1 Introduction 2 Speech Act Theory: Examining Language at the Utterance Level

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

1 Introduction 2 Speech Act Theory: Examining Language at the Utterance Level Notes 1 Introduction 1. An initial distinction of this type can be found in Dascal (1983) under 'socio­ pragmatics' and 'psychopragmatics'. 2. For a detailed historical account of the development of the study of spoken discourse (el discurso oral) in Spanish from 1950 to 1999, including aspects of pragmatics as defined here, the reader is referred to Cortes Rodriguez (2002). 2 Speech Act Theory: Examining Language at the Utterance Level 1. One of Grewendorf's (2002) arguments, for instance, has to do with felicity conditions: If in uttering a performative we implicitly performed the act of making a statement and explicitly performed the act denoted by the performative verb, then performatives would be subject to two different sets of felicity conditions: the conditions for the act of making a statement and the con­ ditions for the act denoted by the performative verb (p. 33). Grewendorf, nonetheless, provides examples that show that only one set of conditions can be fulfilled. 2. Achugar (2002) defines piropos as compliments with an amorous or sexual tone, normally issued to strangers in the street and normally performed for an audience. It should be noted, however, that although Achugar's distinc­ tion between piropos and other types of compliments stands for ES, it does not necessarily hold for all varieties of Spanish. 3. See a related idea under the notion of adjacency pairs within conversation analysis (3.3.1). 4. In his seminal work, Speech Acts. An Essay on the Philosophy ofLanguage, Searle (1969) outlines his overall speech act theory, offering a detailed, rule-based characterization of speech acts. Searle (197 5) develops the notion of indirect speech acts, and, finally, Searle (1976) offers a taxonomy of speech acts. Searle's 1975 and 1976 publications are also contained, with slight modifi­ cations, in Expression and Meaning (Searle, 1979). 5. This example was obtained through participant observation. All other exam­ ples in the book where the source is not stipulated were obtained in the same manner. 6. Goodwin and Duranti (1992) express a related criticism when they point out that, with Searle's development of the theory, interest shifted from conven­ tions and context to a focus on intentionality, leaving out 'reference to soci- 231 232 Notes eta! norms or conventions that may exist outside of the speaker's conscious intentions to communicate' (p. 18). 7. This view can be more clearly inferred from Searle, 1975. 8. Example from Miranda Stewart, personal communication. 9. Alston (1991) notes that Searle does not provide an unambiguous definition of 'point' or 'purpose', so it is not clear whether purpose is intended to mean the same as point, such as to commit the speaker to what is promised, in the case of promises, or whether it refers to the speaker's purpose, which may be a variety of things. 10. Alston (1991) notes that there is an oddity in having expressives as a sepa­ rate category of illocutionary acts where 'something which is a feature of all illocutionary acts is here [in the case of expressives] the basic illocutionary point' (p. 73). 11. See also Gonzalez Mangas's (2000) analysis of how participants in the exchange listed under (30) arrive at each other's intended meaning. 12. Some requests, as Blum-Kulka eta/. (1989, p. 276) acknowledge, can be mul­ tiple-headed; that is, they may have more than one minimal unit realizing the requestive goal, as in 'Clean up the kitchen. Get rid of this mess'. 13. Blum-Kulka and House (1989) relabel this category as 'impositives', whereas they refer to strong and mild hints (non-conventional indirectness) as 'hints' only. 14. The notion of 'hedged performatives' belongs to Fraser (1975). 15. This is in contrast to the view expressed by Leech (1983), for whom a scale of (in)directness can be established and who associates indirectness with ten­ tativeness, 'the more indirect an illocution is, the more diminished and ten­ tative its force tends to be' (p. 108). This does not mean, however, that all indirectness leads to more politeness. 'Can't you sit down?' is an example Leech (1983) provides of indirectness leading to less politeness. 16. Blum-Kulka et al.'s (1989) basic notions of head acts and levels of directness, and internal and external modification have been applied to the analysis of invitations (Garcia, 1999) and reprimands (Garcia, 1996), among other speech acts. Placencia (2000), however, notes that the application of these notions can be problematic with complex speech acts (such as, complaints, made up of chains of acts with multiple functions), where it can be difficult to identify a central head act, as House and Kasper (1981) or Olshtain and Weinbach (1987) have done in their studies. 