Measure Theory and Probability

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Measure Theory and Probability Measure theory and probability Alexander Grigoryan University of Bielefeld Lecture Notes, October 2007 - February 2008 Contents 1 Construction of measures 3 1.1Introductionandexamples........................... 3 1.2 σ-additive measures ............................... 5 1.3 An example of using probability theory . .................. 7 1.4Extensionofmeasurefromsemi-ringtoaring................ 8 1.5 Extension of measure to a σ-algebra...................... 11 1.5.1 σ-rings and σ-algebras......................... 11 1.5.2 Outermeasure............................. 13 1.5.3 Symmetric difference.......................... 14 1.5.4 Measurable sets . ............................ 16 1.6 σ-finitemeasures................................ 20 1.7Nullsets..................................... 23 1.8 Lebesgue measure in Rn ............................ 25 1.8.1 Productmeasure............................ 25 1.8.2 Construction of measure in Rn. .................... 26 1.9 Probability spaces ................................ 28 1.10 Independence . ................................. 29 2 Integration 38 2.1 Measurable functions.............................. 38 2.2Sequencesofmeasurablefunctions....................... 42 2.3 The Lebesgue integral for finitemeasures................... 47 2.3.1 Simplefunctions............................ 47 2.3.2 Positivemeasurablefunctions..................... 49 2.3.3 Integrablefunctions........................... 52 2.4Integrationoversubsets............................ 56 2.5 The Lebesgue integral for σ-finitemeasure.................. 59 2.6 Convergence theorems............................. 61 2.7 Lebesgue function spaces Lp .......................... 68 2.7.1 The p-norm............................... 69 2.7.2 Spaces Lp ................................ 71 2.8ProductmeasuresandFubini’stheorem.................... 76 2.8.1 Productmeasure............................ 76 1 2.8.2 Cavalieriprinciple............................ 78 2.8.3 Fubini’stheorem............................ 83 3 Integration in Euclidean spaces and in probability spaces 86 3.1ChangeofvariablesinLebesgueintegral................... 86 3.2Randomvariablesandtheirdistributions...................100 3.3Functionalsofrandomvariables........................104 3.4Randomvectorsandjointdistributions....................106 3.5Independentrandomvariables.........................110 3.6Sequencesofrandomvariables.........................114 3.7Theweaklawoflargenumbers........................115 3.8Thestronglawoflargenumbers........................117 3.9 Extra material: the proof of the Weierstrass theorem using the weak law oflargenumbers................................121 2 1 Construction of measures 1.1 Introduction and examples Themainsubjectofthislecturecourseandthenotionofmeasure (Maß). The rigorous definition of measure will be given later, but now we can recall the familiar from the elementary mathematics notions, which are all particular cases of measure: 1. Length of intervals in R:ifI is a bounded interval with the endpoints a, b (that is, I is one of the intervals (a, b), [a, b], [a, b), (a, b]) then its length is defined by (I)= b a . | − | The useful property of the length is the additivity:ifanintervalI is a disjoint union of n a finite family Ik of intervals, that is, I = Ik,then { }k=1 k n F (I)= (Ik) . k=1 X N Indeed, let ai be the set of all distinct endpoints of the intervals I,I1,...,In enumer- { }i=0 ated in the increasing order. Then I has the endpoints a0,aN while each interval Ik has necessarily the endpoints ai,ai+1 for some i (indeed, if the endpoints of Ik are ai and aj with j>i+1 then the point ai+1 is an interior point of Ik, which means that Ik must in- tersect with some other interval Im). Conversely, any couple ai, ai+1 of consecutive points are the end points of some interval Ik (indeed, the interval (ai,ai+1) must be covered by some interval Ik; since the endpoints of Ik are consecutive numbers in the sequence aj , { } it follows that they are ai and ai+1). We conclude that N 1 n − (I)=aN a0 = (ai+1 ai)= (Ik) . − − i=0 k=1 X X 2. Area of domains in R2. The full notion of area will be constructed within the general measure theory later in this course. However, for rectangular domains the area is defined easily. A rectangle A in R2 is defined as the direct