How to Train Your Oracle: the Delphi Method and Its Turbulent Youth in Operations Research and the Policy Sciences
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
The Delphi Method: Techniques and Applications from the Foreword by Olaf Helmer
The Delphi Method Techniques and Applications Edited by Harold A. Linstone Portland State University Murray Turoff New Jersey Institute of Technology With a Foreword by Olaf Helmer University of Southern California ©2002 Murray Turoff and Harold A. Linstone I. Introduction I. Introduction HAROLD A. LINSTONE and MURRAY TUROFF General Remarks It is common, in a book of this kind, to begin with a detailed and explicit definition of the subject- the Delphi technique. However, if we were to attempt this, the reader would no doubt encounter at least one contribution to this collection which would violate our definition. There is in addition a philosophical perspective that when something has attained a point at which it is explicitly definable, then progress has stopped; such is the view we hold with respect to Delphi. In 1969 the number of Delphi studies that had been done could be counted in three digits; today, in 1974, the figure may have already reached four digits. The technique and its application are in a period of evolution, both with respect to how it is applied and to what it is applied. It is the objective of this book to expose the richness of what may be viewed as an evolving field of human endeavor. The reader will encounter in these pages many different perspectives on the Delphi method and an exceedingly diverse range of applications. For a technique that can be considered to be in its infancy, it would be presumptuous of us to present Delphi in the cloak of a neatly wrapped package, sitting on the shelf and ready to use, Rather, we have adopted the approach, through our selection of contributions, of exhibiting a number of different objects having the Delphi label and inviting you to sculpt from these examples your own view and assessment of the technique. -
The Berlin School of Logical Empiricism and Its Legacy
Nicholas Rescher July 6, 2006 THE BERLIN SCHOOL OF LOGICAL EMPIRICISM AND ITS LEGACY 1. BACKGROUND What has become generally known as the Berlin School of Logical Empiricism constitutes a philosophical movement that was based in Berlin’s Gesellschaft fuer empirische Philosophie and erected on foundations laid by Albert Einstein. His revolutionary work in physics had a profound impact on philosophers interested in scientific issues, prominent among them Paul Oppenheim and Hans Reichenbach, the founding fathers of the school, who joined in viewing him as their hero among philosopher-scientists. Overall the membership of this school falls into three groups, as per Display 1.1 The founding generation was linked by the circumstance that both Grelling and Reichenbach were collaborators of Oppenheim; the middle generation by the fact that both Hempel and Helmer were students of Reichenbach’s in Berlin; and the younger generation by the fact that all of its members were students and (at least in their early years) disciples either of Reichenbach or of Hempel in the USA. Three stages are thus at issue: an initial phase in Berlin, a transatlantic migration, and a continuation in the U.S.A.—principally in Pittsburgh. 1 Various other people were involved in the Berlin School in a more peripheral way. A detailed account of its early days in Berlin (roughly 1927 to 1933) is given in Dieter Hoffman’s contribution to Dannenberg et. al. 1994, entitled “Zur Geschichte der Berliner Gesellschaft für empirisch/wissenschaftliche Philosophie.” 2 ___________________________________________________ Display 1 THE BERLIN SCHOOL I. THE FOUNDING GENERATION • Paul Oppenheim (1885-1977) • Kurt Grelling (1886-1942) • Hans Reichenbach (1891-1953) • Walter Dubislav (1895-1937) II. -
The American Futures Studies Movement (1965-1975); Its Roots, Motivations, and Influences Kaya Tolon Iowa State University
