquelyn Grant’s Hermaneutics of Location” BOOK REVIEWS Mark David Wood: Cornel West and the Politics of Prophetic Pragmatism REVIEWED BY JOHN H. MCCLENDON III George Yancy, Ed.: Cornel West: A Critical Reader REVIEWED BY ARNOLD L. FARR © 2002 by The American Philosophical Association ISSN: 1067-9464 APA NEWSLETTER ON Philosophy and the Black Experience John McClendon & George Yancy, Co-Editors Fall 2002 Volume 02, Number 1 George Yancy’s recent groundbreaking work, Cornel West: A ETTER ROM THE EW DITORS Critical Reader. Farr particularly highlights the revolutionary L F N E historical importance of Yancy’s book. For submissions to the APA newsletter on Philosophy and the Black Experience, book reviews should be sent to George We would like to say that it is an honor to assume, as new Yancy at Duquesne University Philosophy Department, 600 editors, the helm of the APA Newsletter on Philosophy and the Forbes Avenue, Pittsburgh, PA 15282; and he can be e-mailed Black Experience. Editors Leonard Harris and Jesse Taylor have at [email protected]. Articles for submission can done a consistent job of providing us with articles and reviews be sent to John H. McClendon, Associate Professor of African that reflect the importance of philosophy vis-a-vis the Black American and American Cultural Studies, Bates College, 223 experience.
    [Show full text]
  • Interpreting the Theology of Barth in Light of Nietzsche's Dictum “God Is Dead”
    Interpreting the theology of Barth in light of Nietzsche’s dictum “God is dead” André J Groenewald Pastor: Presbyterian Church of Scotland Edinburgh, Scotland Abstract Karl Barth responded with his theology to Nietzsche’s dictum “God is dead” by stating that God is the living God. God does not need the human race to exist. God reveals God self to humankind whenever God wills. Barth agreed with Nietzsche that the god of the nineteenth century was a “Nicht-Gott”. The article aims to discus Karl Barth’s respons to Nietzsche’s impulse towards the development of a concept of God that would lead to neither atheism nor theism. The article argues that Barth paved the way for talking about God by defining God as the “communicative God”. 1. INTRODUCTION In his book, Die fröhliche Wissenschaft, originally written in 1882, Nietzsche tells about a mad man who runs around in a marketplace looking for “God” (Nietzsche 1973:159). Since he cannot find God, he can only reach one conclusion. God is dead! Nietzsche did not per se deny or affirm the existence of God. He announced the death of the god of modernity (Ward [1997] 1998:xxix; Groenewald 2005:146). He had a problem with the notion of “Fortschritt” according to which history has proven that human beings develop to greater heights of their own accord and that the potential for progress is intrinsic to humankind (Nietzsche 1969a:169; 1972: 304, 309, 310; see Jensen 2006:47, 51). “God’s existence and providence could then be proven on account of this optimistic progress in the course of history” (Groenewald 2005:146).
    [Show full text]
  • Thomas J.J. Altizer: on the Death of God Theology
    Obsculta Volume 7 Issue 1 Article 3 June 2014 Thomas J.J. Altizer: On the Death of God Theology Jose L. Gutierrez OSB College of Saint Benedict/Saint John's University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.csbsju.edu/obsculta Part of the Christianity Commons ISSN: 2472-2596 (print) ISSN: 2472-260X (online) Recommended Citation Gutierrez, Jose L. OSB. 2014. Thomas J.J. Altizer: On the Death of God Theology. Obsculta 7, (1) : 11-28. https://digitalcommons.csbsju.edu/obsculta/vol7/iss1/3. This Article is brought to you for free and open access by DigitalCommons@CSB/SJU. It has been accepted for inclusion in Obsculta by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@CSB/SJU. For more information, please contact [email protected]. OBSCVLTA T HOMAS J.J. A L T IZER : O N T HE D EA T H OF G O D T HEOLO G Y José L. Gutierrez, O.S.B. (1970) Note bene—This paper was submitted to the faculty of graduate studies at Saint John’s University, Collegeville, Minnesota, in partial fulfill- ment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in Theology, in 1970. Obsculta is proud to present archived scholarship in the spirit of tracing the historical continuum of Saint John’s commit- ment both to ressourcement and to the equally arduous task of being attentive to the signs of the times. Introduction—Radical theology Radical theology or “death of God” theology is a development within Protestantism, which is carry- ing the careful openness of the older theologies toward atheism a step further.