product of two intervals I,J from R: 2 A = I J = (x, y) R : x I,y J . × ∈ ∈ ∈ Then set © ª area (A)= (I) (J) . We claim that the area is also additive: if a rectangle A is a disjoint union of a finite family of rectangles A1,...,An,thatis,A = k Ak,then Fn area (A)= area (Ak) . k=1 X For simplicity, let us restrict the consideration to the case when all sides of all rectangles are semi-open intervals of the form [a, b).Considerfirst a particular case, when the 3 rectangles A1, ..., Ak form a regular tiling of A;thatis,letA = I J where I = Ii and × i J = Jj, and assume that all rectangles Ak have the form Ii Jj.Then j × F F area (A)= (I) (J)= (Ii) (Jj)= (Ii) (Jj)= area (Ak) . i j i,j k X X X X Now consider the general case when A is an arbitrary disjoint union of rectangles Ak. Let xi be the set of all X-coordinates of the endpoints of the rectangles Ak put in { } the increasing order, and yj be similarly the set of all the Y -coordinates, also in the increasing order. Consider{ the} rectangles Bij =[xi,xi+1) [yj,yj+1). × Then the family Bij forms a regular tiling of A and, by the first case, { }i,j area (A)= area (Bij) . i,j X On the other hand, each Ak is a disjoint union of some of Bij, and, moreover, those Bij that are subsets of Ak, form a regular tiling of Ak, which implies that area(Ak)= area (Bij) . Bij A X⊂ k Combining the previous two lines and using the fact that each Bij is a subset of exactly one set Ak,weobtain area (Ak)= area (Bij)= area (Bij)=area(A) . k k Bij A i,j X X X⊂ k X 3. Volume of domains in R3. The construction is similar to the area. Consider all boxes in R3, that is, the domains of the form A = I J K where I,J,K are intervals × × in R, and set vol (A)= (I) (J) (K) . Then volume is also an additive functional, which is proved in a similar way. Later on, we will give the detailed proof of a similar statement in an abstract setting. 4. Probability is another example of an additive functional. In probability theory, one considers a set Ω of elementary events, and certain subsets of Ω are called events (Ereignisse). For each event A Ω, one assigns the probability, which is denoted by ⊂ P (A) and which is a real number in [0, 1]. A reasonably defined probability must satisfy the additivity: if the event A is a disjoint union of a finite sequence of evens A1, ..., An then n P (A)= P (Ak) . k=1 X The fact that Ai and Aj are disjoint, when i = j, means that the events Ai and Aj cannot occur at the same time. 6 Thecommonfeatureofalltheaboveexampleisthefollowing.Wearegivenanon- empty set M (which in the above example was R, R2, R3, Ω), a family S of its subsets (the 4 families of intervals, rectangles, boxes, events), and a functional μ : S R+ := [0, + ) (length, area, volume, probability) with the following property: if A → S is a disjoint∞ n ∈ union of a finite family Ak of sets from S then { }k=1 n μ (A)= μ (Ak) . k=1 X A functional μ with this property is called a finitely additive measure. Hence, length, area, volume, probability are all finitely additive measures. 1.2 σ-additive measures As above, let M be an arbitrary non-empty set and S be a family of subsets of M. Definition. A functional μ : S R+ is called a σ-additive measure if whenever a set → N A S is a disjoint union of an at most countable sequence Ak k=1 (where N is either finite∈ or N = )then { } ∞ N μ (A)= μ (Ak) . k=1 X If N = then the above sum is understood as a series. If this property holds only for finite values∞ of N then μ is a finitely additive measure. Clearly, a σ-additive measure is also finitely additive (but the converse is not true). At first, the difference between finitely additive and σ-additive measures might look in- significant, but the σ-additivity provides much more possibilities for applications and is one of the central issues of the measure theory. On the other hand, it is normally more difficult to prove σ-additivity. Theorem 1.1 The length is a σ-additive measure on the family of all bounded intervals in R. Before we prove this theorem, consider a simpler property. N Definition. A functional μ : S R+ is called σ-subadditive if whenever A Ak → ⊂ k=1 where A and all Ak areelementsofS and N is either finite or infinite, then S N μ (A) μ (Ak) . ≤ k=1 X If this property holds only for finite values of N then μ is called finitely subadditive. Lemma 1.2 The length is σ-subadditive. Proof. Let I, Ik ∞ be intervals such that I ∞ Ik and let us prove that { }k=1 ⊂ k=1 ∞ S (I) (Ik) ≤ k=1 X 5 (the case N< follows from the case N = byaddingtheemptyinterval).Letusfix ∞ ∞ some ε>0 and choose a bounded closed interval I0 I such that ⊂ (I) (I0)+ε. ≤ For any k,chooseanopen interval I0 Ik such that k ⊃ ε (I0 ) (Ik)+ . k ≤ 2k Then the bounded closed interval I0 is covered by a sequence Ik0 of open intervals. By n{ } the Borel-Lebesgue lemma, there is a finite subfamily Ik0 that also covers I0.It j j=1 follows from the finite additivity of length that it is finitelyn subadditive,o that is, (I0) (Ik0 j ), ≤ j X (see Exercise 7), which implies that ∞ (I0) (I0 ) . ≤ k k=1 X This yields ∞ ε ∞ l (I) ε + (Ik)+ =2ε + (Ik) . ≤ 2k k=1 k=1 X ³ ´ X Since ε>0 is arbitrary, letting ε 0 we finish the proof. → Proof of Theorem 1.1. We need to prove that if I = k∞=1 Ik then ∞ F (I)= (Ik) k=1 X ByLemma1.2,wehaveimmediately ∞ (I) (Ik) ≤ k=1 X sowearelefttoprovetheoppositeinequality.Foranyfixed n N,wehave ∈ n I Ik.
Recommended publications
  • Measure-Theoretic Probability I
    Measure-Theoretic Probability I Steven P.Lalley Winter 2017 1 1 Measure Theory 1.1 Why Measure Theory? There are two different views – not necessarily exclusive – on what “probability” means: the subjectivist view and the frequentist view. To the subjectivist, probability is a system of laws that should govern a rational person’s behavior in situations where a bet must be placed (not necessarily just in a casino, but in situations where a decision must be made about how to proceed when only imperfect information about the outcome of the decision is available, for instance, should I allow Dr. Scissorhands to replace my arthritic knee by a plastic joint?). To the frequentist, the laws of probability describe the long- run relative frequencies of different events in “experiments” that can be repeated under roughly identical conditions, for instance, rolling a pair of dice. For the frequentist inter- pretation, it is imperative that probability spaces be large enough to allow a description of an experiment, like dice-rolling, that is repeated infinitely many times, and that the mathematical laws should permit easy handling of limits, so that one can make sense of things like “the probability that the long-run fraction of dice rolls where the two dice sum to 7 is 1/6”. But even for the subjectivist, the laws of probability should allow for description of situations where there might be a continuum of possible outcomes, or pos- sible actions to be taken. Once one is reconciled to the need for such flexibility, it soon becomes apparent that measure theory (the theory of countably additive, as opposed to merely finitely additive measures) is the only way to go.
    [Show full text]
  • Probability and Statistics Lecture Notes
    Probability and Statistics Lecture Notes Antonio Jiménez-Martínez Chapter 1 Probability spaces In this chapter we introduce the theoretical structures that will allow us to assign proba- bilities in a wide range of probability problems. 1.1. Examples of random phenomena Science attempts to formulate general laws on the basis of observation and experiment. The simplest and most used scheme of such laws is: if a set of conditions B is satisfied =) event A occurs. Examples of such laws are the law of gravity, the law of conservation of mass, and many other instances in chemistry, physics, biology... If event A occurs inevitably whenever the set of conditions B is satisfied, we say that A is certain or sure (under the set of conditions B). If A can never occur whenever B is satisfied, we say that A is impossible (under the set of conditions B). If A may or may not occur whenever B is satisfied, then A is said to be a random phenomenon. Random phenomena is our subject matter. Unlike certain and impossible events, the presence of randomness implies that the set of conditions B do not reflect all the necessary and sufficient conditions for the event A to occur. It might seem them impossible to make any worthwhile statements about random phenomena. However, experience has shown that many random phenomena exhibit a statistical regularity that makes them subject to study. For such random phenomena it is possible to estimate the chance of occurrence of the random event. This estimate can be obtained from laws, called probabilistic or stochastic, with the form: if a set of conditions B is satisfied event A occurs m times =) repeatedly n times out of the n repetitions.
