John Stuart Mill on Justice and Self-Development Gustavo

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

John Stuart Mill on Justice and Self-Development Gustavo John Stuart Mill on justice and self-development Gustavo Hessmann Dalaqua – UFPR [email protected] Proofread by Malcolm Clark (ESL teacher, Curitiba). [email protected] ABSTRACT: This paper deals with John Stuart Mill’s account of justice, which posits a strong relationship between justice, morality and self-development. According to Mill, law and morality can be seen in two different ways: (i) as something that never changes; (ii) as something that can be put into question and improved. Endorsing the latter, Mill is going to advance a creative morality that attaches justice to debate. Justice requires public discussion and constant critical examination of law. Sometimes it requires even breaking up with the law; civil disobedience is an example of that. For Mill, justice cannot do without individual critical thinking, conscience and self-development. Indeed, self-development is the sine qua non of justice. One can only care for others if one has cared for one’s self. Key words: John Stuart Mill; justice; self-development; civil disobedience. RESUMO: Este artigo trata da questão da justiça no pensamento de John Stuart Mill, segundo o qual há uma relação forte entre justiça, moralidade e desenvolvimento de si. De acordo com o autor, lei e moralidade podem ser vistas de duas maneiras distintas: (i) como algo que nunca muda; (ii) como algo passível de ser questionado e aperfeiçoado. Endossando a segunda visão, Mill irá postular uma moral criativa que liga justiça e debate. A justiça requer discussão pública e um constante exame crítico da lei. Por vezes, requer inclusive uma ruptura com a lei; a desobediência civil é um exemplo disto. Para Mill, não há justiça sem pensamento crítico individual, consciência e desenvolvimento do eu. Com efeito, o desenvolvimento de si é condição sine qua non da justiça. Somente quem cuida de si é capaz de se importar com outrem. Palavras-chave: John Stuart Mill; justiça; desenvolvimento de si; desobediência civil. 1 I would like to talk about John Stuart Mill’s thinking on justice, and to do it in a thirty-minute presentation is only acceptable because my speaking a whole afternoon on the subject would be nearly as incomplete. “What is justice?” – Philosophy has puzzled itself with this question from time immemorial, and I assume no one here is expecting to get back home with an answer that could work once and for all. That would be against the very nature of our colloquia. For if we are expected to meet year after year to discuss justice, then something must have changed. It would be simply a waste of time to meet again if nothing new came up. Time and again we gather and endeavor to pose the question anew: “What is justice?”. This proves, if it needs proving, how provisional our consensus on the issue is. Now and then people assemble not only to debate but also to demand justice (we shall return to this issue when talking about civil disobedience). Justice has been out and about, on people’s lips, on the streets; indeed one can scarcely think of a political revolution or a public turmoil in which it has not been of prime concern. And here lies the chief difficulty in studying justice nowadays. Since it is so stored with past echoes and conflicting associations, justice cannot be captured by a single and indisputable definition. That is why I shall concentrate mainly on Mill and see what he has to say about justice. Initially the question of justice seems to be confined only to Utilitarianism, and when scholars want to discuss Mill’s thinking on justice, that work is usually where they turn to. In Utilitarianism’s final chapter, we read: “justice is a name for certain moral requirements” that belong to “social utility” (MILL, 1861: 200). Justice, Mill believes, is grounded not on an absolute, transcendental standard but rather on social utility, that is to say, on human happiness and well-being. Far from being immutable, social utility is a historical phenomenon which changes over time; what is considered useful for one age may not be so for the next. That which one generation regarded as conducive to human well-being can become burdensome or even contrary to happiness for the next generation. The way we look at utility is established and improved through public debate and social intercourse (cf. MILL, 1859: 41). Justice and utility, in short, are open to discussion and a fortiori can only be sustained through debate, in the broad sense of the word. Justice, I shall argue, 2 requires public debate as well as inner debate, an activity which one exercises through self-development. Justice is anchored in self-development and is conducive to human happiness. Happiness should not be mistaken for contentment. It is not merely a succession of pleasant mental states; when Mill speaks of happiness, as Rawls has noticed, he means “a way of life” (RAWLS, 2007: 259). One is happy insofar as one leads a critical way of life and cares for one’s self. Those who passively conform to society’s mandates and do not develop an intelligent relationship with them cannot be called happy, and are not properly speaking individuals. According to Mill, being an individual presupposes the ability to develop and care for his or her self, which in turn allows the individual to gain some distance from his or her background, whereupon critique becomes feasible. Self-development and the critical thinking thereby produced are essential for justice. In what follows, my aim will be simply to underscore the relationship between justice and self-development, a theme scholars often neglect when talking about Mill’s thinking on justice. When Mill