17. Additionally, Pratt (1981) points out that people do not always speak for themselves, but 'for or through other people' (p. 9); that is, in some sort of institutionalized role, where the intentions are not those of the private individual. 18. Hence, building on Wittgenstein's notion of language games, Levinson (1979) proposes the notion of activity types within which utterances are embedded and within which they have to be examined. Allwood (1995) and Linell (1996), on the other hand, discuss related proposals under the notions of an activity based approach to meaning and communicative projects, respectively. 19. Pratt (1981) goes even further when she accentuates the overemphasis within the theory on one-to-one, private communication: the norm within the theory is to have a speaker formulating his/her intention and a hearer Notes 233 understanding that intention, while speech situations often involve multi­ ple participants with multiple intentions toward one another. 20. The notion of inter-act, rather than speech act, is thus proposed by Linen (1996) to emphasize the collaborative nature of communicative actions (see also Linen and Markova, 1993). 21. In Haverkate's (1979) view, verbs such as, 'persuade' or 'convince', which in Austin and Searle's proposals appear as perlocutionary acts, are not speech acts as such; it is possible, therefore, to refer only to their 'effect' on the hearer. 22. In his 1994 publication, Haverkate follows Searle (1969), subsuming the referring and predicating acts under the propositional act. 23. Haverkate (1984) modifies his model slightly retaining the notion of allo­ cution not as a subact, but as the strategical component of the speech act that influences the performance of the different subacts. He does so in order to 'make it clear that speakers develop specific strategies in performing each of the subacts of the speech act' (p. 45). 24. See also Ortega Olivares (1985). 25. On the function of t.me entendes? in AS in the context of informal interac­ tions, see Boretti (1999). 26. It should be noted that the overview of speech act studies that we offer con­ centrates on those based on corpora of spoken data, usually within particu­ lar sociocultural contexts. Other studies, which are based on literary works, for example, or for which no indication of the corpus employed is given, have not been included. It should also be noted that we only report on studies published in Spanish and English. This applies to the other chapters in the book too. 27. The label 'single language and culture' does not imply that researchers nec­ essarily regard culture as fully homogeneous. In fact, variation in speech act realization is often studied in relation to considerations of stable character­ istics of the participants (mainly age and sex), as well as situated features (such as the degree of social distance obtaining between the participants in an interaction, power and ranking of the imposition) (Brown and Levinson, 1978, 1987). This is also the case in cross-cultural studies. 28. We refer here to situations where people with different cultural backgrounds interact in the same language, which might be the first language for both groups, or the first for one group and the second or later language for the other (see Clyne, 1998 for related distinctions). In the latter case, the inter­ language of the group becomes the focus of examination. 29. In the broadest sense, Blum-Kulka and Sheffer (1993) define interlanguage pragmatics as 'concerned with the ways in which nonnatives do things with words in a second language' (p.l96). They say that, although 'we have been used to thinking about interlanguage as an L2 (second language) specific notion' (p. 197), in bilingual situations like the ones they examine in their study, the participants are 'in effect, in contact with two incongruent prag­ matic systems, each realized by a culturally specific style of language use' (p. 197). According to this definition, some intercultural studies may also be subsumed under interlanguage; however, the notion might be relevant when describing the language of one of the participants, but not necessarily of both. 30. Intercultural encounters may take place in bilingual contexts. Nevertheless, 234 Notes here we keep the distinction between intercultural and bilingual studies in order to distinguish those studies that deal with two cultural groups in interaction (intercultural studies) from those where members from the same cultural group, who have the influence from two or more languages and cultures, interact with one another, as in the case of Chicanos interacting with other Chicanos (see, for example, Yanez, 1990 here). 31. See also Ferrer and Sanchez Lanza's (1998) examination of features of requests and commands. 32. It should be noted that Blum-Kulka and House (1989) comment on the need to examine a larger sample of Argentinian Spanish to further confirm the results of their study. They indicate, nonetheless, that 'there is evidence to suggest that they [the results of their study] reliably reflect a general Spanish trend for higher levels of directness than those acceptable in English' (p.
