SCEPTICISM ABOUT the KNOWLEDGE of OTHER MINDS: a WITTGENSTEINIAN PERSPECTIVE Dr
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Load more
Recommended publications
-
Ryle's Behaviorist View of the Mind
Ryle’s behaviorist view of the mind Jeff Speaks August 31, 2006 1 The dogma of the ghost in the machine . 1 1.1 The problem of mental causation . 1 1.2 The problem of other minds . 2 2 The Cartesian view as a category mistake . 2 3 Ryle’s positive view . 3 1 The dogma of the ghost in the machine Ryle calls the kind of dualist view that we found in Descartes ‘the official doctrine’, and summarizes it like this: “The official doctrine, which hails chiefly from Descartes, is something like this. With the doubtful exceptions of idiots and infants in arms every human being has both a body and a mind. His body and mind are ordinarily harnessed together, but after the death of his body his mind may continue to exist and function. Human bodies are in space and are subject to the mechanical laws which govern all other bodies in space . But minds are not in space, nor are their operations subject to mechanical laws. A person therefore lives through two collateral histories, one consisting of what happens in and to his body, the other consisting of what happens in and to his mind. The events in the first history are events in the physical world, those in the second are events in the mental world.” Now, it is clear that Ryle thinks that this view is not the right one; he says that he will refer to it, ‘with deliberate abusiveness’, as the dogma of the ghost in the machine. What we have to get clear on is why he thinks the Cartesian view is so clearly false. -
What the Problem of Other Minds Really Tells Us About Descartes
What the Problem of Other Minds Really Tells us about Descartes Gideon Manning The College of William and Mary Ever since the first generation Cartesian Gerauld de Cordemoy wrote a self- standing book dedicated to the problem of other minds philosophers have proceeded as though Descartes’ work entails some version of the problem.1 In this paper I evaluate Descartes’ own contribution to creating and answering skepticism about other minds. It is my contention, first, that for most of his working life Descartes did not see the problem as distinct from the problem of the external world. Second, that when he was finally presented with the problem in a late letter from Henry More, Descartes looked not to behavior, but to a body’s origins as a guide to who does and does not have a mind. Specifically, the response Descartes offers to More appeals to a shared “nature,” something which has struck many readers as an ineffectual response, even as a response which begs the question. On the contrary, and this is my third contention, Descartes’ response is a fairly plausible one when read as utilizing the meaning of “nature” as complexio found in Meditation Six.2 Though it may be translated as “complex,” complexio is really a technical Latin term coming from the medical tradition, likely introduced into the lexicon at Salerno in the tenth- or eleventh-century. It means, roughly, a unique composition of elements or qualities distinguishing species (and individual members of a species) from one another. By emphasizing our shared complexio Descartes is telling More that having resolved the problem of the external world we can rely on God’s uniform action in the world to entail joining a mind to members of our species. -
Ryle's Behaviorist View of the Mind
Ryle’s behaviorist view of the mind Jeff Speaks August 28, 2018 1 The dogma of the ghost in the machine . 1 1.1 The problem of mental causation . 1 1.2 The problem of other minds . 2 2 The Cartesian view as a category mistake . 2 3 Ryle’s view of mental states . 3 4 Full-blown behaviorism . 5 1 The dogma of the ghost in the machine Ryle calls the kind of dualist view that we found in Descartes ‘the official doctrine’, and summarizes it like this: “The official doctrine, which hails chiefly from Descartes, is something like this. With the doubtful exceptions of idiots and infants in arms every human being has both a body and a mind. His body and mind are ordinarily harnessed together, but after the death of his body his mind may continue to exist and function. Human bodies are in space and are subject to the mechanical laws which govern all other bodies in space . But minds are not in space, nor are their operations subject to mechanical laws. A person therefore lives through two collateral histories, one consisting of what happens in and to his body, the other consisting of what happens in and to his mind. The events in the first history are events in the physical world, those in the second are events in the mental world.” Now, it is clear that Ryle thinks that this view is not the right one; he says that he will refer to it, ‘with deliberate abusiveness’, as the dogma of the ghost in the machine. -
CHAPTER4: Private Language Argument and the Problem of Other Minds