    [Show full text]
  • Lay Christian Views of Life After Death: a Qualitative Study and Theological Appraisal of the `Ordinary Eschatology' of Some Congregational Christians
    Durham E-Theses Lay Christian Views of Life After Death: A Qualitative Study and Theological Appraisal of the `Ordinary Eschatology' of Some Congregational Christians ARMSTRONG, MICHAEL,ROBERT How to cite: ARMSTRONG, MICHAEL,ROBERT (2011) Lay Christian Views of Life After Death: A Qualitative Study and Theological Appraisal of the `Ordinary Eschatology' of Some Congregational Christians, Durham theses, Durham University. Available at Durham E-Theses Online: http://etheses.dur.ac.uk/3274/ Use policy The full-text may be used and/or reproduced, and given to third parties in any format or medium, without prior permission or charge, for personal research or study, educational, or not-for-prot purposes provided that: • a full bibliographic reference is made to the original source • a link is made to the metadata record in Durham E-Theses • the full-text is not changed in any way The full-text must not be sold in any format or medium without the formal permission of the copyright holders. Please consult the full Durham E-Theses policy for further details. Academic Support Oce, Durham University, University Oce, Old Elvet, Durham DH1 3HP e-mail: [email protected] Tel: +44 0191 334 6107 http://etheses.dur.ac.uk 2 Michael Robert Armstrong Lay Christian Views of Life After Death: A Qualitative Study and Theological Appraisal of the ‘Ordinary Eschatology’ of Some Congregational Christians ABSTRACT The thesis investigates the life after death (hereafter LAD) beliefs of members of my Congregational church via in-depth semi-structured interviews. Complementary criteria of critical reflection and visible effect on behaviour are used to identify these views as „ordinary theology‟.
    [Show full text]
  • God Is Dead: the Anatomy of a Slogan [Review] / Hamilton, Kenneth
    118 SEMINARY STUDIES place: as certainly as Christ was a man, there must reside in human nature the possibility of taking up the divine into itself, just as did happen in Christ. So that the idea that the divine revelation in Christ must in this respect be something absolutely supernatural will simply not stand the test. Natural laws (but divine too, as every- thing in Nature is natural-divine) account completely for the incar- nation." Then Hamilton goes on to show how the liberal theologians who have succeeded Schleiermacher have built upon his principles and teachings. It may be that he proves too much, but the broad outline of his conclusions seems to be valid. Billings, Montana WALTERSIEMSEN Hamilton, Kenneth, God is Dead; the Anatomy of a Slogan. Grand Rapids, Mich. : William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company, I 966. 86 pp. Paperbound. $ I .25. "It is hardly surprising that the death-of-God theology has made such a stir, for, considered as a slogan, 'God is dead' is magnificient. It is short, clear, and shocking even to the non-believer." With these words Kenneth Hamilton begins his second study of the "God is dead" theology. He goes on to say that "whatever else it may represent, death-of-God theology certainly represents a challenge to, and a break with, mainstream Christianity in all its forms. Christian atheism affirms that all images of God are equally uselcss, because the concept 'God' is an empty idea for modern man. There is nothing in the experience of our generation, with its scientific understanding of the universe, which can possibly correspond to the word 'God.' " This is certainly radical thinking, but Hamilton, as he did in his earlier work, demonstrates that its antecedents go back into the distant past.
    [Show full text]
  • Abandonment of Faith Among Jewish Survivors of the Holocaust Jennifer Lassley University of Nebraska-Omaha
    International Social Science Review Volume 90 | Issue 2 Article 3 2015 A Defective Covenant: Abandonment of Faith among Jewish Survivors of the Holocaust Jennifer Lassley University of Nebraska-Omaha Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.northgeorgia.edu/issr Part of the Anthropology Commons, Communication Commons, Economics Commons, Geography Commons, International and Area Studies Commons, Political Science Commons, and the Public Affairs, Public Policy and Public Administration Commons Recommended Citation Lassley, Jennifer (2015) "A Defective Covenant: Abandonment of Faith among Jewish Survivors of the Holocaust," International Social Science Review: Vol. 90: Iss. 2, Article 3. Available at: http://digitalcommons.northgeorgia.edu/issr/vol90/iss2/3 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Nighthawks Open Institutional Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in International Social Science Review by an authorized administrator of Nighthawks Open Institutional Repository. A Defective Covenant: Abandonment of Faith among Jewish Survivors of the Holocaust Cover Page Footnote Jennifer Lassley is a graduate student in the history department at the University of Nebraska-Omaha. This article is available in International Social Science Review: http://digitalcommons.northgeorgia.edu/issr/vol90/iss2/3 Lassley: A Defective Covenant A Defective Covenant: Abandonment of Faith among Jewish Survivors of the Holocaust Wenn es einen Gott gibt muß er mich um Verzeihung bitten. – Unknown The phrase above was carved into the prison cell walls of the Mauthausen concentration camp in Austria. Although the authorship is unknown, this prisoner’s words hold considerable weight. In English, the phrase translates to “If there is a God, He will have to beg my forgiveness.”1 Religious victims of the Holocaust were confronted with the ultimate test of faith.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter One Is Heaven a Place We Can Get To?