asks himself, “What is justice?”, he notices people have different answers for it. Mill writes from a background of assumed conflict and knows that he cannot rely on a shared opinion, for there is none. People began to conceive justice in different ways in the nineteenth century and that is why an all-embracing definition will not do. In genealogical fashion, Mill then attempts to trace the genesis of the concept “justice” and turns back to the Greeks and Romans. I quote him: Among so many diverse applications of the term Justice . it is a matter of some difficulty to seize the link which holds them together. Perhaps, in this embarrassment, some help may be derived from the history of the word, as indicated by its etymology. In most, if not in all, languages, the etymology of the word which corresponds to Just, points to an origin connected either with positive law, or with that which was in most cases the primitive form of law — authoritative custom. Justum is a form of jussum, that which has been ordered. Jus is of the same origin Δίκαιον comes from δίκη, of which the principal meaning, at least in the historical ages of Greece, was a suit at law. Originally, indeed, it meant only the mode or manner of doing things, but it early came to mean the prescribed manner; that which the recognized authorities, patriarchal, judicial, or political, would enforce (MILL, 1861: 181-2). 3 The concept of “justice” was connected with “law” and “custom” both in Rome and Greece. It meant conformity to a set of prescriptions which were imposed upon the individual by an external authority, which was not necessarily judicial. Usually the source of authority was what determined whether the prescription was a “law” or “custom”. Such distinction, according to Mill, remained valid in nineteenth century and still makes sense in our time (cf. MILL, 1859: 23ff). For one thing, it seems safe to say that laws and customs are not the same. Laws are prescriptions issued by a judicial authority. When one disrespects them, the punishment one faces is exercised mainly by juridical institutions, such as the police. Customs, by contrast, are not necessarily regulated by judicial power. Usually they are imposed upon us by non-juridical power mechanisms and the punishment we get when we disobey them is of a different nature. Mill offers an interesting analysis of how such extra juridical power shapes individual conduct, but to explain it here would lead us too far afield. So far what the etymology of the word has revealed is that the concept of justice is not exclusively juridical. Justice is much more than a legal matter; it signifies acting in conformity not only to law but also to custom. Thus we are led to the questions: what is law and what is custom? According to Mill, both can be seen in two ways: (i) something man-made that can be changed; (ii) something sacred and immutable that emanates directly “from the Supreme Being” (MILL, 1861: 182). To each one there is a corresponding morality: (i) a morality of creation, that is to say, a creative morality; (ii) a morality of passive obedience, where one is not expected to question but only to conform to the never changing law and custom. It is Mill’s view that since the birth of Christianity morality (ii) has been superseded by (i) and, not surprisingly, his proposal will be to favor the latter and reverse or relieve, so to speak, the harmful effects of institutionalized Christianity. Ancient ethics functions as a model for modern morality. As those who are familiar with the etymology of the word may probably know, ethics derives from the Greek word êthos. The concept, according to Mill, has a twofold meaning (MILL, 1843: 54). On its collective aspect, êthos means the guiding principles and beliefs of a community. 4 On the individual level, it means an attitude opposed to blind obedience, a way of life, as it were, in which individuals breed an active relationship with their community precepts and “fashion themselves” (MILL, 1859: 26).
Recommended publications
  • Civil Disobedience
    Civil Disobedience Henry David Toreau Civil Disobedience Henry David Toreau Foreword by Connor Boyack Libertas Institute Salt Lake City, Utah Civil Disobedience Thoreau’s essay is out of copyright and in the public domain; this version is lightly edited for modernization. Supplemental essays are copyrighted by their respective authors and included with permission. The foreword is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution- ShareAlike 3.0 Unported License. LIBERTAS PRESS 770 E. MAIN STREET, SUITE 255 LEHI, UT 84043 Civil Disobedience / Henry David Toreau — 1st ed. First printing, June 2014 Cover Design by Ben Jenkins Manufactured in the United States of America For bulk orders, send inquiries to: [email protected] ISBN-13: 978-0-9892912-3-1 dedicated to Edward Snowden for doing what was right “Te most foolish notion of all is the belief that everything is just which is found in the customs or laws of nations. Would that be true, even if these laws had been enacted by tyrants?” “What of the many deadly, the many pestilential statutes which nations put in force? Tese no more deserve to be called laws than the rules a band of robbers might pass in their assembly. For if ignorant and unskillful men have prescribed deadly poisons instead of healing drugs, these cannot possibly be called physicians’ prescriptions; neither in a nation can a statute of any sort be called a law, even though the nation, in spite of being a ruinous regulation, has accepted it.” —Cicero Foreword by Connor Boyack Americans know Henry David Thoreau as the author of Walden, a narrative published in 1854 detailing the author’s life at Walden Pond, on property owned by his friend Ralph Waldo Emerson near Concord, Massachusetts.