Recommended publications
  • Performative Speech Act Verbs in Present Day English
    PERFORMATIVE SPEECH ACT VERBS IN PRESENT DAY ENGLISH ELENA LÓPEZ ÁLVAREZ Universidad Complutense de Madrid RESUMEN. En esta contribución se estudian los actos performativos y su influencia en el inglés de hoy en día. A partir de las teorías de J. L. Austin, entre otros autores, se desarrolla un panorama de esta orientación de la filosofía del lenguaje de Austin. PALABRAS CLAVE. Actos performativos, enunciado performativo, inglés. ABSTRACT. This paper focuses on performative speech act verbs in present day English. Reading the theories of J. L. Austin, among others,. With the basis of authors as J. L. Austin, this paper develops a brief landscape about this orientation of Austin’s linguistic philosophy. KEY WORDS. Performative speech act verbs, performative utterance, English. 1. INTRODUCCIÓN 1.1. HISTORICAL THEORETICAL BACKGROUND 1.1.1. The beginnings: J.L. Austin The origin of performative speech acts as we know them today dates back to the William James Lectures, the linguistic-philosophical theories devised and delivered by J.L. Austin at Harvard University in 1955, and collected into a series of lectures entitled How to do things with words, posthumously published in 1962. Austin was one of the most influential philosophers of his time. In these lectures, he provided a thorough exploration of performative speech acts, which was an extremely innovative area of study in those days. In the following pages, Austin’s main ideas (together with some comments by other authors) will be presented. 1.1.1.1. Constative – performative distinction In these lectures, Austin begins by making a clear distinction between constative and performative utterances.
    [Show full text]
  • The Pragmatics of Powerlessness in Police Interrogation Author(S): Janet E
    The Yale Law Journal Company, Inc. In a Different Register: The Pragmatics of Powerlessness in Police Interrogation Author(s): Janet E. Ainsworth Reviewed work(s): Source: The Yale Law Journal, Vol. 103, No. 2 (Nov., 1993), pp. 259-322 Published by: The Yale Law Journal Company, Inc. Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/797097 . Accessed: 16/08/2012 14:37 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. The Yale Law Journal Company, Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Yale Law Journal. http://www.jstor.org Articles In a Different Register: The Pragmatics of Powerlessness in Police Interrogation Janet E. Ainswortht CONTENTS I. INTRODUCTION....................................... 260 II. How WE Do THINGS WITH WORDS .............................. 264 A. Performative Speech Acts . ................................. 264 B. Indirect Speech Acts as Performatives ......... ................ 267 C. Conversational Implicature Modifying Literal Meaning ..... ........ 268 III. GENDER AND LANGUAGEUSAGE: A DIFFERENTREGISTER .271 A. Characteristics of the Female Register . .275 1. Hedges .276 2. Tag Questions .277 t Associate Professorof Law, Universityof Puget Sound School of Law. B.A. BrandeisUniversity, M.A. Yale University, J.D. HarvardLaw School. My appreciativethanks go to HarrietCapron and Blain Johnson for their able research assistance.