84 CHAPTER4: Private Language Argument and the Problem of Other Minds The problem of other minds is an age old predicament in the history of philosophy. It existed during the time of Plato and still remains a quandary in philosophical discussions at length. We find in Plato's Theaetetus the question: "Are you quite certain that the several colours .appear to a dog or to any animal whatever as they appear to you? ... Or that anything appears the same to you as to another man?"lls This problem is a kind of other minds dilemma. The problem of other minds is found in Wittgenstein' s philosophy too. As far as Wittgenstein is concerned, the problem arises due to the self- centred perception of knowledge. When one thinks that he can have knowledge of his own psychological states and on that basis he constructs the world from his own private experiences or sense data, problem of other minds take place. This is a major issue which Wittgenstein strikes to resolve. This issue originally came up from the Cartesian Meditations where Descartes takes his own self as the being to doubt, by his method arrives at the conclusion that one has the best possible access to his own private self. Wittgenstein. believes that it is a ns Benjamin Jowett (tr.), Plato's Theaetetus: With Introduction and Analysis (Rockville, Maryland: Serenity Publishers, 2009), p. 102. 85 false idea to construct the world view in this way. His private language argument is related to the problem of other minds in a quite integrated way. -
The Problem of Other Minds: a Yoruba Hermeneutic Deconstruction of the Logical Behaviourist Approach
The Problem of Other Minds: A Yoruba Hermeneutic Deconstruction of the Logical Behaviourist Approach by Babalola Joseph Balogun [email protected] Department of Philosophy Obafemi Awolowo University, Ile-Ife, Nigeria : Abstract Using the hermeneutics of the Yoruba linguistic framework, the paper reconsiders the scepticism about other minds, especially from the logical behaviourist perspectives. As a theory, logical behaviourism equates other minds with the overt movements of other bodies. The paper advances arguments against logical behaviourism, particularly on the ground that it blurred our traditional concept of mind as something different from the body. The paper concludes by proposing a search for an appropriate methodological approach through which the logical behaviourist account could be improved to properly incorporate the role of the mind in the production of physical behaviour of the body. Keywords: Other Minds, Logical Behaviourism, Yoruba, hermeneutics Introduction Our intention in this paper is not to set out a theory of other minds that will explain the theoretical flaws inherent in the existing theories. Rather, it is a demonstration of the inadequacy of one of the earliest theories of other minds, namely, logical behaviourism. Hence, the paper is essentially a critique. This critique is basically aimed at arousing the need for a search for a better theory of other minds that will take into consideration some of the identified shortcomings of the existing theories, especially as they are somewhat reducible to the behaviourist attitude. It should be noted that such exercise is not new, as several contemporary commentators have amply shown. However, the novelty of the present paper derives from the fact that it is the first time an objection to any of the theories of other minds would be attempted using an African language, especially Yoruba language. -
Ryle and the Para-Mechanical
BRYAN BENHAM Ryle and the Para-mechanical WINNER OF mE 1999 LARRY TAYLOR MEMORIAL AWARD The thesis of this paper is the unconventional claim that Gilbert Ryle is not a logical behaviorist. The popular account ofRyle clearly places his work in The Concept ofMind (1949) in the camp oflogical behaviorist.! The object of this paper, however, will be to illustrate how the conventional interpretation of Ryle is misleading. My argument is not an exhaustive account of Ryle, but serves as a starting point for understanding Ryle outside of the behaviorist label that is usually attached to his work. The argument is straightforward. First, it is apparent on any reasonable construal that logical behaviorism is a reductionist project about the mind. The basic claim of logical behaviorism is that statements containing mental vocabulary can be analyzed into statements containing only the vocabulary of physical behavior. Second, any reasonable account ofRyle will show that he is not a reductionist about the mental, in fact he was adamantly anti-reductionist about the mind. Once these two claims are established it follows quite readily that Ryle was not a logical behaviorist. The first premise is uncontroversial. Anyone familiar with logical behaviorism understands that its aim is to show that mental terminology doesn't refer to unobserved phenomena, supposedly in the head of the person described, but rather to the observed physical behaviors or dispositions to behave (Hempel 1999). In fact, in its strict formulation, logical behaviorism claims that mental terminology signifies only these observed behaviors or dispositions to behave. Thus, I will take it as a reasonably established claim that logical behaviorism is reductionist about the mind. -
Philosophy of Mind