    [Show full text]
  • Civil Disobedience Civics Is All Around Us
    Civics in Real Life Civil Disobedience Civics is all around us. There is a lot to know about the government and how “We the People” interact with the government and each other. Let’s help each other expand our civic literacy. The United States is a nation that emerged out of protest. Drawing on the principles of natural rights and consent of the governed, voting for change, marching to demand action, and petitioning leaders are ways in which “we the people” fight injustice and inequality. Sometimes, public protests fail, leading some to engage in civil disobedience. Civil disobedience is a form of public protest that involves taking action against unjust laws. These actions may take several forms although most acts of civil disobedience involve intentionally violating a law in order to demonstrate opposition to unjust policy and demand change. Nineteenth century writer Henry David Thoreau, a strong advocate of civil disobedience, argued that if the law “...is of such a nature that it requires you to be the agent of injustice to another, then I say, break the law.” In his own act of civil disobedience, Thoreau refused to pay taxes that could support slavery and war, and went to jail for it. Acts of civil disobedience may involve knowingly breaking an unjust law and facing the consequences (such as arrest and jail time), in order to draw attention to the injustice or to force change. One of the most well- known examples of protest is the 381-day Montgomery Bus Boycott, which was launched in opposition to segregated bus seating that made it illegal for African Americans to sit in front of Whites on the bus.
    [Show full text]
  • Hong Kong's Civil Disobedience Under China's Authoritarianism
    Emory International Law Review Volume 35 Issue 1 2021 Hong Kong's Civil Disobedience Under China's Authoritarianism Shucheng Wang Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarlycommons.law.emory.edu/eilr Recommended Citation Shucheng Wang, Hong Kong's Civil Disobedience Under China's Authoritarianism, 35 Emory Int'l L. Rev. 21 (2021). Available at: https://scholarlycommons.law.emory.edu/eilr/vol35/iss1/2 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at Emory Law Scholarly Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Emory International Law Review by an authorized editor of Emory Law Scholarly Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. WANG_2.9.21 2/10/2021 1:03 PM HONG KONG’S CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE UNDER CHINA’S AUTHORITARIANISM Shucheng Wang∗ ABSTRACT Acts of civil disobedience have significantly impacted Hong Kong’s liberal constitutional order, existing as it does under China’s authoritarian governance. Existing theories of civil disobedience have primarily paid attention to the situations of liberal democracies but find it difficult to explain the unique case of the semi-democracy of Hong Kong. Based on a descriptive analysis of the practice of civil disobedience in Hong Kong, taking the Occupy Central Movement (OCM) of 2014 and the Anti-Extradition Law Amendment Bill (Anti-ELAB) movement of 2019 as examples, this Article explores the extent to which and how civil disobedience can be justified in Hong Kong’s rule of law- based order under China’s authoritarian system, and further aims to develop a conditional theory of civil disobedience for Hong Kong that goes beyond traditional liberal accounts.
    [Show full text]
  • Victory Briefs
    Victory Briefs Resolved: Civil disobedience in a democracy is morally justified. September-October Novice LD Topic∗ ∗Published by Victory Briefs, PO Box 803338 #40503, Chicago, IL 60680-3338. Edited by Jake Nebel and Chris Theis. Written by Chetan Hertzig, Jerry Chen, and Nick Smith. Evidence cut by authors. For customer support, please email [email protected] or call 330.333.2283. Transaction: 4731 - September 9, 2014 - This product is licensed to: Wilson Wyatt Debate League - [email protected] by Victory Briefs. Any distribution or modification of this file not explicitly allowed by the terms of purchase (including removing or obscuring this text) is a violation of copyright. Please report illicit distribution of this file to [email protected] Contents 1 Introduction 4 2 Topic Analysis by Chetan Hertzig 5 2.1 Background ................................... 5 2.2 What the Resolution Means .......................... 7 2.3 Affirmative Arguments ............................. 10 2.4 Negative Arguments .............................. 14 2.5 Full Text of Evidence Above .......................... 17 2.6 Full Definitions ................................. 17 2.7 Affirmative Evidence .............................. 20 2.8 Negative Evidence ............................... 25 3 Topic Analysis by Jerry Chen 29 3.1 Background Information ............................ 29 3.2 Resolutional Analysis and Definitions ..................... 30 3.3 Framework Issues ................................ 31 3.4 Affirmative Arguments ............................
