Meta Math! Cover

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Meta Math! Cover i META MATH! The Quest for Omega by Gregory Chaitin Gregory Chaitin has devoted his life to the attempt to understand what mathematics can and cannot achieve, and is a member of the digital philos- ophy/digital physics movement. Its members believe that the world is built out of digital information, out of 0 and 1 bits, and they view the universe as a giant information-processing machine, a giant digital computer. In this book on the history of ideas, Chaitin traces digital philosophy back to the nearly-forgotten 17th century genius Leibniz. He also tells us how he dis- covered the celebrated Omega number, which marks the current boundary of what mathematics can achieve. This book is an opportunity to get inside the head of a creative mathematician and see what makes him tick, and opens a window for its readers onto a glittering world of high-altitude thought that few intellectual mountain climbers can ever glimpse. arXiv:math/0404335v7 [math.HO] 13 Sep 2004 ii Meta Math! Cover William Blake: The Ancient of Days, 1794. Relief etching with watercolor, 9 1 6 7 inches. 8 × 8 British Museum, London. iii iv Meta Math! Preface Science is an open road: each question you answer raises ten new questions, and much more difficult ones! Yes, I’ll tell you some things I discovered, but the journey is endless, and mostly I’ll share with you, the reader, my doubts and preoccupations and what I think are promising and challenging new things to think about. It would be easy to spend many lifetimes working on any of a number of the questions that I’ll discuss. That is how the good questions are. You can’t answer them in five minutes, and it would be no good if you could. Science is an adventure. I don’t believe in spending years studying the work of others, years learning a complicated field before I can contribute a tiny little bit. I prefer to stride off in totally new directions, where imagina- tion is, at least initially, much more important than technique, because the techniques have yet to be developed. It takes all kinds of people to advance knowledge, the pioneers, and those who come afterwards and patiently work a farm. This book is for pioneers! Most books emphasize what the author knows. I’ll try to emphasize what I would like to know, what I’m hoping someone will discover, and just how much there is that is fundamental and that we don’t know! And yes, I’m a mathematician, but I’m really interested in everything: what is life, what’s intelligence, what is consciousness, does the universe contain randomness, are space and time continuous or discrete. To me math is just the fundamental tool of philosophy, it’s a way to work out ideas, to flesh them out, to build models, to understand! As Leibniz said, without math you cannot really understand philosophy, without philosophy you cannot v vi Meta Math! really understand mathematics, and with neither of them, you can’t really understand a thing! Or at least that’s my credo, that’s how I operate. On the other hand, as someone said a long time ago, “a mathematician who is not something of a poet will never be a good mathematician.” And “there is no permanent place in the world for ugly mathematics” (G. H. Hardy). To survive, mathematical ideas must be beautiful, they must be seductive, and they must be illuminating, they must help us to understand, they must inspire us. So I hope this little book will also convey something of this more personal aspect of mathematical creation, of mathematics as a way of celebrating the universe, as a kind of love-making! I want you to fall in love with mathematical ideas, to begin to feel seduced by them, to see how easy it is to be entranced and to want to spend years in their company, years working on mathematical projects. And it is a mistake to think that a mathematical idea can survive merely because it is useful, because it has practical applications. On the contrary, what is useful varies as a function of time, while “a thing of beauty is a joy forever” (Keats). Deep theory is what is really useful, not the ephemeral usefulness of practical applications! Part of that beauty, an essential part, is the clarity and sharpness that the mathematical way of thinking about things promotes and achieves. Yes, there are also mystic and poetic ways of relating to the world, and to create a new math theory, or to discover new mathematics, you have to feel com- fortable with vague, unformed, embryonic ideas, even as you try to sharpen them. But one of the things about