    [Show full text]
  • Version of 21.8.15 Chapter 43 Topologies and Measures II The
    Version of 21.8.15 Chapter 43 Topologies and measures II The first chapter of this volume was ‘general’ theory of topological measure spaces; I attempted to distinguish the most important properties a topological measure can have – inner regularity, τ-additivity – and describe their interactions at an abstract level. I now turn to rather more specialized investigations, looking for features which offer explanations of the behaviour of the most important spaces, radiating outwards from Lebesgue measure. In effect, this chapter consists of three distinguishable parts and two appendices. The first three sections are based on ideas from descriptive set theory, in particular Souslin’s operation (§431); the properties of this operation are the foundation for the theory of two classes of topological space of particular importance in measure theory, the K-analytic spaces (§432) and the analytic spaces (§433). The second part of the chapter, §§434-435, collects miscellaneous results on Borel and Baire measures, looking at the ways in which topological properties of a space determine properties of the measures it carries. In §436 I present the most important theorems on the representation of linear functionals by integrals; if you like, this is the inverse operation to the construction of integrals from measures in §122. The ideas continue into §437, where I discuss spaces of signed measures representing the duals of spaces of continuous functions, and topologies on spaces of measures. The first appendix, §438, looks at a special topic: the way in which the patterns in §§434-435 are affected if we assume that our spaces are not unreasonably complex in a rather special sense defined in terms of measures on discrete spaces.
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Measure Theory Terence
    An introduction to measure theory Terence Tao Department of Mathematics, UCLA, Los Angeles, CA 90095 E-mail address: [email protected] To Garth Gaudry, who set me on the road; To my family, for their constant support; And to the readers of my blog, for their feedback and contributions. Contents Preface ix Notation x Acknowledgments xvi Chapter 1. Measure theory 1 x1.1. Prologue: The problem of measure 2 x1.2. Lebesgue measure 17 x1.3. The Lebesgue integral 46 x1.4. Abstract measure spaces 79 x1.5. Modes of convergence 114 x1.6. Differentiation theorems 131 x1.7. Outer measures, pre-measures, and product measures 179 Chapter 2. Related articles 209 x2.1. Problem solving strategies 210 x2.2. The Radamacher differentiation theorem 226 x2.3. Probability spaces 232 x2.4. Infinite product spaces and the Kolmogorov extension theorem 235 Bibliography 243 vii viii Contents Index 245 Preface In the fall of 2010, I taught an introductory one-quarter course on graduate real analysis, focusing in particular on the basics of mea- sure and integration theory, both in Euclidean spaces and in abstract measure spaces. This text is based on my lecture notes of that course, which are also available online on my blog terrytao.wordpress.com, together with some supplementary material, such as a section on prob- lem solving strategies in real analysis (Section 2.1) which evolved from discussions with my students. This text is intended to form a prequel to my graduate text [Ta2010] (henceforth referred to as An epsilon of room, Vol. I ), which is an introduction to the analysis of Hilbert and Banach spaces (such as Lp and Sobolev spaces), point-set topology, and related top- ics such as Fourier analysis and the theory of distributions; together, they serve as a text for a complete first-year graduate course in real analysis.