    [Show full text]
  • Performative Sentences and the Morphosyntax-Semantics Interface in Archaic Vedic
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Journal of South Asian Linguistics JSAL volume 1, issue 1 October 2008 Performative Sentences and the Morphosyntax-Semantics Interface in Archaic Vedic Eystein Dahl, University of Oslo Received November 1, 2007; Revised October 15, 2008 Abstract Performative sentences represent a particularly intriguing type of self-referring assertive clauses, as they constitute an area of linguistics where the relationship between the semantic-grammatical and the pragmatic-contextual dimension of language is especially transparent. This paper examines how the notion of performativity interacts with different tense, aspect and mood categories in Vedic. The claim is that one may distinguish three slightly different constraints on performative sentences, a modal constraint demanding that the proposition is represented as being in full accordance with the Common Ground, an aspectual constraint demanding that there is a coextension relation between event time and reference time and a temporal constraint demanding that the reference time is coextensive with speech time. It is shown that the Archaic Vedic present indicative, aorist indicative and aorist injunctive are quite compatible with these constraints, that the basic modal specifications of present and aorist subjunctive and optative violate the modal constraint on performative sentences, but give rise to speaker-oriented readings which in turn are compatible with that constraint. However, the imperfect, the present injunctive, the perfect indicative and the various modal categories of the perfect stem are argued to be incompatible with the constraints on performative sentences. 1 Introduction Performative sentences represent a particularly intriguing type of self-referring assertive clauses, as they constitute an area of linguistics where the relationship between the semantic-grammatical and the pragmatic-contextual dimension of language is especially transparent.
    [Show full text]
  • Semantics Versus Pragmatics
    Linguistics 103: Language Structure and Verbal Art Pragmatics and Speech Act Theory Semantics versus Pragmatics semantics: branch of linguistics concerned with the meanings of propositions pragmatics: branch of linguistics concerned with • the use and function of language; • the relation between the structural properties of an utterance and its deployment and reception by language users Traditionally, meaning has been studied by examining those sentences which express propositions which have a truth-value. (1) Snow is white. The cat is on the mat. Semantics is concerned with the conditions under which the proposition expressed by a sentence is true. These are said to be its truth-conditions. (2) ‘Snow is white’ is True if and only if snow is white. ‘The cat is on the mat’ is True iff the cat is on the mat. object language: language in which sentences subject to study are expressed metalanguage: language in which the truth-conditions of the proposition expressed by the sentence are expressed (3) ‘Schnee ist weiss’ is True if and only if snow is white. ‘La neige est blanche’ is True if and only if snow is white. The study of the truth-conditions of propositions has a long history in linguistics and logic. One way to talk about truth-conditions is to imagine an inifinite number of ‘possible worlds’ where different states-of-affairs hold true. A (true-false) proposition picks out the set of worlds in which the proposition is true. This way of conceptualizing meaning then permits certain logical relations to be defined mathematically in terms of set theory.
    [Show full text]
  • The Cyber-Performative in Second Life
    The Cyber-Performative in Second Life by Meindert Nicholas van Orden B.A., University of Victoria, 2007 A Thesis Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of MASTER OF ARTS in the Department of English, with a specialization in Cultural, Social, and Political Thought © Meindert Nicholas van Orden, 2010 University of Victoria All rights reserved. This thesis may not be reproduced in whole or in part, by photocopy or other means, without the permission of the author. ii The Cyber-Performative in Second Life by Meindert Nicholas van Orden B.A., University of Victoria, 2007 Supervisory Committee Dr. Evelyn Cobley, Supervisor (Department of English) Dr. Ray Siemens, Departmental Member (Department of English) Dr. Arthur Kroker, Outside Member (Department of Political Science) iii Supervisory Committee Dr. Evelyn Cobley, Supervisor (Department of English) Dr. Ray Siemens, Departmental Member (Department of English) Dr. Arthur Kroker, Outside Member (Department of Political Science) Abstract I argue that current descriptions of the ways that language and computer code effect change (are “performative”) oversimplify the effects that utterances made in and through virtual spaces have on the real world. Building on J.L. Austin’s speech-act theory and Jacques Derrida’s deconstruction of Austin’s notion of performative language, I develop the theory of cyber-performativity. Though Katherine Hayles argues that “code” is more strongly performative than the utterances Austin focused on, Hayles’ analysis is founded on her problematic distinction between the logical computational worldview and the slippery natural-languages worldview. Cyber-performative theory builds on Hayles’ argument by showing that computational processes are as uncertain as natural languages: like human languages, “code” might always signify more and other than is intended.