math that seduced me as a child was the black/whiteness, the clarity and sharpness of the world of mathematical ideas, that is so different from the messy (but wonderful!) world of human emotions and interpersonal complications! No wonder that scientists express their understanding in mathematical terms, when they can! As has been often said, to understand something is to make it mathe- matical, and I hope that this may eventually even happen to the fields of psychology and sociology, someday. That is my bias, that the math point of view can contribute to everything, that it can help to clarify anything. Mathematics is a way of characterizing or expressing structure. And the universe seems to be built, at some fundamental level, out of mathematical structure. To speak metaphorically, it appears that God is a mathematician, and that the structure of the world—God’s thoughts!—are mathematical, that this is the cloth out of which the world is woven, the wood out of which the world is built. Preface vii When I was a child the excitement of relativity theory (Einstein!) and quantum mechanics was trailing off, and the excitement of DNA and molec- ular biology had not begun. What was the new big thing then? The Com- puter! Which some people referred to then as “Giant Electronic Brains.” I was fascinated by computers as a child. First of all, because they were a great toy, an infinitely malleable artistic medium of creation. I loved programming! But most of all, because the computer was (and still is!) a wonderful new philosophical and mathematical concept. The computer is even more revo- lutionary as an idea, than it is as a practical device that alters society—and we all know how much it has changed our lives. Why do I say this? Well, the computer changes epistemology, it changes the meaning of “to understand.” To me, you understand something only if you can program it. (You, not someone else!) Otherwise you don’t really understand it, you only think you understand it. And, as we shall see, the computer changes the way you do mathematics, it changes the kind of mathematical models of the world that you build. In a nutshell, now God seems to be a programmer, not a mathematician! The computer has provoked a paradigm shift: it suggests a digital philosophy, it suggests a new way of looking at the world, in which everything is discrete and nothing is continuous, in which everything is digital information, 0’s and 1’s. So I was naturally attracted to this revolutionary new idea. And what about the so-called real world of money and taxes and disease and death and war? What about this “best of all possible worlds, in which everything is a necessary evil!?” Well, I prefer to ignore that insignificant world and concentrate instead on the world of ideas, on the quest for under- standing. Instead of looking down into the mud, how about looking up at the stars! Why don’t you try it? Maybe you’ll like that kind of a life too! Anyway, you don’t have to read these musings from cover to cover. Just leap right in wherever you like, and on a first reading please skip anything that seems too difficult. Maybe it’ll turn out afterwards that it’s actually not so difficult. I think that basic ideas are simple. And I’m not really interested in complicated ideas, I’m only interested in fundamental ideas. If the answer is extremely complicated, I think that probably means that we’ve asked the wrong question! No man is an island, and practically every page of this book has benefited from discussions with Fran¸coise Chaitin-Chatelin during the past decade; she has wanted me to write this book for that long. Gradiva, a Portuguese publishing house, arranged a stimulating visit for me to that country in viii Meta Math! January 2004. During that trip my lecture at the University of Lisbon on Chapter V of this book was captured on digital video and is now available on the web. I am also grateful to Jorge Aguirre for inviting me to present this book as a course at his summer school at the University of R´ıo Cuarto in C´ordoba, Argentina, in February 2004; the students’ comments there were extremely helpful. And Cristian Calude has provided me with a delightful environment in which to finish this book at his Center for Discrete Math and Theoretical Computer Science at the University of Auckland. In particular, I thank Simona Dragomir for all her help. Finally, I am greatly indebted to Nabil Amer and to the Physics Depart- ment at the IBM Thomas J. Watson Research Center in Yorktown Heights, New York (my home base between trips) for their support of my work.