Iowa State University Capstones, Theses and Graduate Theses and Dissertations Dissertations 2011 The American futures studies movement (1965-1975); its roots, motivations, and influences Kaya Tolon Iowa State University Follow this and additional works at: https://lib.dr.iastate.edu/etd Part of the History Commons Recommended Citation Tolon, Kaya, "The American futures studies movement (1965-1975); its roots, motivations, and influences" (2011). Graduate Theses and Dissertations. 12029. https://lib.dr.iastate.edu/etd/12029 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Iowa State University Capstones, Theses and Dissertations at Iowa State University Digital Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Graduate Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Iowa State University Digital Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The American futures studies movement (1965-1975); its roots, motivations, and influences by Kaya Tolon A dissertation submitted to the graduate faculty in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY Major: History of Technology and Science Program of Study Committee: Amy Bix, Major Professor David B. Wilson James T. Andrews Hamilton Cravens John W. Monroe Iowa State University Ames, Iowa 2011 Copyright © Kaya Tolon, 2011. All rights reserved. ii TABLE OF CONTENTS Abstract iv Introduction 1 Chapter 1. Post-World War Two Beginnings and Cold War Pressures 19 a. Overall Context & Start of the Cold War 21 b. Emergence of Project RAND and its Theoretical Division 28 c. Emergence of Project DELPHI 33 d. Game Theory, Gaming, and Other Futurist Threads from Cold War Strategic Thinking 40 e. -
RAND History Project Interview: Olaf Helmer 6/3/1994
Dr. Olaf Helmer June 3, 1994 TAPE 1 1 SIDE 1 1-3 Family background, graduate education in mathematics and logic, and immigration to the United States. Early acquaintance with John von Neumann. Study under Susan Stebbing. Doctoral thesis related to Bertrand Russell's work. 3-4 Tenure at u.s. universities during Second World War. Early impressions of teaching, and acquaintance with Rudolf carnap, Paul Oppenheim, Albert Einstein. 4-5 Hired by John Williams for Columbia University Princeton statistical Research Group, later recruited by Williams for RAND. 5-6 Initial introduction to RAND: staffing, computers, emphasis on systems analysis. Helmer's new awareness of possible applications of mathematics, and ongoing interest in logic. 6-8 Early climate at RAND conducive to independent thinking and cooperation. Helmer's initial activity at RAND involving logistics of supplying military operations. 8-9 Research recognized by colleagues and clients. 9-10 Early focus by RAND mathematics division on game theory, and Helmer's interest in its practical applications. Influence of von Neumann, role of Lloyd Shapley. Distinction between game theory and gaming. 10-11 Evolving interest in economic and social sciences, on the part of RAND and Helmer. TAPE 1 1 SIDE 2 11-12 RAND incorporates social scientists into its operations. Role of Helmer, John Williams, 1947 conference. Early intellectual intermingling among mathematicians, engineers, social scientists at RAND. 12-13 Importance of developing rules for simulation gaming. Helmer's perspective on value or utility of gaming approaches. 13-16 Development of Delphi method. Project concerning impact of atomic bombing on u.s. -
The Berlin Group and the Society for Scientific Philosophy
The Berlin Group and the Society for Scientific Philosophy In the late 1920s and early 1930s, the philosopher Hans Reichenbach led a group of like- minded colleagues in Berlin that must count as an independent point of origin of the movement of logical empiricism. Like the Vienna Circle with whom they cooperated on numerous occasions, their concern was to develop a philosophy of science adequate to the latest advances in science itself. Differences of philosophical background and interests, however, resulted in putting different accents by justifying scientific knowledge. 1. The Berlin Group: Ideas The Berlin Group of Logical Empiricism—to be distinguished from the Society for Empirical/Scientific Philosophy (see §3)—originated with Hans Reichenbach’s seminars, held from October 1926 at the University of Berlin. In the spring of 1928, Walter Dubislav joined the Group and soon they met in a special colloquium, led by both of them together. After Reichenbach was forced to emigrate to Istanbul in the summer of 1933 and until the spring of 1935, Dubislav ran it alone. The Group was rather small, its core members being Reichenbach, Dubislav, Kurt Grelling, Alexander Herzberg, and occasionally, also Kurt Lewin and Wolfgang Köhler. Carl Gustav Hempel, Olaf Helmer, Martin Strauss, and Valentin Bergmann were among its younger participants. Paul Oppenheim can be seen as its associate member (see §2). In contrast to the Vienna Circle, the Berlin Group considered philosophy to be a sound academic discipline. They devoted themselves to logical and epistemological criticism (analysis) of science and mathematics to determine what we really know. Their task was empirical: to isolate and identify (“herauszuschälen”) the first principles and truths of human knowledge on the basis of the latest results in mathematics and science. -
Carl Hempel: Whose Philosopher?