    [Show full text]
  • A Plea for Perlocutions
    CONVERSATIONS 4 A Plea for Perlocutions DAVID KAUFMANN After staging the shipwreck of the constative-performative distinction halfway through How To Do Things With Words, J.L. Austin goes on famously to “make a fresh start on the problem.”1 He relinquishes the original opposition between making statements and doing things and then introduces a ternary account of speech acts. He distinguishes between locutionary acts (in which we produce sounds with “a certain sense and a cer- tain reference”[95]), illocutionary acts (in which we perform acts such as “asking or answering a question, giving some information… announcing a verdict...and the nume- rous like” [98-99]), and perlocutionary acts (in which we “produce consequential ef- fects upon the feelings, thoughts or actions of an audience, or of the speaker, or of other persons”[101]). For all the philosophical ink that has been spilled on Austin, not much has been devoted to perlocutions. Locutions and illocutions get almost all the action. Stanley Cavell has been one of the few philosophers to emphasize the impor- tance of the perlocutionary for speech act theory. In his forward to the second edition of Shoshana Felman’s The Scandal of the Speaking Body and in his essay “Performa- tive and Passionate Utterances,” Cavell assumes, as Stephen Mulhall puts it, that Aus- tin believes that “the perlocutionary effect of any utterance [is] extrinsic to its sense and force” and thus that the perlocutionary can be opposed to the illocutionary act.2 Because Austin maintains that the illocutionary is conventional and the perlocutio- nary is not (121), Cavell argues that illocutions come down on the side of the Law, while perlocutions give voice to Desire.
    [Show full text]
  • Students' Awareness of Felicity Conditions and Their Attitudes
    People’s Democratic Republic of Algeria Ministry of Higher Education and Scientific Research University of Constantine Faculty of letters and languages Department of English Students’ Awareness of Felicity Conditions and Their Attitudes towards the Application of Felicitous Speech Acts The Case of Master One English Students University of Constantine A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Master degree in languages sciences Submitted by : Mr. Idriss TOUMI Supervisor : Pr. Ahmed MOUMENE Board of Examiners Member: Dr. Samir LARABA MC Constantine University Supervisor: Prof. Ahmed MOUMENE Professor Constantine University 2010 Dedication To my dear and precious parents To all my sisters, especially my little sister: Imane To All My Brothers: Othman, Saad, Ibrahim and Mohamed To all my family… To my friends: Yahia. Ismail and Najib To all who know me … I Acknowledgments I should like to thank my supervisor, Professor Ahmed Moumene, for his considerable efforts to enhance this dissertation. His comments were always penetrating and stimulating and his criticism was always constructive. His constant and good- humored insistence on clarity of presentation helped me turn my confused first drafts into considerably better-organized final product. I am grateful to Professor Ahmed Moumene, who was kind enough to show an interest in my thesis from the earliest stages and who helped me through all the stages of inspite of all the pressing circumstances. I should also like to express my sincere thanks to Dr Samir Laraba for his acceptance to be the examiner of the jury. I am also thankful for Miss Soucha and her students who were very kind with me and who were very objective in filling in the questionnaire.
    [Show full text]
  • Universality and Language-Dependency of Tense And
    Linguistic Typology 2019; 23(1): 1–58 Egbert Fortuin Universality and language-dependency of tense and aspect: Performatives from a crosslinguistic perspective https://doi.org/10.1515/lingty-2018-0018 Received April 02, 2018; revised November 14, 2018 Abstract: This paper presents a cross-linguistic typology of performatives, espe- cially with respect to their relationship with tense and aspect, in the languages of the world. I explore the relationship between performatives and particular tenses and aspects, and touch on the mechanisms underlying such a relation- ship. The paper finds that there is not one relation between performatives and a particular tense and aspect and there are no languages which have a special (dedicated) performative tense or aspect marker. Instead, performatives are compatible with various tense and aspect markers, even though the use of a present tense seems to be the most common. What counts as the most optimal tense and aspect for performatives depends on the division of labor within the linguistic structure. Keywords: performatives, verbal aspect, tense, perfective, imperfective, comparative semantics 1 Introduction Austin (1962) introduces performatives such as I promise as speech acts which not only describe a given reality, but also change the reality they are describing. Even though Austin argues that the simple present is directly or indirectly inherent to performatives in English, it was noted already in the first half of the twentieth century that some languages express performatives differently, for example by a perfective with a past reading (Koschmieder 1929, Koschmieder 1930 for Biblical Hebrew) or a verb which is morphologically marked as a perfective present tense (Škrabec 1903; Koschmieder 1929, Koschmieder 1930 for Slavic).