Recommended publications
  • Does the Category of Multisets Require a Larger Universe Than
    Pure Mathematical Sciences, Vol. 2, 2013, no. 3, 133 - 146 HIKARI Ltd, www.m-hikari.com Does the Category of Multisets Require a Larger Universe than that of the Category of Sets? Dasharath Singh (Former affiliation: Indian Institute of Technology Bombay) Department of Mathematics, Ahmadu Bello University, Zaria, Nigeria [email protected] Ahmed Ibrahim Isah Department of Mathematics Ahmadu Bello University, Zaria, Nigeria [email protected] Alhaji Jibril Alkali Department of Mathematics Ahmadu Bello University, Zaria, Nigeria [email protected] Copyright © 2013 Dasharath Singh et al. This is an open access article distributed under the Creative Commons Attribution License, which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited. Abstract In section 1, the concept of a category is briefly described. In section 2, it is elaborated how the concept of category is naturally intertwined with the existence of a universe of discourse much larger than what is otherwise sufficient for a large part of mathematics. It is also remarked that the extended universe for the category of sets is adequate for the category of multisets as well. In section 3, fundamentals required for adequately describing a category are extended to defining a multiset category, and some of its distinctive features are outlined. Mathematics Subject Classification: 18A05, 18A20, 18B99 134 Dasharath Singh et al. Keywords: Category, Universe, Multiset Category, objects. 1. Introduction to categories The history of science and that of mathematics, in particular, records that at times, a by- product may turn out to be of greater significance than the main objective of a research.
    [Show full text]
  • Simulating Quantum Field Theory with a Quantum Computer
    Simulating quantum field theory with a quantum computer John Preskill Lattice 2018 28 July 2018 This talk has two parts (1) Near-term prospects for quantum computing. (2) Opportunities in quantum simulation of quantum field theory. Exascale digital computers will advance our knowledge of QCD, but some challenges will remain, especially concerning real-time evolution and properties of nuclear matter and quark-gluon plasma at nonzero temperature and chemical potential. Digital computers may never be able to address these (and other) problems; quantum computers will solve them eventually, though I’m not sure when. The physics payoff may still be far away, but today’s research can hasten the arrival of a new era in which quantum simulation fuels progress in fundamental physics. Frontiers of Physics short distance long distance complexity Higgs boson Large scale structure “More is different” Neutrino masses Cosmic microwave Many-body entanglement background Supersymmetry Phases of quantum Dark matter matter Quantum gravity Dark energy Quantum computing String theory Gravitational waves Quantum spacetime particle collision molecular chemistry entangled electrons A quantum computer can simulate efficiently any physical process that occurs in Nature. (Maybe. We don’t actually know for sure.) superconductor black hole early universe Two fundamental ideas (1) Quantum complexity Why we think quantum computing is powerful. (2) Quantum error correction Why we think quantum computing is scalable. A complete description of a typical quantum state of just 300 qubits requires more bits than the number of atoms in the visible universe. Why we think quantum computing is powerful We know examples of problems that can be solved efficiently by a quantum computer, where we believe the problems are hard for classical computers.
    [Show full text]
  • Geometric Algorithms
    Geometric Algorithms primitive operations convex hull closest pair voronoi diagram References: Algorithms in C (2nd edition), Chapters 24-25 http://www.cs.princeton.edu/introalgsds/71primitives http://www.cs.princeton.edu/introalgsds/72hull 1 Geometric Algorithms Applications. • Data mining. • VLSI design. • Computer vision. • Mathematical models. • Astronomical simulation. • Geographic information systems. airflow around an aircraft wing • Computer graphics (movies, games, virtual reality). • Models of physical world (maps, architecture, medical imaging). Reference: http://www.ics.uci.edu/~eppstein/geom.html History. • Ancient mathematical foundations. • Most geometric algorithms less than 25 years old. 2 primitive operations convex hull closest pair voronoi diagram 3 Geometric Primitives Point: two numbers (x, y). any line not through origin Line: two numbers a and b [ax + by = 1] Line segment: two points. Polygon: sequence of points. Primitive operations. • Is a point inside a polygon? • Compare slopes of two lines. • Distance between two points. • Do two line segments intersect? Given three points p , p , p , is p -p -p a counterclockwise turn? • 1 2 3 1 2 3 Other geometric shapes. • Triangle, rectangle, circle, sphere, cone, … • 3D and higher dimensions sometimes more complicated. 4 Intuition Warning: intuition may be misleading. • Humans have spatial intuition in 2D and 3D. • Computers do not. • Neither has good intuition in higher dimensions! Is a given polygon simple? no crossings 1 6 5 8 7 2 7 8 6 4 2 1 1 15 14 13 12 11 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 2 18 4 18 4 19 4 19 4 20 3 20 3 20 1 10 3 7 2 8 8 3 4 6 5 15 1 11 3 14 2 16 we think of this algorithm sees this 5 Polygon Inside, Outside Jordan curve theorem.