    [Show full text]
  • Gandhi: Sources and Influences. a Curriculum Guide. Fulbright-Hays Summer Seminars Abroad, 1997 (India)
    DOCUMENT RESUME ED 421 419 SO 029 067 AUTHOR Ragan, Paul TITLE Gandhi: Sources and Influences. A CurriculumGuide. Fulbright-Hays SummerSeminars Abroad, SPONS AGENCY United States 1997 (India). Educational Foundationin India. PUB DATE 1997-00-00 NOTE 28p.; For other curriculum projectreports by 1997 seminar participants, see SO029 068-086. Seminar Her Ethos." title: "India and PUB TYPE Guides - Classroom EDRS PRICE - Teacher (052) MF01/PCO2 PlusPostage. DESCRIPTORS Asian Studies;Civil Disobedience; Culture; Ethnic Cultural Awareness; Groups; ForeignCountries; High Schools; *Indians; Instructional Materials;Interdisciplinary Approach; NonWestern Civilization; Social Studies;*World History; *WorldLiterature IDENTIFIERS Dalai Lama; *Gandhi (Mahatma); *India;King (Martin Luther Jr); Thoreau (HenryDavid) ABSTRACT This unit isintended for secondary literature, Asian students in American history, U.S. history,or a world cultures emphasis is placedon the literary class. Special David Thoreau, contributions of fourindividuals: Henry Mahatma Gandhi,Martin Luther King, The sections Jr., and the DalaiLama. appear in chronologicalorder and contain strategies that objectives and are designed tovary the materials the daily activities. students use in their Study questionsand suggested included. Background evaluation toolsare also is included inthe head notes of primary and secondary each section with sources listed in each is designed for section's bibliography.The unit four weeks, butcan be adapted to fit classroom needs. (EH) ********************************************************************************
    [Show full text]
  • Unit 13 Civil Disobedience and Satyagraha
    UNIT 13 CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE AND SATYAGRAHA Structure 13.1 Introduction 13.2 Concept of Civil Disobedience 13.3 History of the Concept of Civil Disobedience 13.4 Theory of Civil Disobedience and Existentialist Philosophy 13.5 Gandhian Concept of Civil Disobedience and Satyagraha 13.6 Civil Disobedience in Practice 13.7 Summary 13.8 Exercises 13.1 INTRODUCTION The concept of civil disobedience movement has become an important element in the political power structure in contemporary world. This movement has spread around the world. It has been exemplified by Dr. Martin Luther King, Jr. in the civil rights movement in the United States, the ‘ people’s power’ movement in the Philippines, the non-violent collapse of communism in Eastern Europe and so on. The success of Gandhi and Dr. Martin Luther King, Jr. had a lot to do with the emergence of satyagraha as an organisational power. To discuss about the history of the twentieth century, without exploring the impact of civil disobedience and satyagraha is to malign the very basis of the people’s movement and the study of social science. The Gandhian method of civil disobedience and satyagraha has given a new dimension to the concept of statecraft. While delivering the most prestigious Gandhi Memorial Lecture on “Towards a World without war- Gandhism and the Modern World” on 11 February 1992, Dr. Daisaku Ikeda said, “As we approach the end of this century of unprecedented wars and violence, we seek as our common goal the creation of a world without war. At this critical juncture what can we – must we- learn from this great philosopher – a man whose spiritual legacy could rightly be termed as one of humanity’s priceless treasures, a miracle of the twentieth century.” The basic aim of every political system is to assist in the process of self-actualisation of individuals to fulfil the inner requirements for a continuous moral growth.