    [Show full text]
  • The Analysis of Performative Utterances in the Movie Script Captain America: Civil War and Its Application to Teach Speaking at the Tenth Grade for Senior High School
    THE ANALYSIS OF PERFORMATIVE UTTERANCES IN THE MOVIE SCRIPT CAPTAIN AMERICA: CIVIL WAR AND ITS APPLICATION TO TEACH SPEAKING AT THE TENTH GRADE FOR SENIOR HIGH SCHOOL S1 Thesis Submitted as a partial fulfillment of the requirement to obtain Sarjana Pendidikan degree at English Education Program of Purworejo Muhammadiyah University By RIYA ARBIYANTI 132120206 ENGLISH EDUCATION PROGRAM TEACHER TRAINING AND EDUCATION FACULTY PURWOREJO MUHAMMADIYAH UNIVERSITY 2017 THE ANALYSIS OF PERFORMATIVE UTTERANCES IN THE MOVIE SCRIPT CAPTAIN AMERICA: CIVIL WAR AND ITS APPLICATION TO TEACH SPEAKING AT THE TENTH GRADE FOR SENIOR HIGH SCHOOL S1 Thesis Submitted as a partial fulfillment of the requirement to obtain Sarjana Pendidikan degree at English Education Program of Purworejo Muhammadiyah University By RIYA ARBIYANTI 132120206 ENGLISH EDUCATION PROGRAM TEACHER TRAINING AND EDUCATION FACULTY PURWOREJO MUHAMMADIYAH UNIVERSITY 2017 i ii iii iv MOTTOS Really shared hardship and relief. Because it when you have finished (do something else). And to ALLAH SWT, hopefully. (Q.S Al Insyirah:6-8) Try not to be a people of success, but rather to become a people value (Einstein) “Ajining dhiri iku dumunung ana ing anggone pribadhi netepi kewajiban” (Mbah Maridjan) Fall down seven time, get up eight !! Whatever I receive today is the best of ALLAH SWT, because ALLAH SWT will always give the best for me and have wonderful planning. Riya Arbiyanti v DEDICATION This work is lovingly dedicated to: My one and only Mamak, alm. Bapak, and my beloved Mas and Mba vi ACKNOWLEDGEMENT ﺑِﺴْﻢِ ﷲﱠ ِ اﻟﺮﱠﺣْ ﻤَﻦِ اﻟﺮﱠﺣِﻲ Alhamdulillahirobbil’alamin. All praises to Allah, the Almighty, who has always been giving me blessing, grace, and mercy, without which I would never be able to finish this thesis.
    [Show full text]
  • Code As Performative Speech Act
    QXP Arns 73 06/07/05 09:35 Página I July 2005 ISSN: 1695-5951 www.uoc.edu/artnodes Article Code as performative speech act http://www.uoc.edu/artnodes/eng/art/arns0505.pdf Inke Arns QXP Arns 73 06/07/05 09:35 Página 1 Artnodes July 2005 July 2005Code ISSN: as 1695-5951performative speech act Article Code as performative speech act http://www.uoc.edu/artnodes/eng/art/arns0505.pdf Inke Arns Abstract Software art involves an artistic activity which, in the medium —or rather, the material— of software, allows for cri- tical reflection on software (and its cultural impact). It thus highlights the aesthetic and political subtexts of seemingly neutral technical commands. In this article Inke Arns argues that, in the context of software art, a far more interes- ting notion than the “generative” nature of code is its “performativity”. This notion —borrowed from speech act the- ory— not only involves the ability to generate in a technical context, but also encompasses the implications and reper- cussions of code in terms of aesthetics, politics and society. This article proposes the notion of the performativity of code as one of the reasons for contemporary artists’ growing interest in using software as an artistic material. Keywords Software art, generative art, code, performativity A similar, but indeed far more interesting, story for our Introduction context is that of the Golem. In 1580 in Prague, as the leg- end goes, the famous Rabbi Loew created a Golem, an artifi- Let’s start at the very beginning (I won’t spare you this classic).