    [Show full text]
  • Specifying Verified X86 Software from Scratch
    Specifying verified x86 software from scratch Mario Carneiro Carnegie Mellon University, Pittsburgh, PA, USA [email protected] Abstract We present a simple framework for specifying and proving facts about the input/output behavior of ELF binary files on the x86-64 architecture. A strong emphasis has been placed on simplicity at all levels: the specification says only what it needs to about the target executable, the specification is performed inside a simple logic (equivalent to first-order Peano Arithmetic), and the verification language and proof checker are custom-designed to have only what is necessary to perform efficient general purpose verification. This forms a part of the Metamath Zero project, to build a minimal verifier that is capable of verifying its own binary. In this paper, we will present the specification of the dynamic semantics of x86 machine code, together with enough information about Linux system calls to perform simple IO. 2012 ACM Subject Classification Theory of computation → Program verification; Theory of com- putation → Abstract machines Keywords and phrases x86-64, ISA specification, Metamath Zero, self-verification Digital Object Identifier 10.4230/LIPIcs.ITP.2019.19 Supplement Material The formalization is a part of the Metamath Zero project at https://github. com/digama0/mm0. Funding This material is based upon work supported by AFOSR grant FA9550-18-1-0120 and a grant from the Sloan Foundation. Acknowledgements I would like to thank my advisor Jeremy Avigad for his support and encourage- ment, and for his reviews of early drafts of this work. 1 Introduction The field of software verification is on the verge of a breakthrough.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction to Computational Social Choice
    1 Introduction to Computational Social Choice Felix Brandta, Vincent Conitzerb, Ulle Endrissc, J´er^omeLangd, and Ariel D. Procacciae 1.1 Computational Social Choice at a Glance Social choice theory is the field of scientific inquiry that studies the aggregation of individual preferences towards a collective choice. For example, social choice theorists|who hail from a range of different disciplines, including mathematics, economics, and political science|are interested in the design and theoretical evalu- ation of voting rules. Questions of social choice have stimulated intellectual thought for centuries. Over time the topic has fascinated many a great mind, from the Mar- quis de Condorcet and Pierre-Simon de Laplace, through Charles Dodgson (better known as Lewis Carroll, the author of Alice in Wonderland), to Nobel Laureates such as Kenneth Arrow, Amartya Sen, and Lloyd Shapley. Computational social choice (COMSOC), by comparison, is a very young field that formed only in the early 2000s. There were, however, a few precursors. For instance, David Gale and Lloyd Shapley's algorithm for finding stable matchings between two groups of people with preferences over each other, dating back to 1962, truly had a computational flavor. And in the late 1980s, a series of papers by John Bartholdi, Craig Tovey, and Michael Trick showed that, on the one hand, computational complexity, as studied in theoretical computer science, can serve as a barrier against strategic manipulation in elections, but on the other hand, it can also prevent the efficient use of some voting rules altogether. Around the same time, a research group around Bernard Monjardet and Olivier Hudry also started to study the computational complexity of preference aggregation procedures.