Introduction to Philosophy: Philosophy of Mind INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY: PHILOSOPHY OF MIND ERAN ASOULIN, PAUL RICHARD BLUM, TONY CHENG, DANIEL HAAS, JASON NEWMAN, HENRY SHEVLIN, ELLY VINTIADIS, HEATHER SALAZAR (EDITOR), AND CHRISTINA HENDRICKS (SERIES EDITOR) Rebus Community Introduction to Philosophy: Philosophy of Mind by Eran Asoulin, Paul Richard Blum, Tony Cheng, Daniel Haas, Jason Newman, Henry Shevlin, Elly Vintiadis, Heather Salazar (Editor), and Christina Hendricks (Series Editor) is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License, except where otherwise noted. CONTENTS What is an open textbook? vii Christina Hendricks How to access and use the books ix Christina Hendricks Introduction to the Series xi Christina Hendricks Praise for the Book xiv Adriano Palma Acknowledgements xv Heather Salazar and Christina Hendricks Introduction to the Book 1 Heather Salazar 1. Substance Dualism in Descartes 3 Paul Richard Blum 2. Materialism and Behaviorism 10 Heather Salazar 3. Functionalism 19 Jason Newman 4. Property Dualism 26 Elly Vintiadis 5. Qualia and Raw Feels 34 Henry Shevlin 6. Consciousness 41 Tony Cheng 7. Concepts and Content 49 Eran Asoulin 8. Freedom of the Will 58 Daniel Haas About the Contributors 69 Feedback and Suggestions 72 Adoption Form 73 Licensing and Attribution Information 74 Review Statement 76 Accessibility Assessment 77 Version History 79 WHAT IS AN OPEN TEXTBOOK? CHRISTINA HENDRICKS An open textbook is like a commercial textbook, except: (1) it is publicly available online free of charge (and at low-cost in print), and (2) it has an open license that allows others to reuse it, download and revise it, and redistribute it. -
Seeing Souls: Wittgenstein and Cavell on the “Problem of Other Minds”
Seeing Souls: Wittgenstein and Cavell on the “Problem of Other Minds” JÔNADAS TECHIO The human body is the best picture of the human soul. LUDWIG WITTGENSTEIN, Philosophical Investigations […] not to believe there is such a thing as the human soul is not to know what the human body is […] CAVELL, The Claim of Reason Introduction The so-called “Part I” of Philosophical Investigations (PI) contains many claims con- cerning the grammar of psychological predicates, and particularly about the condi- tions for ascribing them to others. The following are some of the most well-known (and also most representative) among such claims: (i) “only of a living human being and what resembles (behaves like) a living human being can one say: it has sensa- tions; it sees; is blind; hears; is deaf; is conscious or unconscious”;1 (ii) “An ‘inner process’ stands in need of outward criteria.”2 The content of these and other kindred remarks has led a great number of readers to ascribe some kind of “externalistic”3 ac- count to the author of the Investigations. !!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!! 1. Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, trans. P. M. S. Hacker and Joachim Schulte (New York: John Wiley & Sons, 2009), §281. 2. Ibid., §580. 3. I mean this in a very broad sense, so as to cover many different attempts of including in the analysis of the content of (presumably “inner”) mental states some features of the subject’s larger. (“external”) environment, such as her behavior, her community’s standards, the constitution of the objects with which she relates, etc. CONVERSATIONS 1 64! Now, “externalism” comes in many flavors. -
The Elusive Origins of Consciousness: a Philosophical Argument for Panpsychism Over Competing Metaphysical Theories of Mind
Trinity College Trinity College Digital Repository Trinity Publications (Newspapers, Yearbooks, The Trinity Papers (2011 - present) Catalogs, etc.) 2019 The Elusive Origins of Consciousness: A Philosophical Argument for Panpsychism over Competing Metaphysical Theories of Mind Tommy Tobias Aahlberg Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalrepository.trincoll.edu/trinitypapers Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Aahlberg, Tommy Tobias, "The Elusive Origins of Consciousness: A Philosophical Argument for Panpsychism over Competing Metaphysical Theories of Mind". The Trinity Papers (2011 - present) (2019). Trinity College Digital Repository, Hartford, CT. https://digitalrepository.trincoll.edu/trinitypapers/79 The Elusive Origins of Consciousness: A Philosophical Argument for Panpsychism over Competing Metaphysical Theories of Mind Tommy Tobias Aahlberg Introduction Underpinning everything that constitutes our perceived reality is consciousness. The fact that there is something that it is like to be us is at the foundation of everything we consequently come to care about in our lives. Every observation, sensation, thought, and emotion is predicated on the phenomenon that there is something that it is like to observe, sense, think, and feel. The awareness and experience of a world is the essential factor that separates our universe from any conceivable zombie universe where nothing is observed, sensed, thought, or felt. Necessarily, we filter every single moment through our consciousness. If consciousness did not exist there would be no groundwork for meaning as it would hold no basis in any conceivable creature’s awareness, and therefore such a universe would be meaningless. Despite, or perhaps due to, its fundamental nature and important implications – consciousness is poorly understood by contemporary science and philosophy alike, at least in the theoretical sense of understanding. -