    [Show full text]
  • Measure, Integral and Probability
    Marek Capinski´ and Ekkehard Kopp Measure, Integral and Probability Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg NewYork London Paris Tokyo Hong Kong Barcelona Budapest To our children; grandchildren: Piotr, Maciej, Jan, Anna; Luk asz Anna, Emily Preface The central concepts in this book are Lebesgue measure and the Lebesgue integral. Their role as standard fare in UK undergraduate mathematics courses is not wholly secure; yet they provide the principal model for the development of the abstract measure spaces which underpin modern probability theory, while the Lebesgue function spaces remain the main source of examples on which to test the methods of functional analysis and its many applications, such as Fourier analysis and the theory of partial differential equations. It follows that not only budding analysts have need of a clear understanding of the construction and properties of measures and integrals, but also that those who wish to contribute seriously to the applications of analytical methods in a wide variety of areas of mathematics, physics, electronics, engineering and, most recently, finance, need to study the underlying theory with some care. We have found remarkably few texts in the current literature which aim explicitly to provide for these needs, at a level accessible to current under- graduates. There are many good books on modern probability theory, and increasingly they recognize the need for a strong grounding in the tools we develop in this book, but all too often the treatment is either too advanced for an undergraduate audience or else somewhat perfunctory. We hope therefore that the current text will not be regarded as one which fills a much-needed gap in the literature! One fundamental decision in developing a treatment of integration is whether to begin with measures or integrals, i.e.
    [Show full text]
  • Determinism, Indeterminism and the Statistical Postulate
    Tipicality, Explanation, The Statistical Postulate, and GRW Valia Allori Northern Illinois University [email protected] www.valiaallori.com Rutgers, October 24-26, 2019 1 Overview Context: Explanation of the macroscopic laws of thermodynamics in the Boltzmannian approach Among the ingredients: the statistical postulate (connected with the notion of probability) In this presentation: typicality Def: P is a typical property of X-type object/phenomena iff the vast majority of objects/phenomena of type X possesses P Part I: typicality is sufficient to explain macroscopic laws – explanatory schema based on typicality: you explain P if you explain that P is typical Part II: the statistical postulate as derivable from the dynamics Part III: if so, no preference for indeterministic theories in the quantum domain 2 Summary of Boltzmann- 1 Aim: ‘derive’ macroscopic laws of thermodynamics in terms of the microscopic Newtonian dynamics Problems: Technical ones: There are to many particles to do exact calculations Solution: statistical methods - if 푁 is big enough, one can use suitable mathematical technique to obtain information of macro systems even without having the exact solution Conceptual ones: Macro processes are irreversible, while micro processes are not Boltzmann 3 Summary of Boltzmann- 2 Postulate 1: the microscopic dynamics microstate 푋 = 푟1, … . 푟푁, 푣1, … . 푣푁 in phase space Partition of phase space into Macrostates Macrostate 푀(푋): set of macroscopically indistinguishable microstates Macroscopic view Many 푋 for a given 푀 given 푀, which 푋 is unknown Macro Properties (e.g. temperature): they slowly vary on the Macro scale There is a particular Macrostate which is incredibly bigger than the others There are many ways more to have, for instance, uniform temperature than not equilibrium (Macro)state 4 Summary of Boltzmann- 3 Entropy: (def) proportional to the size of the Macrostate in phase space (i.e.
    [Show full text]
  • The Axiom of Choice and Its Implications
    THE AXIOM OF CHOICE AND ITS IMPLICATIONS KEVIN BARNUM Abstract. In this paper we will look at the Axiom of Choice and some of the various implications it has. These implications include a number of equivalent statements, and also some less accepted ideas. The proofs discussed will give us an idea of why the Axiom of Choice is so powerful, but also so controversial. Contents 1. Introduction 1 2. The Axiom of Choice and Its Equivalents 1 2.1. The Axiom of Choice and its Well-known Equivalents 1 2.2. Some Other Less Well-known Equivalents of the Axiom of Choice 3 3. Applications of the Axiom of Choice 5 3.1. Equivalence Between The Axiom of Choice and the Claim that Every Vector Space has a Basis 5 3.2. Some More Applications of the Axiom of Choice 6 4. Controversial Results 10 Acknowledgments 11 References 11 1. Introduction The Axiom of Choice states that for any family of nonempty disjoint sets, there exists a set that consists of exactly one element from each element of the family. It seems strange at first that such an innocuous sounding idea can be so powerful and controversial, but it certainly is both. To understand why, we will start by looking at some statements that are equivalent to the axiom of choice. Many of these equivalences are very useful, and we devote much time to one, namely, that every vector space has a basis. We go on from there to see a few more applications of the Axiom of Choice and its equivalents, and finish by looking at some of the reasons why the Axiom of Choice is so controversial.