    Copyrighted Material Chapter One Is Heaven a Place We Can Get To? Having shaken off the yoke of being chair of the department (aft er seven years) it is a great honor to be invited by my colleagues to give these lectures. It is also a particular delight. For this lecture series celebrates the memory of our wonderful former colleague, Carl Gustav “Peter” Hempel. Like all those who knew him, I remember Peter as a very good and kind man. To mention just one small kindness—a single example among so many—one Princeton summer, long ago, Peter off ered his magnifi ­ cent office in McCosh to my then fellow graduate student Alison Mc­ Intyre and me, with the encouragement that we look into his library. It provided a great education in the long history of positivism, especially in the often unnoticed practical idealism of that movement, which ap­ peared so forcefully in the many early pamphlets associated with its for­ mation, pamphlets that Peter still kept on hand. One of those pamphlets contained a partial translation of August Comte’s Système de politique positive, in which I found an idea that I shall return to in the last lecture. I wonder what Peter would have made of it. So now to begin on the lectures, I should say that I am very conscious of the awkwardness of my topic. To speak in this kind of academic con­ text about whether we survive death is widely regarded as a form of bad Many people have made enormously helpful comments on these lectures.
    [Show full text]
  • A Mennonite-Feminist Exploration of Dorothee Sölle and J. Denny Weaver on Nonviolence, Atonement, and Redemption
    Making Peace with the Cross: A Mennonite-Feminist Exploration of Dorothee Sölle and J. Denny Weaver on Nonviolence, Atonement, and Redemption by Margreta Susanne Guenther Loewen A Thesis submitted to the Faculty of Emmanuel College and the Department of Theology of the Toronto School of Theology In partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Theology awarded by the University of St. Michael’s College © Copyright by Margreta Susanne Guenther Loewen 2016 Making Peace with the Cross: A Mennonite-Feminist Exploration of Dorothee Sölle and J. Denny Weaver on Nonviolence, Atonement, and Redemption Margreta Susanne Guenther Loewen Doctor of Philosophy in Theology University of St. Michael’s College 2016 Abstract This thesis brings German liberationist-feminist theologian Dorothee Sölle and American Anabaptist-Mennonite peace theologian J. Denny Weaver into conversation as a way of addressing two significant debates within contemporary theology – namely, the debate among feminists and womanists asking whether the cross can be redemptive for women and other historically marginalized groups and the debate among Anabaptist-Mennonite and other peace-oriented theologians asking whether God is nonviolent. I take the position that by holding Sölle’s more Abelardian emphasis on the cross as divine solidarity with the oppressed together with Weaver’s “narrative Christus Victor” understanding of Jesus’ resurrection as nonviolent divine victory over evil, both debates can be addressed. I therefore synthesize their views into an integrated Mennonite-feminist theology of the cross and redemption which neither reifies violence nor all forms of suffering as redemptive. The first two chapters provide context for the conversation between Sölle and Weaver.
    [Show full text]
  • Is God Dead? It Is a Question That Tantalizes Both Believers, Who Perhaps Secretly Fear That He Is, and Atheists, Who Possibly Suspect That the Answer Is No
    Friday, Apr. 08, 1966 THEOLOGY Toward a Hidden God Is God dead? It is a question that tantalizes both believers, who perhaps secretly fear that he is, and atheists, who possibly suspect that the answer is no. Is God dead? The three words represent a summons to reflect on the meaning of existence. No longer is the question the taunting jest of skeptics for whom unbelief is the test of wisdom and for whom Nietzsche is the prophet who gave the right answer a century ago. Even within Christianity, now confidently renewing itself in spirit as well as form, a small band of radical theologians has seriously argued that the churches must accept the fact of God's death, and get along without him. How does the issue differ from the age-old assertion that God does not and never did exist? Nietzsche's thesis was that striving, self-centered man had killed God, and that settled that. The current death-of-God group* believes that God is indeed absolutely dead, but proposes to carry on and write a theology without theos, without God. Less radical Christian thinkers hold that at the very least God in the image of man, God sitting in heaven, is dead, and—in the central task of religion today—they seek to imagine and define a God who can touch men's emotions and engage men's minds. If nothing else, the Christian atheists are waking the churches to the brutal reality that the basic premise of faith—the existence of a personal God, who created the world and sustains it with his love—is now subject to profound attack.