    [Show full text]
  • Appalachian Civil Disobedience in Critical Legal Research Modeled Law Reform
    STUMP Mountain Resistance: Appalachian Civil Disobedience in Critical Legal Research Modeled Law Reform Nicholas F. Stump* John Rawls authored the modern seminal work on civil disobedience in A Theory of Justice. Like all Rawlsian political theory, civil disobedience is very much conceived vis-à-vis the liberalism paradigm. Through this restrictive lens, the role of civil disobedience is in communicating injustices to the societal majority and to legal-institutional elites, who thereafter effect intra-systemic change (i.e., based on the pleas of disobedients). This Article, however, rejects the Rawlsian model, instead adopting a critical legal theory-based approach to civil disobedience. The role of civil disobedience via critical thought is not in communicating to the societal majority—but rather in engaging in collective contestation and self-determination. Thus imbued with contemporary critical theory, civil disobedience is re-envisioned as a grassroots sociopolitical end and not as a mere communicative means towards reform. This Article discusses critically informed civil disobedience in the context of the critical legal research movement (“CLR”). Dedicated equally to intra- systemic and systemic reform, CLR is a proceduralist-based school that aims to effect change via radical approaches to legal research and analysis. Core CLR practices are as follows: (1) the deconstruction of the commercial legal research regime, which facilitates the unpacking of unjust doctrine, (2) a newfound practitioner reliance upon critically based theoretical resources for doctrinal reconstruction, and (3) the incorporation of grassroots activists into progressive reform initiatives. As an expansionist project, this Article examines the role of critically informed civil disobedience in this latter practice, demonstrating that transformative doctrinal and systemic change may best be achieved through the egalitarian cultivation of the civil disobedient work * Library Faculty Member, WVU College of Law.
    [Show full text]
  • The Trump Resistance's
    THE TRUMP RESISTANCE’S REPERTOIRE OF CONTENTION The Trump Resistance’s Rep- ertoire of Contention and its Practice of Civil Disobedience (2016-2018) Charlotte Thomas-Hébert Université Paris 1 Panthéon-Sorbonne European Center for Sociology and Political Science (CESSP) France Abstract: The Resistance, formed in opposition to Donald Trump, has seen progressive groups ally in marches and ral- lies all over the United States. Yet one of its most striking fea- tures is that there have been few acts of civil disobedience. Using the tools of social movement studies and political soci- ology as well as ethnographic data, this paper investigates why breaking the law has not been a more popular form of nonvio- lent direct action, and why activists seemed to favor permitted marches at a time when civil disobedience had become if not le- gitimate, at least increasingly accepted as a democratic practice. 1 SOCIETY OF AMERICANISTS REVIEW he election of Barack Obama as well as the Great Reces- sion of 2008 marked a subsequent revival of protest poli- Ttics in the United States, with movements ranging from campaigns for better living wages such as Fight for $15, Black Lives Matter actions against police brutality and institutional racism and strikes in the public sector (Wisconsin in 2011, the Chicago teach- ers’ strike of 2012). Additional protest politics movements include the “Nonviolent Moral Fusion Direct Actions” of the Moral Mon- days in the South in 2013 and Occupy in 2011, that held public space in opposition to “corporate greed” and the financialization of the economy. If these movements have adopted different strategies and repertoires of contention, they have stayed clear of electoral politics and have criticized the legitimacy of the American political system.
    [Show full text]
  • Civil Disobedience Excerpts by Henry David Thoreau
    Civil Disobedience excerpts By Henry David Thoreau 1849 Note: The 20-page essay, Civil Disobedience, is often published in the same book following the 250-page Walden, an interesting juxtaposition of an appreciation of nature with an appreciation of social justice. Many have heard of this essay, but most cannot recall that Henry Thoreau spent his night in jail for refusing to pay taxes in protest of slavery and the Mexican War. --- The government itself, which is only the mode which the people have chosen to execute their will, is equally liable to be abused and perverted before the people can act through it. Witness the present Mexican war, the work of comparatively a few individuals using the standing government as their tool; for, in the outset, the people would not have consented to this measure. The character inherent in the American people has done all that has been accomplished; and it would have done somewhat more, if the government had not sometimes got in its way. But, to speak practically and as a citizen, unlike those who call themselves no- government men, I ask for, not at once no government, but at once a better government. Let every man make known what kind of government would command his respect, and that will be one step toward obtaining it. Can there not be a government in which majorities do not virtually decide right and wrong, but conscience? Must the citizen ever for a moment, or in the least degree, resign his conscience to the legislation? Why has every man a conscience, then? I think that we should be men first, and subjects afterward.