    [Show full text]
  • Topic 1: Basic Probability Definition of Sets
    Topic 1: Basic probability ² Review of sets ² Sample space and probability measure ² Probability axioms ² Basic probability laws ² Conditional probability ² Bayes' rules ² Independence ² Counting ES150 { Harvard SEAS 1 De¯nition of Sets ² A set S is a collection of objects, which are the elements of the set. { The number of elements in a set S can be ¯nite S = fx1; x2; : : : ; xng or in¯nite but countable S = fx1; x2; : : :g or uncountably in¯nite. { S can also contain elements with a certain property S = fx j x satis¯es P g ² S is a subset of T if every element of S also belongs to T S ½ T or T S If S ½ T and T ½ S then S = T . ² The universal set ­ is the set of all objects within a context. We then consider all sets S ½ ­. ES150 { Harvard SEAS 2 Set Operations and Properties ² Set operations { Complement Ac: set of all elements not in A { Union A \ B: set of all elements in A or B or both { Intersection A [ B: set of all elements common in both A and B { Di®erence A ¡ B: set containing all elements in A but not in B. ² Properties of set operations { Commutative: A \ B = B \ A and A [ B = B [ A. (But A ¡ B 6= B ¡ A). { Associative: (A \ B) \ C = A \ (B \ C) = A \ B \ C. (also for [) { Distributive: A \ (B [ C) = (A \ B) [ (A \ C) A [ (B \ C) = (A [ B) \ (A [ C) { DeMorgan's laws: (A \ B)c = Ac [ Bc (A [ B)c = Ac \ Bc ES150 { Harvard SEAS 3 Elements of probability theory A probabilistic model includes ² The sample space ­ of an experiment { set of all possible outcomes { ¯nite or in¯nite { discrete or continuous { possibly multi-dimensional ² An event A is a set of outcomes { a subset of the sample space, A ½ ­.
    [Show full text]
  • Ground and Explanation in Mathematics
    volume 19, no. 33 ncreased attention has recently been paid to the fact that in math- august 2019 ematical practice, certain mathematical proofs but not others are I recognized as explaining why the theorems they prove obtain (Mancosu 2008; Lange 2010, 2015a, 2016; Pincock 2015). Such “math- ematical explanation” is presumably not a variety of causal explana- tion. In addition, the role of metaphysical grounding as underwriting a variety of explanations has also recently received increased attention Ground and Explanation (Correia and Schnieder 2012; Fine 2001, 2012; Rosen 2010; Schaffer 2016). Accordingly, it is natural to wonder whether mathematical ex- planation is a variety of grounding explanation. This paper will offer several arguments that it is not. in Mathematics One obstacle facing these arguments is that there is currently no widely accepted account of either mathematical explanation or grounding. In the case of mathematical explanation, I will try to avoid this obstacle by appealing to examples of proofs that mathematicians themselves have characterized as explanatory (or as non-explanatory). I will offer many examples to avoid making my argument too dependent on any single one of them. I will also try to motivate these characterizations of various proofs as (non-) explanatory by proposing an account of what makes a proof explanatory. In the case of grounding, I will try to stick with features of grounding that are relatively uncontroversial among grounding theorists. But I will also Marc Lange look briefly at how some of my arguments would fare under alternative views of grounding. I hope at least to reveal something about what University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill grounding would have to look like in order for a theorem’s grounds to mathematically explain why that theorem obtains.