    [Show full text]
  • Number Theory
    “mcs-ftl” — 2010/9/8 — 0:40 — page 81 — #87 4 Number Theory Number theory is the study of the integers. Why anyone would want to study the integers is not immediately obvious. First of all, what’s to know? There’s 0, there’s 1, 2, 3, and so on, and, oh yeah, -1, -2, . Which one don’t you understand? Sec- ond, what practical value is there in it? The mathematician G. H. Hardy expressed pleasure in its impracticality when he wrote: [Number theorists] may be justified in rejoicing that there is one sci- ence, at any rate, and that their own, whose very remoteness from or- dinary human activities should keep it gentle and clean. Hardy was specially concerned that number theory not be used in warfare; he was a pacifist. You may applaud his sentiments, but he got it wrong: Number Theory underlies modern cryptography, which is what makes secure online communication possible. Secure communication is of course crucial in war—which may leave poor Hardy spinning in his grave. It’s also central to online commerce. Every time you buy a book from Amazon, check your grades on WebSIS, or use a PayPal account, you are relying on number theoretic algorithms. Number theory also provides an excellent environment for us to practice and apply the proof techniques that we developed in Chapters 2 and 3. Since we’ll be focusing on properties of the integers, we’ll adopt the default convention in this chapter that variables range over the set of integers, Z. 4.1 Divisibility The nature of number theory emerges as soon as we consider the divides relation a divides b iff ak b for some k: D The notation, a b, is an abbreviation for “a divides b.” If a b, then we also j j say that b is a multiple of a.
    [Show full text]
  • Cantor, God, and Inconsistent Multiplicities*
    STUDIES IN LOGIC, GRAMMAR AND RHETORIC 44 (57) 2016 DOI: 10.1515/slgr-2016-0008 Aaron R. Thomas-Bolduc University of Calgary CANTOR, GOD, AND INCONSISTENT MULTIPLICITIES* Abstract. The importance of Georg Cantor’s religious convictions is often ne- glected in discussions of his mathematics and metaphysics. Herein I argue, pace Jan´e(1995), that due to the importance of Christianity to Cantor, he would have never thought of absolutely infinite collections/inconsistent multiplicities, as being merely potential, or as being purely mathematical entities. I begin by considering and rejecting two arguments due to Ignacio Jan´e based on letters to Hilbert and the generating principles for ordinals, respectively, showing that my reading of Cantor is consistent with that evidence. I then argue that evidence from Cantor’s later writings shows that he was still very religious later in his career, and thus would not have given up on the reality of the absolute, as that would imply an imperfection on the part of God. The theological acceptance of his set theory was very important to Can- tor. Despite this, the influence of theology on his conception of absolutely infinite collections, or inconsistent multiplicities, is often ignored in contem- porary literature.1 I will be arguing that due in part to his religious convic- tions, and despite an apparent tension between his earlier and later writings, Cantor would never have considered inconsistent multiplicities (similar to what we now call proper classes) as completed in a mathematical sense, though they are completed in Intellectus Divino. Before delving into the issue of the actuality or otherwise of certain infinite collections, it will be informative to give an explanation of Cantor’s terminology, as well a sketch of Cantor’s relationship with religion and reli- gious figures.
    [Show full text]
  • The Metamathematics of Putnam's Model-Theoretic Arguments
    The Metamathematics of Putnam's Model-Theoretic Arguments Tim Button Abstract. Putnam famously attempted to use model theory to draw metaphysical conclusions. His Skolemisation argument sought to show metaphysical realists that their favourite theories have countable models. His permutation argument sought to show that they have permuted mod- els. His constructivisation argument sought to show that any empirical evidence is compatible with the Axiom of Constructibility. Here, I exam- ine the metamathematics of all three model-theoretic arguments, and I argue against Bays (2001, 2007) that Putnam is largely immune to meta- mathematical challenges. Copyright notice. This paper is due to appear in Erkenntnis. This is a pre-print, and may be subject to minor changes. The authoritative version should be obtained from Erkenntnis, once it has been published. Hilary Putnam famously attempted to use model theory to draw metaphys- ical conclusions. Specifically, he attacked metaphysical realism, a position characterised by the following credo: [T]he world consists of a fixed totality of mind-independent objects. (Putnam 1981, p. 49; cf. 1978, p. 125). Truth involves some sort of correspondence relation between words or thought-signs and external things and sets of things. (1981, p. 49; cf. 1989, p. 214) [W]hat is epistemically most justifiable to believe may nonetheless be false. (1980, p. 473; cf. 1978, p. 125) To sum up these claims, Putnam characterised metaphysical realism as an \externalist perspective" whose \favorite point of view is a God's Eye point of view" (1981, p. 49). Putnam sought to show that this externalist perspective is deeply untenable. To this end, he treated correspondence in terms of model-theoretic satisfaction.