Chapter 14 Carl Hempel: Whose Philosopher? Nikolay Milkov For most academics, even most philosophers, the individual who best personified logical empiricism in North America was neither Carnap nor Reichenbach, but Carl Hempel. ::: Hempel’s early papers, “Studies in the Logic of Confirmation” (1945) and “Studies in the Logic of Explanation” (1948, with Paul Oppenheim), effectively defined what by 1960 were arguably the two most active areas of research in North American philosophy of science. (Giere 1996, pp. 339–340) 14.1 Michael Friedman’s Thesis Recently, Michael Friedman has claimed that virtually all the seeds of Hempel’s philosophical development trace back to his early encounter with the Vienna Circle (Friedman 2003, 94). Hempel, it is true, spent the fall term of 1929 as a student at the University of Vienna, and, thanks to a letter of recommendation from Hans Reichenbach, he even attended some sessions of the Vienna Circle. This gave the young Hempel the opportunity to witness firsthand what was called in the literature “stage one” of the debate that saw Moritz Schlick and Friedrich Waismann go head- to-head with Otto Neurath and Rudolf Carnap on the “protocol sentences.” As opposed, however, to Friedman’s view of the principal early influences on Hempel, we shall see that those formative influences originated rather with the Berlin Group. The evidenced adduced here against Friedman on this score concentrates on his contention that Hempel’s entire philosophical development, as well as the major themes that were his special concern, were colored by (i) the N. Milkov () Department of Philosophy, University of Paderborn, Paderborn, Germany e-mail: [email protected] N. -
The Correspondence Between Alfred Tarski and Joseph H. Woodger
Journal of Humanistic Mathematics Volume 11 | Issue 2 July 2021 Logic and Biology: The Correspondence Between Alfred Tarski and Joseph H. Woodger Paolo Mancosu UC Berkeley Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.claremont.edu/jhm Part of the Arts and Humanities Commons, and the Mathematics Commons Recommended Citation Mancosu, P. "Logic and Biology: The Correspondence Between Alfred Tarski and Joseph H. Woodger," Journal of Humanistic Mathematics, Volume 11 Issue 2 (July 2021), pages 18-105. DOI: 10.5642/ jhummath.202102.04 . Available at: https://scholarship.claremont.edu/jhm/vol11/iss2/4 ©2021 by the authors. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons License. JHM is an open access bi-annual journal sponsored by the Claremont Center for the Mathematical Sciences and published by the Claremont Colleges Library | ISSN 2159-8118 | http://scholarship.claremont.edu/jhm/ The editorial staff of JHM works hard to make sure the scholarship disseminated in JHM is accurate and upholds professional ethical guidelines. However the views and opinions expressed in each published manuscript belong exclusively to the individual contributor(s). The publisher and the editors do not endorse or accept responsibility for them. See https://scholarship.claremont.edu/jhm/policies.html for more information. Logic and Biology: The Correspondence Between Alfred Tarski and Joseph H. Woodger Paolo Mancosu Department of Philosophy, University of California, Berkeley, USA [email protected] Abstract This article makes available some early letters chronicling the relationship be- tween the biologist Joseph H. Woodger and the logician Alfred Tarski. Using twenty-five unpublished letters from Tarski to Woodger preserved in the Woodger Papers at University College, London, I reconstruct their relationship for the pe- riod 1935–1950. -
THE BERLIN SCHOOL of LOGICAL EMPIRICISM and ITS LEGACY What Has Become Generally Known As the Berlin School of Logical Empiricis
Erkenntnis (2006) 64:281À304 Ó Springer 2006 DOI 10.1007/s10670-005-4311-7 NICOLAS RESCHER THE BERLIN SCHOOL OF LOGICAL EMPIRICISM AND ITS LEGACY ABSTRACT. What has become generally known as the Berlin School of Logical Empiricism constitutes a philosophical movement that was erected on foundations laid by Albert Einstein. His revolutionary work in physics had a profound impact on philosophers interested in scientific issues, prominent among them Paul Oppenheim and Hans Reichenbach, the founding fathers of the school, who joined in viewing him as their hero among philosopherÀscientists. Overall the membership of this school falls into three groups. The founding generation was linked by the circum- stance that both Grelling and Reichenbach were collaborators of Oppenheim; the middle generation by the fact that both Hempel and Helmer were students of Rei- chenbach’s in Berlin; and the younger generation by the fact that all of its members were students and (at least in their early years) disciples either of Reichenbach’s or of Hempel’s in the USA. Three stages are at issue: an initial phase in Berlin, a trans- atlantic migration, and a continuation in the U.S.A.