Mcdowell's Disjunctivism and Other Minds
MCDOWELL’S DISJUNCTIVISM AND OTHER MINDS Anil Gomes Birkbeck College, London Forthcoming, Inquiry [accepted 2010] John McDowell’s original motivation of disjunctivism occurs in the context of a problem regarding other minds. Recent commentators have insisted that McDowell’s disjunctivism should be classed as an epistemological disjunctivism about epistemic warrant, and distinguished from the perceptual disjunctivism of Hinton, Snowdon and others. In this paper I investigate the relation between the problem of other minds and disjunctivism, and raise some questions for this interpretation of McDowell. 1. Introduction In his ‘Criteria, Defeasibility and Knowledge’, John McDowell uses a debate about other minds, as raised in the context of Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations, to motivate a disjunctive claim about those cases where things appear to a subject to be a certain way.1 In the recent focus on disjunctive theories in the philosophy of perception, a number of writers have moved to distance McDowell’s disjunctivism from the perceptual disjunctivism discussed and advocated by such writers as J.M. Hinton, Paul Snowdon and Mike Martin.2 The standard way of effecting such a distancing is by distinguishing McDowell’s ‘epistemological 1 [McDowell 1982], reprinted as [McDowell 1998a]. All references to this edition. 2 [Hinton 1973], [Snowdon 1980-1], [Martin 2002], [Martin 2004]. disjunctivism’ from the ‘metaphysical’ or ‘perceptual disjunctivism’ of Hinton, Snowdon and Martin, and concluding – as Byrne and Logue do – that ‘[McDowell’s] -
Re-Introducing the Concept of Mind
RE-INTRODUCING THE CONCEPT OF MIND IMAGINE somebody whose enthusiasm for metaphysical musings is so matched by ineptitude that when his bank informs him that his account is overdrawn, he manages to convince himself that the mod ern banking system had created a new kind of Cosmic Substance: anti--cash, convertible into minus-pounds-sterling, nego-dollars, vac euros, and so forth. Being a staunch 'realist' about all things, he decides that his bankers have just informed him that they are hold ing, somewhere within their walls, in a container with his name on it, a particular quantity of anti-cash. It's like matter and anti-matter, he thinks, and he supposes that the annihilation that happens when his overdraft of -£200.43 meets his deposit of £300.46 is - shazam! - the explosive generation of£100.03 of ordinary cash (minus a small quan tity extracted by the bank) plus, perhaps, a few stray photons or quarks or gravity waves. He wonders: What kind of containers does the bank use to hold the anti-cash till the regular cash arrives? How are they insulated? Can you store cash and anti-cash in the same box and somehow prevent them from getting in contact? Might there be zombanks that only seemed to store cash and anti-cash? How could we tell? This is a hard problem indeed! What this poor chap needs is a good dose of Gilbert Ryle's 'logical behaviourism,' which is the plain truth about bank balances, however controversial it might be as a theory of the mind. -
Wittgenstein and Embodied Cognition: a Critique of the Language of Thought Amber Sheldon University of San Diego, [email protected]
University of San Diego Digital USD Keck Undergraduate Humanities Research Fellows Humanities Center Spring 2019 Wittgenstein and Embodied Cognition: A Critique of the Language of Thought Amber Sheldon University of San Diego, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digital.sandiego.edu/hc-keck Part of the Other Philosophy Commons, Philosophy of Language Commons, and the Philosophy of Mind Commons Digital USD Citation Sheldon, Amber, "Wittgenstein and Embodied Cognition: A Critique of the Language of Thought" (2019). Keck Undergraduate Humanities Research Fellows. 2. https://digital.sandiego.edu/hc-keck/2 This Working Paper is brought to you for free and open access by the Humanities Center at Digital USD. It has been accepted for inclusion in Keck Undergraduate Humanities Research Fellows by an authorized administrator of Digital USD. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Sheldon Fall 2018 Wittgenstein and Embodied Cognition: A Critique of the Language of Thought Amber Sheldon University of San Diego, 2018 1 Sheldon Fall 2018 Wittgenstein and Embodied Cognition: A Critique of the Language of Thought Amber Sheldon University of San Diego, 2018 Introduction The “computer metaphor” views the content of the mind as being akin to software. Our brains are coded using abstract symbols to represent concepts and semantic rules.1 Such models for understanding the relation between mind and body have been popular among cognitive scientists and philosophers.2 Computational Functionalism views the mind/brain like a computer that works according to a system of symbolic inputs and corresponding outputs. The framework of these computational mental representations is the “language of thought.”3 This symbolic mental language is often analogized with the symbolic “language” of a computer.