    [Show full text]
  • Feminism and the Deconstruction of God's Death Victoria Barker
    Feminism and the Deconstruction of God's Death Victoria Barker 1. Introduction: Feminism and the Death of God The relationship between feminism and postmodernism is not always an easy one. A range of criticisms has been levelled by feminists against this most slippery of discourses, targeting its apparent tendency to relativism, to apoliticism and, most importantly, its apparently refusal of 'woman' as a well-constituted political identity. These criticisms have, in turn, been ably addressed by feminists identifying themselves with the work of Jacques Derrida, Michel Foucault, Gilles Deleuze and others. 1 There is one criticism, however, which still seems rather telling. It is raised by Rosi Braidotti, among others. In her Patterns of Dissonance, Braidotti ponders why it is that the so-called death of the subject should become a philosophical necessity at precisely that point in our history when women should at last be demanding - and to some extent achieving - the status of full subjecthood within our political, economic, philosophical and other theoretical agenda.2 As women gain independence, autonomy, and the capacity for self­ definition, why are these qualities no longer deemed to support a claim to subjective identity? It is a mundane reality that the status of a community or profession is commonly downgraded as women gain increasing access to it; is the same tawdry operation occurring here at the theoretical level? Since this issue was first raised, it has often occurred to me that a parallel argument could be made out concerning the death of God. Is it happenchance that the death of God should have occurred at that moment when women are at last demanding - and to some extent achieving - the status of full subjecthood in relation to God? During this century, women have come to assume those qualities that were hitherto accorded to man in his relation to God: freedom, self-knowledge, and ethical and spiritual responsibility.
    [Show full text]
  • Phil 2303 Intro to Worldviews Philosophy Department Dallas Baptist University Dr
    Phil 2303 Intro to Worldviews Philosophy Department Dallas Baptist University Dr. David Naugle More on Naturalism: Naturalism, Atheism, Materialism, Humanism, Secularism I. Introduction Definitions and distinctions: Naturalism: In recent usage, naturalism is a specie of philosophical monism according to which whatever exists or happens is natural and can be explained, as modeled in the natural sciences, by means of the scientific method. Naturalism is a methodological monism rather than an ontological monism and as such repudiates the view that there exists any entity or event which lie beyond the scope of scientific explanation. Technically, naturalism is not to be confused with materialism or atheism and thus it leaves room for a variety of ontologies including dualism, idealism, materialism, atheism, theism. Here are a few of the leading propositions of naturalism. a. The entire knowable universe is composed of natural objects—objects that come into and pass out of existence as a result of natural causes. b. A natural cause is a natural object or episode in the history of a natural object which brings about a change in some other natural object. A natural process is any change in a natural object or system of natural objects which is due to a natural cause or system of natural causes. c. The natural method is (1) explaining natural processes through the identification of the natural causes responsible for them and (2) testing any given explanation with regard to consequences that must hold if it is true. d. Nature is intelligible based on the fact that natural processes are regular and predictable and hence knowable.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 the DEATH of GOD and the DEATH of MORALITY Brian Leiter
    THE DEATH OF GOD AND THE DEATH OF MORALITY Brian Leiter [email protected] draft of February 15, 2016 please do not cite or quote without permission A popular conceit in recent Anglophone philosophy, familiar from the writings of Derek Parfit and Peter Singer in particular, is that until philosophical ethics frees itself from “religion,” it will not be able to make progress. Parfit and Singer think of themselves as vanguards in this movement, a claim rich in irony for any student of Nietzsche.1 For Parfit and Singer both, though in slightly different ways, treat everyone’s sentience and suffering as of decisive moral importance,2 aligning themselves firmly with the egalitarian moral thinking central to Christianity. To be sure, Parfit and Singer detach themselves from certain sectarian doctrines of, say, the Catholic Church (Singer, for example, is happy to see infants and the disabled killed under the right circumstances), but their basic moral outlook is Christian to its core, as any Nietzschean would notice.3 1As Nietzsche quips (thinking of George Eliot, not Parfit or Singer obviously, but apparently the habit is of longstanding with Anglophone writers): “When the English actually believe that they know ‘intuitively’ what is good and evil, when they therefore suppose that they no longer require Christianity as the guarantee of morality, we merely witness the effects of the dominion of the Christian value judgment and an expression of the strength and depth of this dominion….” (TI “Skirmishes”: 5). I return to this important passage later. 2Indeed, Singer takes it clearly a step further: every creature’s sentience and suffering counts the same.
    [Show full text]