    [Show full text]
  • Speech Act Theory and Universal Grammar* Teoria Dos Atos De Fala E Gramática Universal
    Logic, Language and Knowledge. Essays on Chateauriand’s Logical Forms Walter A. Carnielli and Jairo J. da Silva (eds.) CDD: 401 SPEECH ACT THEORY AND UNIVERSAL GRAMMAR* DANIEL VANDERVEKEN** Departement de Philosophie Université du Québec, Trois-Rivières TROIS-RIVIERES G9A 5H7 CANADA [email protected] Abstract: Are there universal transcendent features that any natural language must possess in order to provide for its human speakers adequate means of expression and of communication of their conceptual thoughts? As Frege, Austin and Searle pointed out, complete speech acts of the type called illocutionary acts, and not isolated propositions, are the primary units of meaning in the use and comprehension of language. Thus it is in the very performance of illocutionary acts that speakers express and communicate their thoughts. For this reason, speech act theory contributes to the theory of linguistic universals in formulating the necessary and universal laws governing the successful performance and satisfaction of illocutionary acts in language use and comprehension. I will argue that the logical form of illocutionary acts imposes certain formal constraints on the logical structure of a possible natural language as well as on the mind of competent speakers. In particular, certain syntactic, semantic and pragmatic features are universal because they are indispensable. Moreover, in order to perform and understand illocutionary acts, competent speakers and hearers must have certain mental states and abilities which are in general traditionally related to the faculty of reason. Key-words: Speech act theory. Illocutionary acts. Natural language. Universal grammar. TEORIA DOS ATOS DE FALA E GRAMÁTICA UNIVERSAL Resumo: Há características transcendentes universais que qualquer linguagem natural tem que possuir para fornecer meios adequados de expressão e de comunicação de pensamentos conceituais aos seus falantes humanos? Como Frege, Austin e Searle * Originally published in Manuscrito, v.
    [Show full text]
  • Reconsidering Psycholinguistics' Project : Language As Praxis in Lacan and Kristeva
    Loyola University Chicago Loyola eCommons Dissertations Theses and Dissertations 1992 Reconsidering psycholinguistics' project : language as praxis in Lacan and Kristeva Suzanne Barnard Loyola University Chicago Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_diss Part of the Psychology Commons Recommended Citation Barnard, Suzanne, "Reconsidering psycholinguistics' project : language as praxis in Lacan and Kristeva" (1992). Dissertations. 3021. https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_diss/3021 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Copyright © 1992 Suzanne Barnard RECONSIDERING PSYCHOLINGUISTICS' PROJECT: LANGUAGE AS PRAXIS IN LACAN AND KRISTEVA by Suzanne Barnard, M. A. A Dissertation Submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate School of Loyola University of Chicago in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy September 1992 Copyright by Suzanne Barnard, 1992 All Rights Reserved 11 ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I wish to thank the many individuals who helped to make this dissertation possible. First, I would like to express my appreciation for the constructive criticisms and suggestions of committee members Ors. Jill N. Reich, John R. Shack, and Richard N. Williams. I would especially like to thank Father Daniel C. O'Connell, director of my dissertation, for his unending support and insightful guidance throughout all phases of this project. Finally, I would like to express my gratitude to my parents, Mary Sue Barnard and James A.
    [Show full text]