    [Show full text]
  • Old Notes from Warwick, Part 1
    Measure Theory, MA 359 Handout 1 Valeriy Slastikov Autumn, 2005 1 Measure theory 1.1 General construction of Lebesgue measure In this section we will do the general construction of σ-additive complete measure by extending initial σ-additive measure on a semi-ring to a measure on σ-algebra generated by this semi-ring and then completing this measure by adding to the σ-algebra all the null sets. This section provides you with the essentials of the construction and make some parallels with the construction on the plane. Throughout these section we will deal with some collection of sets whose elements are subsets of some fixed abstract set X. It is not necessary to assume any topology on X but for simplicity you may imagine X = Rn. We start with some important definitions: Definition 1.1 A nonempty collection of sets S is a semi-ring if 1. Empty set ? 2 S; 2. If A 2 S; B 2 S then A \ B 2 S; n 3. If A 2 S; A ⊃ A1 2 S then A = [k=1Ak, where Ak 2 S for all 1 ≤ k ≤ n and Ak are disjoint sets. If the set X 2 S then S is called semi-algebra, the set X is called a unit of the collection of sets S. Example 1.1 The collection S of intervals [a; b) for all a; b 2 R form a semi-ring since 1. empty set ? = [a; a) 2 S; 2. if A 2 S and B 2 S then A = [a; b) and B = [c; d).
    [Show full text]
  • Some Topologies Connected with Lebesgue Measure Séminaire De Probabilités (Strasbourg), Tome 5 (1971), P
    SÉMINAIRE DE PROBABILITÉS (STRASBOURG) JOHN B. WALSH Some topologies connected with Lebesgue measure Séminaire de probabilités (Strasbourg), tome 5 (1971), p. 290-310 <http://www.numdam.org/item?id=SPS_1971__5__290_0> © Springer-Verlag, Berlin Heidelberg New York, 1971, tous droits réservés. L’accès aux archives du séminaire de probabilités (Strasbourg) (http://portail. mathdoc.fr/SemProba/) implique l’accord avec les conditions générales d’utili- sation (http://www.numdam.org/conditions). Toute utilisation commerciale ou im- pression systématique est constitutive d’une infraction pénale. Toute copie ou im- pression de ce fichier doit contenir la présente mention de copyright. Article numérisé dans le cadre du programme Numérisation de documents anciens mathématiques http://www.numdam.org/ SOME TOPOLOGIES CONNECTED WITH LEBESGUE MEASURE J. B. Walsh One of the nettles flourishing in the nether regions of the field of continuous parameter processes is the quantity lim sup X. s-~ t When one most wants to use it, he can’t show it is measurable. A theorem of Doob asserts that one can always modify the process slightly so that it becomes in which case lim sup is the same separable, X~ s-t as its less relative lim where D is a countable prickly sup X, set. If, as sometimes happens, one is not free to change the process, the usual procedure is to use the countable limit anyway and hope that the process is continuous. Chung and Walsh [3] used the idea of an essential limit-that is a limit ignoring sets of Lebesgue measure and found that it enjoyed the pleasant measurability and separability properties of the countable limit in addition to being translation invariant.
    [Show full text]
  • (Measure Theory for Dummies) UWEE Technical Report Number UWEETR-2006-0008
    A Measure Theory Tutorial (Measure Theory for Dummies) Maya R. Gupta {gupta}@ee.washington.edu Dept of EE, University of Washington Seattle WA, 98195-2500 UWEE Technical Report Number UWEETR-2006-0008 May 2006 Department of Electrical Engineering University of Washington Box 352500 Seattle, Washington 98195-2500 PHN: (206) 543-2150 FAX: (206) 543-3842 URL: http://www.ee.washington.edu A Measure Theory Tutorial (Measure Theory for Dummies) Maya R. Gupta {gupta}@ee.washington.edu Dept of EE, University of Washington Seattle WA, 98195-2500 University of Washington, Dept. of EE, UWEETR-2006-0008 May 2006 Abstract This tutorial is an informal introduction to measure theory for people who are interested in reading papers that use measure theory. The tutorial assumes one has had at least a year of college-level calculus, some graduate level exposure to random processes, and familiarity with terms like “closed” and “open.” The focus is on the terms and ideas relevant to applied probability and information theory. There are no proofs and no exercises. Measure theory is a bit like grammar, many people communicate clearly without worrying about all the details, but the details do exist and for good reasons. There are a number of great texts that do measure theory justice. This is not one of them. Rather this is a hack way to get the basic ideas down so you can read through research papers and follow what’s going on. Hopefully, you’ll get curious and excited enough about the details to check out some of the references for a deeper understanding.
    [Show full text]