    [Show full text]
  • Set-Theoretic Geology, the Ultimate Inner Model, and New Axioms
    Set-theoretic Geology, the Ultimate Inner Model, and New Axioms Justin William Henry Cavitt (860) 949-5686 [email protected] Advisor: W. Hugh Woodin Harvard University March 20, 2017 Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Bachelor of Arts in Mathematics and Philosophy Contents 1 Introduction 2 1.1 Author’s Note . .4 1.2 Acknowledgements . .4 2 The Independence Problem 5 2.1 Gödelian Independence and Consistency Strength . .5 2.2 Forcing and Natural Independence . .7 2.2.1 Basics of Forcing . .8 2.2.2 Forcing Facts . 11 2.2.3 The Space of All Forcing Extensions: The Generic Multiverse 15 2.3 Recap . 16 3 Approaches to New Axioms 17 3.1 Large Cardinals . 17 3.2 Inner Model Theory . 25 3.2.1 Basic Facts . 26 3.2.2 The Constructible Universe . 30 3.2.3 Other Inner Models . 35 3.2.4 Relative Constructibility . 38 3.3 Recap . 39 4 Ultimate L 40 4.1 The Axiom V = Ultimate L ..................... 41 4.2 Central Features of Ultimate L .................... 42 4.3 Further Philosophical Considerations . 47 4.4 Recap . 51 1 5 Set-theoretic Geology 52 5.1 Preliminaries . 52 5.2 The Downward Directed Grounds Hypothesis . 54 5.2.1 Bukovský’s Theorem . 54 5.2.2 The Main Argument . 61 5.3 Main Results . 65 5.4 Recap . 74 6 Conclusion 74 7 Appendix 75 7.1 Notation . 75 7.2 The ZFC Axioms . 76 7.3 The Ordinals . 77 7.4 The Universe of Sets . 77 7.5 Transitive Models and Absoluteness .
    [Show full text]
  • Pure Mathematics Professors Teaching and Leading Research CO-OP OR REGULAR 28
    PURE MATHEMATICS Pure Mathematics professors teaching and leading research CO-OP OR REGULAR 28 Mathematician ranked among top 10 TOP 10 jobs from 2011-2017 – Comcast.com of grads are employed Search for a deeper 96.6% within 2 years understanding of mathematics Pure mathematics is at the foundation of all mathematical reasoning. If first-year calculus ALEX teaches you how to drive the car, Pure Mathematics teaches you how to build one. 3B, PURE MATHEMATICS AND Mathematicians know that there could be no general relativity without differential COMBINATORICS AND geometry, and no computer security without advanced number theory. OPTIMIZATION Pure Mathematics at Waterloo is a small, cohesive, and challenging program that will open countless doors for you. Our graduates have used the program as a springboard into careers WHAT DO YOU LOVE ABOUT in information technology, finance, business, science, education, and insurance, often by way PURE MATHEMATICS? The satisfaction from understanding of some of the most prestigious graduate programs in the world. an idea at a deeper level and tying together unrelated branches of ALEX’S FAVOURITE COURSES mathematics or physics for the › PMATH 320 Euclidean Geometry: This course is everything you love about Geometry: first time is the most rewarding Euclid’s axioms, isometries of the Euclidean plane and of Euclidean space, polygons, part of learning and understanding polyhedral, polytopes, and the kissing problem. mathematics. What I really enjoy is › PMATH 351 Real Analysis: It’s a very intuitive and natural approach to real analysis, and the developing a deep understanding of complexity of the course builds very naturally to the end of the semester.