    [Show full text]
  • Civil Disobedience
    Page 1 of 2 Civil Disobedience June 21, 2014 World Focus FRANK SHATZ WILLIAMSBURG In the early 1960s, the United States was engaged in a global struggle for the hearts and minds of newly independent nations, particularly in Africa and Asia, and images of oppression coming out of Birmingham, Ala., caused our nation tremendous embarrassment. In response, on June 11, 1963, President John F. Kennedy delivered a televised civil rights address ± one of the most important speeches of his SUHVLGHQF\´ said Professor Davison Douglas, in an interview with the Gazette. 'RXJODVLVWKHGHDQRI:LOOLDPDQG0DU\¶s Law School and the Arthur B. Hanson professor of law. He is RQHWKHQDWLRQ¶s leading constitutional historians, an eminent scholar of civil rights law, and the author or co-author of seven books. He is not an ivory-tower scholar who perceives things only as they ought to be. He is a realist who analyzes events as they occur. ³,QP\YLHZWKe tipping point in the struggle for civil rights came when powerful groups, such as Congress and the president of the 8QLWHG6WDWHVHPEUDFHG0DUWLQ/XWKHU.LQJ¶s civil right goals, recognizing that progress on FLYLOULJKWVZDVLQWKHQDWLRQDOLQWHUHVW´KHVDLG ³King was able to use civil disobedience to appeal to the interest of certain Americans with the requisite power and influence to help facilitate racial change. This convergence of interest, more than anything else, accounts for his VXFFHVV´ According to a declaration by the Martin Luther King Jr. Center for Nonviolent Social Change, ³Civil disobedience is the active, public, conscientious breach of the law to bring about a change in law or public policy..
    [Show full text]
  • Civil Disobedience, Criminal Justice and the Politics of Conscience
    Socialist Studies: the Journal of the Society for Socialist Studies 6(1) Spring 2010: 224-226 Copyright © 2010 The Author(s) BOOK REVIEW Lovell, Jarret S. 2009. Crimes of Dissent: Civil Disobedience, Criminal Justice and the Politics of Conscience. New York: New York University Press. ISBN 9780814752272. Paperback: 23.00 US. Pages: 272. Reviewed by Jonathan Greene Trent University Crimes of Dissent is a highly engaging examination of contemporary forms and meanings of political activism in the United States. Written from the perspective of the scholar activist, the book is one part promotion of law violating forms of political action – ‘crimes of dissent’ – and one part handbook on civil disobedience. Despite the effectiveness of criminal dissent, ‘it is still common for well-intentioned individuals to “recoil from the very concept of disobedience,” even in the presence of gross injustice, and even when the disobedience in question is passive and nonviolent’ (10). Yet crimes of dissent are a notable part of America’s revolutionary past: today’s Battle in Seattle was yesterday’s Boston Tea Party. It is this past that Lovell seeks to reclaim and the book is a clarion call for Americans to return to their revolutionary roots. In making the democratic and moral case for criminal acts of dissent, Lovell touches upon a number of traditional leftist themes: the stratifying effects of corporate globalization, enhanced class and racial inequality in America, the influence of money in politics, and the role of the corporate media in setting the political agenda. All of these elements upset democratic processes and enhance social injustice.
    [Show full text]
  • The Literature of Civil Disobedience” Response Sheet Section 1 Emerson Introduction: Ralph Waldo Emerson Is a Significant American Essayist, Poet, and Philosopher
    ELA Lesson 3 in the “Save the Trees?” Project Student Name: KEY “The Literature of Civil Disobedience” Response Sheet Section 1 Emerson Introduction: Ralph Waldo Emerson is a significant American essayist, poet, and philosopher. He lived from 1803 to 1882 . Emerson was also an ordained minister (1826), but the death of his first wife contributed to his own philosophical crisis and he resigned from the clergy. Emerson began writing and lecturing on the “ spiritual nature and importance of an individual.” He became friends with other writers of the time period such as Samuel Coleridge, William Wordsworth and of course Henry David Thoreau. This group became known as the American Transcendentalists, writers and philosophers that believe that the individual could discover truth about spirituality and nature through one’s own intuition rather than through a structured religion. Emerson is best known for his essays: “Friendship”, and “Self-Reliance”. His writings are considered an important contribution to American literature and philosophy. Vocabulary: define each term and include the part of speech. suffrage- the right to vote Note: Emerson seems to be using the archaic definition: a vote given in assent to a proposal or in favor of the election of a particular person. capitulate- cease to resist an opponent or an unwelcome demand; surrender. importune- ask (someone) pressingly and persistently for or to do something, to lobby titular- holding or constituting a purely formal position or title without any real authority. ephemeral- lasting for a very short time. arduous- involving or requiring strenuous effort; difficult and tiring. Section 2: “Self-Reliance” ELA Lesson 3 in the “Save the Trees?” Project (pg.
    [Show full text]