—principally in Pittsburgh. 1. BACKGROUND What has become generally known as the Berlin School of Logical Empiricism constitutes a philosophical movement that was based in Berlin’s Gesellschaft fu¨r empirische Philosophie and erected on foun- dations laid by Albert Einstein. His revolutionary work in physics had a profound impact on philosophers interested in scientific issues, prominent among them Paul Oppenheim and Hans Reichenbach, the founding fathers of the school, who joined in viewing him as their hero among philosopherÀscientists. -
Logical Empiricism (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)
10.10.13 Logical Empiricism (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy) Logical Empiricism First published Mon Apr 4, 2011; substantive revision Mon Sep 19, 2011 Logical empiricism is a philosophic movement rather than a set of doctrines, and it flourished in the 1920s and 30s in several centers in Europe and in the 40s and 50s in the United States. It had several different leaders whose views changed considerably over time. Moreover, these thinkers differed from one another, often sharply. Because logical empiricism is here construed as a movement rather than as doctrine, there is probably no important position that all logical empiricists shared — including, surprisingly enough, empiricism. And while most participants in the movement were empiricists of one form or another, they disagreed on what the best form of empiricism was and on the cognitive status of empiricism. What held the group together was a common concern for scientific methodology and the important role that science could play in reshaping society. Within that scientific methodology the logical empiricists wanted to find a natural and important role for logic and mathematics and to find an understanding of philosophy according to which it was part of the scientific enterprise. The following discussion of logical empiricism is organized under five headings: 1. Mapping the Movement The term ‘logical empiricism’ has no very precise boundaries and still less that distinguishes it from ‘logical positivism’. It is therefore hard to map. ‘Logical empiricism’ is used here to include -
The Berlin Group and the Vienna Circle: Affinities and Divergences
Chapter 1 The Berlin Group and the Vienna Circle: Affinities and Divergences Nikolay Milkov My collaboration with the Vienna Circle does not mean an agreement with the number of naiveties which it conveyed to us from Vienna (and to which I also count Schlick’s Ethics), but that this union is a result of the compulsion of the isolation in which the school philosophy put the exact philosophers.1 1.1 Asymmetry in the History of the Vienna and Berlin Scientific Philosophy The Vienna Circle and the Berlin Group were allied schools of scientific phi- losophy that together strove against what they understood to be a philosophical traditionalism that lost touch with the real world. The term “logical empiricism,” as this scientific philosophy came to be called in the last years,2 can be seen as the philosophy of the two Germanic capitals, Berlin and Vienna. Both cities were at the forefront of the modernity and, prior to the Second World War, leading centers of science and research. The cultural milieu in which the new scientifically oriented philosophy was nurtured departed perceptibly from what had long been the traditional seedbed of Germanophone philosophy, namely the small university town such as a Marburg or a Heidelberg, a Graz or a Jena. 1Reichenbach’s letter to Heinrich Scholz from 13.10.1931 [HR 013-31-06]. 2For criticism of this term see the last paragraphs of Sect. 1.8. N. Milkov () Department of Philosophy, University of Paderborn, Paderborn, Germany e-mail: [email protected] N. Milkov and V. Peckhaus (eds.), The Berlin Group and the Philosophy 3 of Logical Empiricism, Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science 273, DOI 10.1007/978-94-007-5485-0 1, © Springer ScienceCBusiness Media Dordrecht 2013 4 N.