    [Show full text]
  • FC Schaffhausen- AC Bellinzona Wärmedämm-, Schall-, Einbruchschutz + Montag, 14
    AZ Schaffhausen Fr. 3.– schaffhauser Nr. 15 Donnerstag, 10. April 2008 Die lokale Wochenzeitung azTel: 052 633 08 33, Fax: 052 633 08 34, E-Mail: [email protected], Webergasse 39, Pf. 36, 8201 Schaffhausen Bild des Alters Seit genau neunzig Jahren zeichnet die «Pro Senectute Kanton Schaffhausen» mit am Bild des Alters, das sich so schnell verändert wie die Ge- sellschaft. Heute darf man sa- gen: Mehr Lebendigkeit war nie. Mit öffentlichen Vorträgen und einem schönen Fest für alle wird gefeiert. Im Bild die neue, spannende Broschüre, die man bestellen kann. (Foto: Peter Pfister) Seite 12 Die SVP-Story Zu sich finden fraz #! Auch der Kanton Schaff- Seit gut einem Jahr gibt es s "ARBARA % ,UDWIG ER- hausen hat seine SVP-Sto- an der Vordergasse 31/33 zählt von ihrer Arbeit beim ry, die sich immer weniger ein Dharmazentrum für Kriegsverbrechertribunal unterscheidet von der Ge- spirituelle Entwicklung. s"UNTE&ILMMISCHUNGAM samtstory. Ein Kommentar Wer sucht es auf und wes- «Kurz & Knapp»-Abend und eine kleine Umfrage, halb? Ute Sita Volmerg, im TapTab die Auseinandersetzungen spirituelle Lehrerin und s*AMAIKA &EELINGMIT2EG- erahnen lässt. So richtig re- Leiterin des Zentrums, GAE +àNSTLER2AY$ARWIN den will niemand – ausser gibt Auskunft im Wochen- s.EUE$OPPELAUSSTELLUNG ein paar Gelassenen. gespräch. im Forum Vebikus Mühlenstrasse 96, 8200 Schaffhausen, 052 644 01 01 [email protected], http://www.automaxx.ch Seiten 2 und 3 Seite 4 Seite 25 Donnerstag 2 DIE ZWEITE 10. April 2008 IMPRESSUM KOMMENTAR schaffhauser az Die Totalen tänzerische Einlagen neben der schon in diesem mittleren Ernst- Die Lokalzeitung für schnurgeraden Parteilinie, so- fall so gnadenlos sind? Aber Schaffhausen.
    [Show full text]
  • Video Lessons for Illustrative Mathematics: Grades 6-8 and Algebra I
    Video Lessons for Illustrative Mathematics: Grades 6-8 and Algebra I The Department, in partnership with Louisiana Public Broadcasting (LPB), Illustrative Math (IM), and SchoolKit selected 20 of the critical lessons in each grade level to broadcast on LPB in July of 2020. These lessons along with a few others are still available on demand on the SchoolKit website. To ensure accessibility for students with disabilities, all recorded on-demand videos are available with closed captioning and audio description. Updated on August 6, 2020 Video Lessons for Illustrative Math Grades 6-8 and Algebra I Background Information: Lessons were identified using the following criteria: 1. the most critical content of the grade level 2. content that many students missed due to school closures in the 2019-20 school year These lessons constitute only a portion of the critical lessons in each grade level. These lessons are available at the links below: • Grade 6: http://schoolkitgroup.com/video-grade-6/ • Grade 7: http://schoolkitgroup.com/video-grade-7/ • Grade 8: http://schoolkitgroup.com/video-grade-8/ • Algebra I: http://schoolkitgroup.com/video-algebra/ The tables below contain information on each of the lessons available for on-demand viewing with links to individual lessons embedded for each grade level. • Grade 6 Video Lesson List • Grade 7 Video Lesson List • Grade 8 Video Lesson List • Algebra I Video Lesson List Video Lessons for Illustrative Math Grades 6-8 and Algebra I Grade 6 Video Lesson List 6th Grade Illustrative Mathematics Units 2, 3,
    [Show full text]